Next Article in Journal
The Prolonged Path of Indigenization: A Study on German Protestant Missionary Ernst Faber’s Chinese Literary Works
Previous Article in Journal
Maternal Practice and the Chuetas of Mallorca: The Inquisitorial Trials of Pedro Onofre Cortés
 
 
Font Type:
Arial Georgia Verdana
Font Size:
Aa Aa Aa
Line Spacing:
Column Width:
Background:
Article

Practices of Tolerance: The Significance of Common Sense in Settings of Dense Coexistence

1
Institute of Protestant Theology and Religious Education, Technische Universität Braunschweig, Bienroder Weg 97, 38106 Braunschweig, Germany
2
Faculty of Humanities and Educational Sciences, Technische Universität Braunschweig, Bienroder Weg 97, 38106 Braunschweig, Germany
*
Author to whom correspondence should be addressed.
Religions 2024, 15(5), 562; https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15050562
Submission received: 30 March 2024 / Revised: 22 April 2024 / Accepted: 26 April 2024 / Published: 30 April 2024
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Religious Ethics in a Conflicted World)

Abstract

:
Deriving from the growing cultural and religious diversity in Germany and the need for educational professionals to be able to deal with heterogeneous groups and communicate to children about how to coexist peacefully with others, this essay focuses on the relationship between common sense and tolerance, particularly in places of inescapable dense coexistence characterised by religious and cultural diversity. Using institutions of preschool and primary education as an example, the extent to which peaceful coexistence and conflict resolution is borne by common sense and supported by practices of tolerance is discussed. Subsequently, the significance of a common-sense approach to practices of tolerance for conceptualising ethical judgement in intercultural and inter-religious education is explored. The article closes with thoughts on the contribution of religious ethics to questions of human coexistence in highly dense and conflict-ridden contexts and briefly addresses aspects of Protestant social ethics.

1. Introduction

Society in Germany is experiencing growing cultural and religious diversity. In 2022, around 26.6 per cent of the population in Germany had a migrant background (Federal Statistical Office 2024).1 As a consequence of living in a heterogeneous society, there is a growing need for skills to coexist peacefully with others. In order to interact and communicate effectively and appropriately, people need to develop intercultural competences fundamentally based on attitudes like respect, openness, curiosity and withholding judgment, as prominently suggested by Deardorff (2006). These competences should already be fostered at an early age: Zakin argues that “the capability to get along with others in a multicultural community is an essential life skill that must be explicitly taught in school” and “that teaching tolerance and social justice is best initiated when children are young” (Zakin 2012, p. 3; see also Stevens and Charles 2005, pp. 17–25). Taking a study conducted by Nathalie Lichy in 2023 into account, this appears even more relevant: Cultural and religious diversity was nominally pronounced in 21 randomly selected nurseries in three major West German cities (Frankfurt, Mannheim, Stuttgart) and one major East German city (Berlin). Six nurseries had a migration percentage of less than 50 per cent, four nurseries had a migration percentage of over 50 and up to 80 per cent and eleven nurseries had a migration percentage of over 80 per cent, with Islam being the predominant religious affiliation (Lichy 2023, p. 133ff). In contrast, there was only a comparatively small number with a migrant background among specialised educational staff (Lichy 2023, p. 137ff). Primary schools in Germany are experiencing growing linguistic, cultural and religious diversity and heterogeneity, similar to nurseries (Kürzinger et al. 2022, pp. 143–52; See also Bohl et al. 2017). Teachers and other educational professionals are nowadays not only tasked with imparting attitudes that help people get along with others but also with developing their own intercultural and inter-religious competences to deal with respective heterogeneity in their classrooms.
Based on these thoughts, triennial development and research into a blended learning course for the inter-religious–intercultural competence development of teacher students in the subject of religion was conducted as part of the “Qualitätsoffensive Lehrerbildung” (Quality development program for teacher education: QLB II), funded by the German Federal Ministry of Education and Research (TU Braunschweig 2023). During this research, we found that the significance of the “sensus communis” within practices of tolerance in potentially conflicting settings is not well elaborated—if at all—in concepts and trainings related to inter-religious and intercultural competence.2 These concepts or trainings feature a wide variety of competences, such as adaptability, flexibility and empathy (Deardorff 2006, pp. 241–66) and the abilities to develop a plurality-sensitive position (Schambeck 2013, p. 174) or to manage inter-religious conflicts (Willems 2011). However, the capacity to embark on practices that constitute the “environment” as a “common world” in which people align with others, namely, their “sensus communis”, widely remains unreflected. Deardorff indeed states that it is “important […] that we renew our efforts in learning how to live together” (Deardorff 2020b, p. 15) and gives examples of perspective-taking, altruism and collective thinking. However, the sensus communis also remains unexplored in her studies. Further literature about intercultural competence even shows examples of common sense not being useful in intercultural communication by citing Carla Vankoughnett, who states that “In a world of cultural differences… there’s no such thing as ‘common sense’” (Lantz-Deaton and Golubeva 2020, p. 61), or by stating that common sense misleads to concede one “logical process” to all cultures (Bennett 1986, p. 190). We therefore focus particularly on the contribution of common sense to the coexistence of people with diverse religious and cultural backgrounds.3 The contours that the notoriously ambivalent (Forst 2008, pp. 14–21)4 and paradoxically charged5 concept of tolerance take on through its reference to common sense in social practices and what this means for religious ethics in a world riddled with conflicts is the subject of this article.
In the following, we will examine the distinction between consensus and common sense (2) and the relationship between common sense and tolerance regarding coexistence in places of inescapable proximity under the conditions of religious, cultural and ideological diversity (3). We are citing institutions of preschool and primary education as examples, where performance expectations do not yet take precedence over learning to live together. We will show the extent to which coexistence here is borne by common sense and supported by practices of tolerance among children and adults and explore the significance of a common-sense approach to practices of tolerance in concepts of intercultural and inter-religious ethics and education (4). The article closes by considering the potential contribution of religious ethics to questions of human coexistence in highly dense and conflict-ridden contexts and briefly addresses aspects of Protestant social ethics (5). Finally, we draw a conclusion (6).

2. On the Distinction between Consensus and Common Sense

Thinking of Rawls’ principles of justice as the basis of well-ordered societies reminds us that “justice is the first virtue of social institutions” (Rawls 1971, p. 3), especially in places of concentrated coexistence that must be determined by principles of fairness—such as Rawls’ principles of freedom, equality and difference (Rawls 1971, p. 42)6—otherwise, conflicts dominate. The concept of a “well-ordered society” is certainly not the first thought in the throng of a nursery’s playground or on a school’s courtyard. Yet, all these children, pupils, parents and educational professionals fill the confined spaces available to them and granted to each other with movements that cannot be consistently standardised or presented in a rule-based manner (Schneider 1996). The interaction contexts at nurseries, schools and other institutions of dense coexistence are only outlined. They are open, undiscovered terrains full of potential conflicts (Schneider 1992, p. 542). Here, peaceful coexistence is not based solely on an explicit consensus on rules of fairness, as if those involved were constantly verifying their actions, but sustained by an interweaving of cognitive performance with sensory performance within well-rehearsed social practices, through which the participants—children and adults alike—jointly fill the available scope of action.
In such practices, people follow rules; they do not just obey them (Schneider 2012, pp. 17–28).7 According to Hubert Dreyfus, the fact that people can find their way in contexts for which they have no or only a few fixed rules and can creatively refer to rules that have been tried and tested in other fields of practice or change these rules is one of the key elements of human intelligence (Dreyfus 1992). People can and must find out how to move sensibly in non-rule-based areas of practice with a mixture of calculation and imagination by using rules and combining them with their spontaneity, with the ability to act without being guided by rules (Schneider 1992, p. 15). They do this by grasping such condensed social spaces as a “common world” with the help of their common sense (Latin: sensus communis)8, as Hannah Arendt pointedly described in her two “Crisis Essays” (Arendt 1968a, 1968b):
“Common sense which the French so suggestively call the ‚good sense’, le bon sens, discloses to us the nature of the world insofar as it is a common world; we owe to it the fact that our strictly private and ‚subjective‘ five senses and their sensory data can adjust themselves to a nonsubjective and ‚objective‘ world which we have in common and share with others.”
Understanding interaction environments as a “common world” is a prerequisite for tolerance. This perspective offers people a multitude of social practices that are unregulated in their use and that need to be consciously perceived, interpreted and forbearingly evaluated. Hence, the know-how that people need in order to move appropriately and peacefully in environments of dense coexistence is not only evolving from rule-based behaviour but also from common sense-based practices.
When coexistence becomes unavoidable, as at nursery or at school, it requires not only a fundamental consensus on fair rules that apply to everyone and that guide action, but also the common sense of those who can move with justice in a common world of shared practices. Whether coexistence succeeds in dense and diverse contexts depends on practices that are based on the “common sense” of each individual, in which the question of tolerance arises differently than in consensus-based interactions.

3. Tolerance between Rejection, Forbearance and Recognition

The fact that tolerance can smack of contempt and devaluation of the tolerated person is the subject of Goethe’s much-quoted criticism of tolerance: “Tolerance should actually only be a temporary attitude: it must lead to recognition. To tolerate means to offend” (Goethe 1981, p. 507).9 In recent decades, social theory has followed this path of critique of “mere” toleration, leading to a “widespread turn from tolerance to recognition“ (Vainio and Visala 2016, p. 554) with the development of various power-critical, identity-sensitive and acceptance-oriented concepts (Mendus 1989).10 This shift from tolerance to recognition can also be observed in contemporary intercultural and inter-religious pedagogy.11 Axel Honneth’s theory of recognition, one of the most elaborate concepts of recognition in social philosophy, understands recognition as a normative criterion for the degree of social freedom that attempts to overcome misrecognition and rejection (Honneth 1995). It allows for a complex inter-relation between liberal concepts of tolerance and communitarian concepts of recognition (Hansteen 2014). Yet, it does not conceptualise the practices of tolerance that allow people to simply get along with others in heterogenous groups without specific demands of recognition or consensus. Nevertheless, these practices are required precisely where coexistence must function permanently without full political, cultural, social or emotional recognition and without occasions for explicit dialogue between religiously and culturally diverse people. As important as the criticism of tolerance and the emphasis on recognition is, it threatens to lose sight of how much freedom and justice the practices of tolerance facilitate in various social contexts that we encounter in everyday life, e.g., at nursery, at school and among work colleagues or relatives.
“Tolerance” is therefore rightly still a component and target perspective of numerous concepts of intercultural and inter-religious learning12, although the current state of research regarding the effects of school lessons or prevention programmes on changing tolerance-related attitudes appears ambiguous (Domínguez et al. 2023; see also Sandoval-Hernández et al. 2018; Ritzer 2010; Beelmann 2018, pp. 9–27). The wide range of assessments and study results depends heavily on the respective concept of tolerance, which remains unclear. In this regard, Rainer Forst’s socio-philosophical analyses of the concept of tolerance point out an inherent ambivalence of the concept of tolerance with an interplay of acceptance and rejection of the other (Forst 2004, 2017a, 2017b) and distinguish the following four concepts of tolerance:
  • The “permission conception”, whereby a more powerful social majority tolerates the deviating values of a minority as long as they do not exceed the limits set by the more powerful group.
  • The “coexistence conception”, in which individuals or groups in power-symmetrical constellations practice tolerance as a modus vivendi in the interest of avoiding conflict.
  • The “respect conception” of tolerance, in which the tolerant parties respect the equal freedom and the equal rights of the other members of a legally constituted community in the sense of formal equality or of qualitative equality sensitive to the form of life.
  • The “esteem conception”, in which certain ideological, cultural and religious differences between the tolerant parties are mutually appreciated as valuable and certain other aspects of the different way of life are rejected.13
In the debates on educational and political ethics—given a unanimous criticism of the “permission conception”—reference is made above all to the “respect conception” and the “coexistence conception” of tolerance, whereby the discourse can characteristically be divided into the following two currents:
  • Liberalist currents prefer the “respect conception”. They may draw primarily on the work of John Rawls, who sees in two fairness principles, namely, the principle of liberty and equality and the principle of difference, an “overarching consensus” as the basis of social integration in the face of pluralism of conflicting doctrines of the good life (Rawls 1993, p. 144f). To elevate these intuitive foundations of well-ordered societies to the rank of a public conception of justice and to further stabilise pluralistic societies, Rawls takes the path of the public use of reason. Thus, the principles of justice and the well-considered judgements of individuals shall be balanced. What applies to coexistence and political tolerance in democratic constitutional states according to Rawls does of course not necessarily apply to the same extent to coexistence in social life contexts with inescapable proximity such as nurseries, schools or specific workplaces. However, a clever modus vivendi and a “prudential tolerance” (Höffe 2000, p. 74) that is more modest in terms of its demands for consensus or recognition often appear to be deficient from the perspective of concepts of tolerance which—like Rawls himself or Jürgen Habermas—emphasise that tolerance relates primarily to consensus (Habermas 2008, pp. 251–70).
  • Communitarian currents refer primarily to the “coexistence conception” of tolerance. As a prominent protagonist of this current, Michael Walzer has developed the concept of tolerance under the premise of a “politics of difference”, whereby tolerance is a modus vivendi of culturally and religiously diversified groups whose interest is not in overarching coexistence, but in self-preservation (Walzer 1997; see also Walzer 2000, pp. 214–30). Walzer thus makes the acceptance of differences the basic category of coexistence. Unlike Charles Taylor, another protagonist of a politics of difference, Walzer turns tolerance from an exception into a rule of social coexistence between groups (Bubner 2000, pp. 45–59). At the interpersonal level, however, the sensorium of the actors involved is not only focused on the perception of differences but also on the perception of similarities and positive aspects of other ways of life in the sense of Forst’s “esteem conception” of tolerance. Walzer’s concept of tolerance faces difficulties in adequately reflecting the multidimensionality of tolerance constellations in the coexistence of people. Without forbearance, living together within heterogeneous groups would not be possible. However, a comprehensive understanding of tolerance includes the aspect of selectively appreciating differences and finding oneself in others.
Thus, while an emphasis on consensus in general principles of coexistence appears to be fundamental to liberalist concepts of tolerance, an emphasis on difference is characteristic of communitarian concepts of tolerance. However, the consensus-oriented concepts of tolerance developed for pluralistic communities are too rich in procedural prerequisites for contexts in which everyday coexistence in social practices is central, while the difference-oriented concepts of tolerance are in danger of normatively fixing identity constructions and stigmatising attributions instead of criticising or deconstructing them (Drerup 2022, pp. 40–57).
Having elaborated that trainings on inter-religious and intercultural competences as well as socio-philosophical concepts of tolerance and of recognition lacks an appropriate reference to common sense as a prerequisite for the possibility of getting along with others in a common world, we now turn explicitly to institutions of preschool and primary education. Will these contexts of the moral and social education of children conceptually reflect this very basic element of practicing tolerance that is needed in adulthood?

4. Practices of Tolerance in Dense Contexts of Cultural and Religious Diversity: The Example of Educational Institutions

In contexts of dense coexistence, tolerance means remaining attentive to other people, e.g., assessing when it is better to leave a person alone; when to keep how much distance; when it is better to practice ignorance to counteract anger; when to overlook insensitivity, some peculiarities or strange behaviour; when to take differences with humour; and when to work towards acceptance, recognition or consensus. Here, social practices are characterised by a rich composition of forbearance that enables peaceful coexistence under conditions of linguistic, social, cultural and religious diversity and heterogeneity. Given the growing diversity in educational institutions in societies that include growing numbers of immigrants, the question of what constitutes living together in justice appears to be of particular relevance (Macleod 2010, pp. 9–21).14
To concretise our considerations, we now turn to the example of preschool and primary education in Germany. Being predominantly oriented towards togetherness, educational work in nurseries and primary schools is fundamentally related to coexistence as its own task. Under conditions of cultural and religious diversity, this task can become particularly acute. In most nurseries and elementary schools in metropolitan areas, children, parents and educational professionals enter a shared world in which proximity, contact and confrontation within socio-culturally and religiously often very heterogeneous groups are an unavoidable part of living together. Provided there are no selective admission requirements, these institutions usually reflect the social composition of their catchment area to a certain extent.
Dealing with diversity and heterogeneity in preschool and primary education is subject to numerous educational research studies including critical discourse on the discriminating effects of such a specific focus (Budde 2015, pp. 19–37) and concepts on teaching tolerance in nurseries (Zakin 2012, pp. 3–13; see also Hawkins 2014, pp. 723–38; Cohen 2006, pp. 201–37), ranging from art-making activities in preschool settings (Zakin 2012, p. 3) to respect-based conceptions of toleration (Macleod 2010), concepts of “embodied tolerance” (Mamlok 2023, pp. 231–46) or trainings on tolerance as a democratic virtue (Drerup 2021, pp. 108–31).
All this research agrees that social practices associated with the dense coexistence of different people require a high degree of tolerance, which not only refers to an explicit consensus on the rules of coexistence, but also builds on a mix of emotional, aesthetic, social and cognitive competences that are acquired through life experiences—starting from an early age which need to be continuously cultivated. However, the question of how and when children develop and apply their sensus communis, understood as the ability to perceive and judge social reality as a shared world, remains unresolved and maybe even unresolvable. There are no conceptual answers to the question of how far the rich variety of skills and competencies which are brought forward in educational concepts or programmes may root in a specific human “sense” and how this “common sense” serves to share a world of social practices with others at all, including practices of direct tolerance in conflictual constellations of coexistence.
Below the high threshold of consensus, i.e., explicit and mutual agreement on rules that apply to everyone and social, legal and emotional recognition, common sense is needed to enable the coexistence of people living together in a common world. In all places of dense coexistence, consensus and recognition are needed, but practices of immediate tolerance are also required from people who have learnt or are learning to use their common sense and get along with others—even with those with whom they disagree and whose beliefs, attitudes and practices they do not consistently recognise or even refuse. This brings tolerance in the sense of practicing forbearance into focus: Tolerance is required “precisely where the behaviour of others seems absurd, goes against the grain or is repugnant to us—and yet we have reason to bear it” (Seel 2012, p. 123). This reason may lie in the realisation that we simply cannot avoid another person in this life context. To enable us to live together in justice, it may sometimes be necessary to simply give space to other people. At the same time, however, it is about looking for common ground in convictions and ways of life.
In dense forms of coexistence, all actors interact with the tools of their common sense, through which commonalities and differences in living together are identified and balanced. The forbearance and acceptance of heterogeneous convictions, idiosyncrasies and practices should not be underestimated in terms of their integrative effect on coexistence in dense and conflict-prone social spheres. However, to ensure that this form of tolerance does not mutate into indifference, it remains bound to the ethical problem of justice and thus to ethical judgement and the associated learning processes. The sensus communis includes not only the agreement with general rules of political coexistence but also a diverse search for common grounds in diversity and a corresponding practice of justice. For ethics, it is significant that coexistence remains linked to the task of discerning how people move meaningfully within their life forms and their corresponding practices to do justice to this reality. Hence, practices of tolerance imply the power of judgement.
Hannah Arendt understood it as a characteristic of human judgement under the sign of common sense that judgement connects us as a mental activity with other judging people, whose points of view the power of judgement incorporates in interaction with their access to the world (Arendt [1970] 1998, p. 91). The contribution of common sense to ethical judgement therefore consists of opening up the world of life as a common world, (Arendt [1954] 1994, pp. 307–27) “Judging is one, if not the most, important activity in which this sharing the world with others come to pass” (Arendt 1968a, p. 221).
Our judgements are based on the perception of the reality that affects us and do not necessarily lead us into a closed subjectivity but open up a shared world of coexistence using common sense (Schauer 2023; see also Weinman 2023). This does not simply exist but becomes real, present and tangible through certain social practices of understanding, discernment and judgement in which the various dimensions of tolerance converge. Common sense thus directs ethical judgement towards a common world shared by people and other entities, whereby viable, sustainable and also new ways of coexistence emerge (Ulrich 2012, pp. 41–59).

5. The Contribution of Religious Ethics to Practices of Tolerance in a Conflicted World

If we follow Hannah Arendt, the ability of human beings to perceive their life with other people as a shared world is indispensable in the ethical sense. It can be realised in every interpersonal encounter whenever common sense guides perception and judgement and opens up the world as a shared one—a world to be constituted and explored through social practices to which tolerance intrinsically belongs in the interplay of its components described above. People are free to view their environment as a shared world and apply social practices such as tolerance, but they may just as well refrain from doing so. Therefore, the crucial question is whether and how institutions of the common life can contribute to constituting and sustaining practices of tolerance and whether religions with their tendency towards intolerance, social exclusion and violence can be considered suitable candidates for this task at all (Assmann 2010; Schmidt-Salomon et al. 2012, pp. 62–65).
In Protestant theology, which we take up as an example of religious attempts to place the idea of tolerance at the heart of religious ethics, this problematic heritage has led to the reformulation of theological key concepts: Faith in a God does not legitimise one’s own truth claims or one’s superiority over people of other faiths, but on the contrary reserves truth for God himself and views others as created equal and subjects of God’s care (Grümme 2017). Religious pedagogics hence orbits around the perception of a shared world of equal creatures who are all dignified by God’s salvific will which they are invited to explore within specific forms and practices of their social lives (Englert 1995, pp. 161–77; Schweitzer and Schwöbel 2007).
Following this theological approach, Protestant social ethics has reflected on social institutions as contexts of interaction which are provided with theological “mandates”. In this way of thinking about specific social contexts as mandates or institutions15, these contexts are understood as places where people may encounter and give way to God’s preserving, creative and transformative will, thereby realising the original meaning of a common, social life.
Political institutions can thus be characterised as places of emancipation from the practices of domination or of violence, economic institutions as places of liberation from abysmal concern and religious institutions as places where the domination of people over other people is refracted and the contours of coexistence in justice become visible.
Understood in this way, institutions structure social reality in such a way that people move within them on the trail of critical, transformative practices and open up new ways of living together in justice. In this religious tradition of thinking about the social, tuning into reality as a common world bears the signature of a double freedom: a freedom from dependence on other people and a freedom to live in a common world. This freedom depends on people realising that (and to what extent) their lives are supported and preserved. The external freedom to coexist depends on the institutional conditions that Rawls describes as a well-ordered society. The inner freedom to do so has prerequisites that people cannot control. One of these conditions is a person’s trust that their life is well protected. On the basis of this trust, people can allow themselves to coexist with others in justice. They may then even turn to others to find out if and how those others can be included in the good gifts that they have received. In the tradition of Protestant ethics, this is referred to as “iustitia passiva”, through which people are called into the “status politicus”, a process of ever-new vocation from concern for one’s own existence into the practices of “iustitia civilis”, living together with others in justice.16
Despite the caution required by the toxic connection between religiosity and intolerance (Augustin et al. 2006; Schockenhoff 2014, pp. 465–75), especially in the context of Protestant ethics and its history (Seiverth 2013, pp. 24–26; Grethlein 2013, pp. 18–23), this way of ethical thinking offers resources that may contribute to fostering practices of tolerance in educational institutions and elsewhere. Its emancipatory drive and emphasis on immediate justice complement Hannah Arendt’s notion of sensus communis as the constituting element of a common life in justice. Religious faith in the “tolerantia Dei”, God’s tolerance with his creation and its creatures, may thus contribute to the social practices through which people tolerate each other.

6. Conclusions

In this article, we focus on the relationship between common sense and tolerance, particularly in places of inescapable dense coexistence characterised by religious and cultural diversity. We argue that in such condensed social spaces, peaceful coexistence is not based solely on an explicit consensus on rules of fairness but is also sustained by an interweaving of cognitive performance with sensory performance within social practices, through which people jointly fill the available scope of action. This ability to move sensibly in non-rule-based areas of practice with a mixture of calculation and imagination by using rules and combining them with spontaneity is guided by common sense (sensus communis). Following Hannah Arendt, we claim that common sense is a fundamental prerequisite for social practices by helping to grasp interaction environments as a common world of shared practices. By revealing the significance of common sense within practices of tolerance, we show that socio-philosophical concepts of tolerance and training on inter-religious and intercultural competence miss the identification of common sense as a prerequisite for the ability of getting along with others. Given the growing cultural and religious diversity in societies that include immigrants and the predominant orientation towards togetherness in institutions of preschool and primary education, we refer to nurseries and elementary schools as examples of the unavoidable dense coexistence of heterogeneous groups. From an early age, people need to learn how to get along with others and how to practice tolerance and social justice. However, the related competencies need to be continuously cultivated throughout adulthood. As Hannah Arendt stated, the ability of human beings to perceive their life with other people as a shared world can be realised in every interpersonal encounter whenever common sense guides ethical judgement and opens up the world as a shared one—a world that is constituted and explored through social practices to which tolerance intrinsically belongs. We therefore argue that ethical judgement directed by common sense needs to be an intrinsic part of training on inter-religious and intercultural competence. With a view on the toxic connection between religiosity and intolerance, we finally ask whether religious ethics may contribute to the development of such competencies. We conclude that Protestant ethical thinking offers resources that may contribute to practices of tolerance among human coexistence in highly dense and conflict-ridden contexts by fostering perceptions of a shared world of equal creatures whose social life is guided by faith in God’s own tolerance.

Author Contributions

Conceptualization, S.H. and A.W.; methodology, S.H.; software, A.W.; validation, S.H. and Alexandra Wolf; formal analysis, S.H. and Alexandra Wolf; investigation, S.H. and A.W.; resources, S.H. and A.W.; data curation, S.H. and A.W.; writing—original draft preparation, S.H.; writing—review and editing, A.W.; visualization, S.H. and A.W; supervision, S.H.; project administration, S.H.; funding acquisition, S.H. All authors have read and agreed to the published version of the manuscript.

Funding

Bundesministerium für Bildung und Forschung (BMBF, Federal Ministry of Education and Research), Berlin, Germany: Qualitätsoffensive Lehrerbildung II (QLB II 2020–2023); Projektschwerpunkt “Interkulturell-interreligiöse Kompetenz” im Teilprojekt Mehr-Sprache2. Projekt - IA-Number: 61260702, Förderkennzeichen (Funding Number): 01JA1909.

Institutional Review Board Statement

This literature study does not require ethical approval according to the DFG’s “Guidelines for Safeguarding Good Scientific Practice” (https://www.dfg.de/resource/blob/173732/4166759430af8dc2256f0fa54e009f03/kodex-gwp-data.pdf).

Informed Consent Statement

Informed consent was obtained from all subjects involved in the original project to which this article is associated.

Data Availability Statement

The publication of further project data is intended.

Conflicts of Interest

The authors declare no conflicts of interest.

Notes

1
In the same year, the religious and ideological distribution in Germany was as follows: around 24.8 per cent were members of the Catholic Church, 22.6 per cent were members of the Protestant church, 3.7 per cent were denominational Muslims, 5.1 per cent belonged to other religious communities and 43.8 per cent of the population were non-denominational (fowid 2023).
2
See researches and models by Bennett (1986), Arasaratnam and Doerfel (2005), Perez et al. (2015), Bennett (2017) and Deardorff (2020a).
3
Aspects of inter-religious and intercultural dialogue are part of our blended-learning concept but are not the focus of this paper. Instead, we will concentrate on settings of high religious diversity that live on practices that facilitate peaceful coexistence rather than explicit dialogue. For more information on activities that foster inter-religious dialogue see Lehmann (2020, pp. 237–54).
4
For the rich diversity of concepts see Forst (2000) and Brown and Forst (2014).
5
See Popper’s formulation of the paradox of tolerance: “Unlimited tolerance must lead to the disappearance of tolerance… We must therefore claim, in the name of tolerance, the right not to tolerate intolerance“ (Popper [1945] 2012, p. 581).
6
For further development of his principles of justice see Rawls (1993).
7
This distinction can be traced back to Ludwig Wittgenstein who insisted that rules neither interpret themselves nor imply the rules for their own application (Wittgenstein 1958). The only way to find out whether one follows a rule correctly is by shared practices (Holtzman and Leich 2014).
8
In the following, we are using the terms “common sense” and “sensus communis” interchangeably.
9
Our translation.
10
See also Taylor (1994) and Galeotti (2002). For an overview on this discussion see Thompson (2006).
11
For the international discourse see Vilà, Freixa and Aneas (Vilà et al. 2020, pp. 255–73), Morgan and Sandage (2016, pp. 129–58), Jackson (2005) and Brown (2000, pp. 257–81). For the German-speaking debate see Auernheimer (2012, p. 20f.) and Diehm (2010, pp. 119–39). Concerning “recognition“ in religious pedagogy see Orth (2011, pp. 84–111).
12
For the international debate see, e.g., Council of Europe (2023), Deardorff (2009) and Leeds-Hurwitz (2013). With regard to the German-speaking debate see the concept of constructive tolerance in religious pedagogics by Adam (1996, pp. 84–96) and the concept of reflexive tolerance by Krimmer (2013). For inter-religious pedagogics see Schweitzer (2014), Englert (1995, pp. 161–77) and Grümme (2017). Regarding the role of tolerance in educational sciences see Drerup (2017, pp. 206–24; 2022, pp. 40–57) and Mikhail (2022, pp. 5–21).
13
For a good overview on his concept see Forst (2007, pp. 215–37; 2013; 2017b).
14
It needs to be noted that the fixation on diversity or otherness is in danger of contributing to exclusion through othering and stigmatisation dynamics (Mecheril et al. 2010).
15
See Dietrich Bonhoeffer’s doctrine of the mandates: “We speak of divine mandates rather than divine orders, because thereby their character as divinely imposed tasks [Auftrag], as opposed to determinate forms of being, becomes clearer.“ (Bonhoeffer 2005, p. 68) For more information on Bonhoeffer see the articles in Ziegler and Mawson (2019). Following this critical path of social thought, please see also Ernst Wolf‘s theological definition of institutions: “Institutionen sind soziale Daseinsstrukturen der geschaffenen Welt als Einladung Gottes zu ordnender und gestaltender Tat in der Freiheit des Glaubensgehorsams gegen sein Gebot“ (Wolf 1988, p. 173).
16
For a classical formulation of this ethics see Luther (1520a; 1520b, pp. 20–38).

References

  1. Adam, Gottfried. 1996. Wahrnehmung des Anderen. Religionspädagogische Perspektiven und Materialien zum interreligiösen Dialog und zu konstruktiver Toleranz. Glaube und Lernen 11: 84–96. [Google Scholar]
  2. Arasaratnam, Lily A., and Marya L. Doerfel. 2005. Intercultural communication competence: Identifying key components from multicultural perspectives. International Journal of Intercultural Relations 29: 137–63. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  3. Arendt, Hannah. 1968a. The Crisis in Culture. In Between Past and Future: Eight Exercises in Political Thought. New York: The Viking Press, pp. 194–222. [Google Scholar]
  4. Arendt, Hannah. 1968b. The Crisis in Education. In Between Past and Future: Eight Exercises in Political Thought. New York: Viking, pp. 170–93. [Google Scholar]
  5. Arendt, Hannah. 1994. Understanding and Politics (The Difficulties of Understanding). In Essays in Understanding 1930–1954: Formation, Exile, and Totalitarianism. Edited by Hannah Arendt and Jerome Kohn. New York and London: Harcourt, Brace & Co., pp. 307–27. First published 1954. [Google Scholar]
  6. Arendt, Hannah. 1998. Über Kants Politische Philosophie. In Das Urteilen: Texte zu Kants Politischer Philosophie. Edited by Hannah Arendt and Ronald Beiner. Translated by Ursula Ludz. München and Zürich: Piper. First published 1970. [Google Scholar]
  7. Assmann, Jan. 2010. The Price of Monotheism. Stanford: Stanford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  8. Auernheimer, Georg. 2012. Einführung in Die Interkulturelle Pädagogik, 7th ed. Darmstadt: wbg Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft. [Google Scholar]
  9. Augustin, Christian, Johannes Wienand, and Christiane Winkler, eds. 2006. Religiöser Pluralismus und Toleranz in Europa. Wiesbaden: vs. Verlag für Sozialwissenschaften. [Google Scholar]
  10. Beelmann, Andreas. 2018. Vorurteilsprävention und Forderung von Toleranz. Konzeption und Wirksamkeit des Präventionsprogramms PARTS. In Toleranz und Radikalisierung in Zeiten sozialer Diversität: Beiträge aus Psychologie und Sozialwissenschaften. Edited by Andreas Beelmann. Schwalbach/Taunus: Wochenschau Verlag, pp. 9–27. [Google Scholar]
  11. Bennett, Milton J. 1986. A Development Approach to Training for Intercultural Sensitivity. International Journal of Intercultural Relations 10: 179–96. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  12. Bennett, Milton J. 2017. Development model of intercultural sensitivity. In International Encyclopedia of Intercultural Communication. Edited by Y. Kim. Hoboken: John Wiley & Sons. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  13. Bohl, Thorsten, Jürgen Budde, and Markus Rieger-Ladich, eds. 2017. Umgang mit Heterogenität in Schule und Unterricht. Grundlagentheoretische Beiträge, empirische Befunde und didaktische Reflexionen. Bad Heilbrunn: Verlag Julius Klinkhardt. [Google Scholar]
  14. Bonhoeffer, Dietrich. 2005. Ethics. DBW 6. Minneapolis: Fortress Press. [Google Scholar]
  15. Brown, Wendy. 2000. Reflexionen über Toleranz im Zeitalter der Identität. In Toleranz: Philosophische Grundlagen und gesellschaftliche Praxis einer umstrittenen Tugend. Edited by Rainer Forst. Frankfurt and New York: Campus Verlag, pp. 257–81. [Google Scholar]
  16. Brown, Wendy, and Rainer Forst. 2014. The Power of Tolerance: A Debate. Edited by Luca Di Blasi and Christoph Holzhey. New York: Columbia University Press. [Google Scholar]
  17. Bubner, Rüdiger. 2000. Zur Dialektik der Toleranz. In Toleranz: Philosophische Grundlagen und gesellschaftliche Praxis einer umstrittenen Tugend. Edited by Rainer Forst. Frankfurt and New York: Campus Verlag, pp. 45–59. [Google Scholar]
  18. Budde, Jürgen. 2015. Heterogenitätsorientierung. In Heterogenitätsforschung: Empirische und theoretische Perspektiven. Edited by Jürgen Budde, Nina Blasse, Andrea Bossen and Georg Rißler. Weinheim: Beltz Juventa, pp. 19–37. [Google Scholar]
  19. Cohen, Jonathan. 2006. Social, emotional, ethical, and academic education: Creating a climate for learning, participation in democracy, and well-being. Harvard Educational Review 76: 201–37. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  20. Council of Europe. 2023. Manual for the Design of a Training Course on Intercultural Competence. Part 1. The Core Principles of the Council of Europe Intercultural Integration Model. Strasbourg: Committee of Experts on Intercultural Integration of Migrants (ADI-INT). Available online: https://rm.coe.int/prems-004823-gbr-2551-part-1-manuel-sur-la-conception-de-formations-a-/1680ac2b15 (accessed on 12 March 2024).
  21. Deardorff, Darla K. 2006. Identification and Assessment of Intercultural Competence as a Student Outcome of Internationalization. Journal of Studies in International Education 10: 241–66. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  22. Deardorff, Darla K. 2020a. Manual for Developing Intercultural Competencies: Story Circles. In Routledge Focus on Environment and Sustainability. Paris: UNESCO. Available online: https://unesdoc.unesco.org/ark:/48223/pf0000370336 (accessed on 12 March 2024).
  23. Deardorff, Darla K. 2020b. (Re)Learning to Live Together in 2020. Journal of International Students 10: 15–18. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  24. Deardorff, Darla K., ed. 2009. The SAGE Handbook of Intercultural Competence. Thousand Oaks: Sage. [Google Scholar]
  25. Diehm, Isabelle. 2010. Anerkennung ist nicht Toleranz. In Anerkennung. Edited by Alfred Schäfer and Christiane Thompson. Paderborn: Schöningh, pp. 119–39. [Google Scholar]
  26. Domínguez, Carolina Quirós, Valeria De Ormaechea Otarola, and Montserrat Freixa Niella. 2023. Intercultural and Interreligious Competences of Youth: A Case Study in a Secondary School in Barcelona. Religions 14: 1380. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  27. Drerup, Johannes. 2017. Erziehung, Pluralismus und die Macht der Toleranz. Zeitschrift für Pädagogik 63: 206–24. [Google Scholar]
  28. Drerup, Johannes. 2021. Education, epistemic virtues, and the power of toleration. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 24: 108–31. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  29. Drerup, Johannes. 2022. Das unverschämte Wir: Identitätspolitik, Toleranz und demokratische Bildung. Vierteljahrsschrift für wissenschaftliche Pädagogik 98: 40–57. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  30. Dreyfus, Hubert L. 1992. What Computers Still Can’t Do: A Critique of Artificial Reason. Cambridge: MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
  31. Englert, Rudolf. 1995. Religiöse Erziehung als Erziehung zur Toleranz. In Mit Anderen leben: Wege zur Toleranz. Edited by Konrad Hilpert and Jürgen Werbick. Düsseldorf: Patmos Verlag, pp. 161–77. [Google Scholar]
  32. Federal Statistical Office. 2024. Mikrozensus—Bevölkerung nach Migrationshintergrund, Endergebnisse 2022. Available online: https://www.destatis.de/DE/Themen/Gesellschaft-Umwelt/Bevoelkerung/Migration-Integration/inhalt.html (accessed on 10 March 2024).
  33. Forschungsgruppe Weltanschauungen in Deutschland (fowid). 2023. Religionszugehörigkeiten 2022. Available online: https://fowid.de/meldung/religionszugehoerigkeiten-2022 (accessed on 12 March 2024).
  34. Forst, Rainer. 2004. Anerkennung und Toleranz. Fiph Journal 3: 1, 3–4. [Google Scholar]
  35. Forst, Rainer. 2007. To Tolerate Means to Insult: Toleration, Recognition and Emancipation. In Recognition and Power: Axel Honneth and the Tradition of Critical Social Theory. Edited by Bert van den Brink and David Owen. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 215–37. [Google Scholar]
  36. Forst, Rainer. 2008. Die Ambivalenz der Toleranz: Vom schwierigen Balanceakt zwischen Gleichheit und Differenz. Forschung Frankfurt Wissenschaftsmagazin der Goethe-Universität 1: 14–21. [Google Scholar]
  37. Forst, Rainer. 2013. Toleration in Conflict: Past and Present. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
  38. Forst, Rainer. 2017a. Toleranz im Konflikt: Geschichte, Gehalt und Gegenwart eines umstrittenen Begriffs, 5th ed. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. [Google Scholar]
  39. Forst, Rainer. 2017b. Toleration. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2017 Edition). Edited by Edward N. Zalta. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2017/entries/toleration/ (accessed on 12 March 2024).
  40. Forst, Rainer, ed. 2000. Toleranz: Philosophische Grundlagen und gesellschaftliche Praxis einer umstrittenen Tugend. Frankfurt am Main: Campus Verlag. [Google Scholar]
  41. Galeotti, Anna E. 2002. Tolerance as Recognition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
  42. Goethe, Johann W. 1981. Maximen und Reflexionen. Werke Bd. 6. Frankfurt am Main: Insel. [Google Scholar]
  43. Grethlein, Christian. 2013. Reformation und Toleranz. Theologische Impulse für die evangelische Erwachsenenbildung. Forum Erwachsenenbildung 1: 18–23. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  44. Grümme, Bernhard. 2017. Heterogenität in der Religionspädagogik: Grundlagen und konkrete Bausteine. Freiburg in Breisgau: Herder. [Google Scholar]
  45. Habermas, Jürgen. 2008. Religious Tolerance as Pacemaker for Cultural Rights. In Between Naturalism and Religion: Philosophical Essays. Translated by Ciaran Cronin. Cambridge: Polity, pp. 251–70. [Google Scholar]
  46. Hansteen, Hans M. 2014. Tolerance and recognition. Fleks Scandinavian Journal of Intercultural Theory and Practice 1. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  47. Hawkins, Karen. 2014. Teaching for social justice, social responsibility and social inclusion: A respectful pedagogy for twenty-first century early childhood education. European Early Childhood Education Research Journal 22: 723–38. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  48. Holtzman, Steven H., and Christopher M. Leich. 2014. Wittgenstein: To Follow a Rule. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
  49. Honneth, Axel. 1995. The Struggle for Recognition. Cambridge: Polity Press. [Google Scholar]
  50. Höffe, Otfried. 2000. Toleranz: Zur politischen Legitimation der Moderne. In Toleranz: Philosophische Grundlagen und gesellschaftliche Praxis einer umstrittenen Tugend. Edited by Rainer Forst. Frankfurt and New York: Campus Veralg, pp. 60–76. [Google Scholar]
  51. Jackson, Robert. 2005. Intercultural Education, Religious Plurality and Teaching for Tolerance: Interpretive and Dialogical Approaches. In Intercultural Education and Religious Plurality. Edited by Robert Jackson and Ursula McKenna. Oslo: Oslo Coalition Occasional Papers, pp. 5–14. [Google Scholar]
  52. Krimmer, Evelyn. 2013. Evangelischer Religionsunterricht und reflektierte Toleranz. Aufgaben und Möglichkeiten religiöser Bildung im Pluralismus. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht. [Google Scholar]
  53. Kürzinger, Anja, Stefanie Schnebel, Stefan Immerfall, Katja Kansteiner, Martina Funk, Katharina Oberdorfer, Susanne Schmid, and Bianca Strohmaier. 2022. Die Gestaltung von Heterogenität in der Primarstufe. Grundlagen und Bedingungen für die Förderung von Grundschulkindern. In Reflexion und Reflexivität im Kontext Grundschule. Perspektiven für Forschung, Lehrer:innenbildung und Praxis. Edited by Eva Gläser, Julia Poschmann, Petra Bücker and Susanne Miller. Bad Heilbrunn: Verlag Julius Klinkhardt, pp. 143–52. [Google Scholar]
  54. Lantz-Deaton, Caprice, and Irina Golubeva. 2020. Intercultural Competence for College and University Students: A Global Guide for Employability and Social Change. Cham: Springer. [Google Scholar]
  55. Leeds-Hurwitz, Wendy. 2013. Intercultural Competences: Conceptual and Operational Framework. Edited by Intersectoral Platform for a Culture of Peace and Non-Violence, Bureau for Strategic Planning. Paris: UNESCO. Available online: https://unesdoc.unesco.org/ark:/48223/pf0000219768 (accessed on 12 March 2024).
  56. Lehmann, Karsten. 2020. Interreligious Dialogue in Context: Towards a Systematic Comparison of IRD-Activities in Europe. Interdisciplinary Journal for Religion and Transformation in Contemporary Society 6: 237–54. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  57. Lichy, Nathalie. 2023. Religiöse und kulturelle Diversität in Kindertageseinrichtungen. Wie kann eine vielfaltssensible Bildung und Erziehung Vorurteilen entgegenwirken? Eine empirisch-qualitative Studie zur vielfaltssensiblen Bildung und Erziehung im Bereich der Elementarpädagogik. Tübingen: Tübingen Library Publishing. [Google Scholar]
  58. Luther, Martin. 1520a. On the Freedom of a Christian. Available online: https://sourcebooks.fordham.edu/mod/luther-freedomchristian.asp (accessed on 12 March 2024).
  59. Luther, Martin. 1520b. Von der Freiheit eines Christenmenschen. WA 7: 20–38. [Google Scholar]
  60. Macleod, Colin. 2010. Toleration, Children and Education. Educational Philosophy and Theory 42: 9–21. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  61. Mamlok, Dan. 2023. The Quest to Cultivate Tolerance Through Education. Studies in Philosophy and Education 42: 231–46. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  62. Mecheril, Paul, Maria do Mar Castro Varela, Inci Dirim, Annita Kalpaka, and Claus Melter. 2010. Migrationspädagogik. Weinheim: Beltz. [Google Scholar]
  63. Mendus, Susan. 1989. Toleration and the Limits of Liberalism. Basingstoke: MacMillan. [Google Scholar]
  64. Mikhail, Thomas. 2022. Toleranz und die Frage nach ihrer Lehrbarkeit. Vierteljahrsschrift für wissenschaftliche Pädagogik 98: 5–21. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  65. Morgan, Jonathan, and Steven J. Sandage. 2016. A Developmental Model of Interreligious Competence: A Conceptual Framework. Archive for the Psychology of Religion 38: 129–58. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  66. Orth, Gottfried. 2011. Toleranz: Anerkennung der einander Fremden und Verschiedenen. Glauben und Lernen 26: 84–111. [Google Scholar]
  67. Perez, Rosemary J., Woojeong Shim, Patricia King, and Marcia B. Magolda. 2015. Refining Kin and Baxter Magolda’s Model of Intercultural Maturity. Journal of College Student Development 56: 759–76. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  68. Popper, Karl. 2012. The Open Society and its Enemies, 7th ed. London: Routledge, p. 581. First published 1945. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  69. Rawls, John. 1971. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
  70. Rawls, John. 1993. Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press. [Google Scholar]
  71. Ritzer, Georg. 2010. Interesse—Wissen—Toleranz—Sinn. Ausgewählte Kompetenzbereiche und deren Vermittlung im Religionsunterricht: Eine Längsschnittstudie. Empirische Theologie Vol. 19. Wien and Berlin: LIT-Verlag. [Google Scholar]
  72. Sandoval-Hernández, Andrés, Maria M. Isac, and Daniela Miranda, eds. 2018. Teaching Tolerance in a Globalized World. Cham: Springer. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  73. Schambeck, Mirjam. 2013. Interreligiöse Kompetenz: Basiswissen für Studium, Ausbildung und Beruf. Göttingen: UTB. [Google Scholar]
  74. Schauer, Alexandra. 2023. Mensch ohne Welt. Eine Soziologie spätmoderner Vergesellschaftung. Berlin: Suhrkamp. [Google Scholar]
  75. Schmidt-Salomon, Michael, Ulrich Riegel, and Hans W. Heymann. 2012. Werte für die Welt von morgen. Brauchen wir dafür Religionsunterricht? Pädagogik 64: 62–65. [Google Scholar]
  76. Schneider, Hans J. 1992. Phantasie und Kalkül. Über die Polarität von Handlung und Struktur in der Sprache. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. [Google Scholar]
  77. Schneider, Hans J. 1996. Wittgensteins Begriff der Grammatik und das Phänomen der Metapher. In Metapher, Kognition, Künstliche Intelligenz. München: Fink, pp. 13–32. [Google Scholar]
  78. Schneider, Hans J. 2012. Was ist eine Regel? In Organisationen Regeln. Die Wirkmacht korporativer Akteure. Edited by Stephan Duschek, Michael Gaitanides, Wenzel Matiaske and Günther Ortmann. Wiesbaden: Springer, pp. 17–28. [Google Scholar]
  79. Schockenhoff, Eberhard. 2014. Glaube und Toleranz—Überlegungen zu ihrem schwierigen Verhältnis’. In Aus Liebe zu Gott—Im Dienst an den Menschen: Spirituelle, pastorale und ökumenische Dimensionen der Moraltheologie. Festschrift für Herbert Schlögel. Edited by Kerstin Schlögl-Flierl and Gunter Prüller-Jagenteufel. Münster: Aschendorff Verlag, pp. 465–75. [Google Scholar]
  80. Schweitzer, Friedrich. 2014. Interreligiöse Bildung. Religiöse Vielfalt als Herausforderung und Chance. Gütersloh: Gütersloher Verlagshaus. [Google Scholar]
  81. Schweitzer, Friedrich, and Christoph Schwöbel. 2007. Religion, Toleranz, Bildung. Neukirchen-Vluyn: Neukirchner Verlag. [Google Scholar]
  82. Seel, Martin. 2012. 111 Tugenden, 111 Laster. Eine Philosophische Revue. Frankfurt am Main: Fischer. [Google Scholar]
  83. Seiverth, Andreas. 2013. Religiöse Toleranz: Reformatorisches Erbe wider Willen. Forum Erwachsenenbildung 1: 24–26. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  84. Stevens, Rebecca, and Jim Charles. 2005. Preparing teachers to teach tolerance. Multicultural Perspectives 7: 17–25. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  85. Taylor, Charles. 1994. The Politics of Recognition. In Multiculturalism. Edited by Amy Gutman. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
  86. Thompson, Simon. 2006. The Political Theory of Recognition: A Critical Introduction. Cambridge: Polity. [Google Scholar]
  87. TU Braunschweig. 2023. TU4Teachers II. Available online: https://www.tu-braunschweig.de/research-institute-of-teacher-education/tu4teachers-2 (accessed on 12 March 2024).
  88. Ulrich, Hans G. 2012. Explorative Ethik. In Urteilen Lernen—Grundlegung und Kontexte ethischer Urteilsbildung. Edited by Ingrid Schoberth. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, pp. 41–59. [Google Scholar]
  89. Vainio, Ollo-Pekka, and Aku Visala. 2016. Tolerance or Recognition? What Can We Expect? Open Theology 2: 553–65. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  90. Vilà, Ruth, Montserrat Freixa Niella, and Assumpta Aneas. 2020. Interreligious and Intercultural Dialogue in Education. Interdisciplinary Journal for Religion and Transformation in Contemporary Society 6: 255–73. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  91. Walzer, Michael. 1997. On Toleration. New Haven: Yale University Press. [Google Scholar]
  92. Walzer, Michael. 2000. Politik der Differenz. Staatsordnung und Toleranz in der multikulturellen Welt. In Toleranz: Philosophische Grundlagen und gesellschaftliche Praxis einer umstrittenen Tugend. Edited by Rainer Forst. Frankfurt and New York: Campus, pp. 214–30. [Google Scholar]
  93. Weinman, Michael. 2023. Hannah Arendt and the Loss of a Common World. Thinking in Concert Against Theory. The Hedgehog Review 25: 20–30. Available online: https://hedgehogreview.com/issues/by-theory-possessed/articles/hannah-arendt-and-the-loss-of-a-common-world (accessed on 12 March 2024).
  94. Willems, Joachim. 2011. Interreligiöse Kompetenz. Theoretische Grundlagen, Konzeptualisierungen, Unterrichtsmethoden. Wiesbaden: Springer. [Google Scholar]
  95. Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1958. Philosophical investigations. New York: Basil Blackwell. [Google Scholar]
  96. Wolf, Ernst. 1988. Sozialethik: Theologische Grundlagen, 3rd ed. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht. [Google Scholar]
  97. Zakin, Andrea. 2012. Hand to Hand: Teaching Tolerance and Social Justice One Child at a Time. Childhood Education 88: 3–13. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  98. Ziegler, Philip G., and Michael Mawson, eds. 2019. The Oxford Handbook of Dietrich Bonhoeffer. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content.

Share and Cite

MDPI and ACS Style

Heuser, S.; Wolf, A. Practices of Tolerance: The Significance of Common Sense in Settings of Dense Coexistence. Religions 2024, 15, 562. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15050562

AMA Style

Heuser S, Wolf A. Practices of Tolerance: The Significance of Common Sense in Settings of Dense Coexistence. Religions. 2024; 15(5):562. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15050562

Chicago/Turabian Style

Heuser, Stefan, and Alexandra Wolf. 2024. "Practices of Tolerance: The Significance of Common Sense in Settings of Dense Coexistence" Religions 15, no. 5: 562. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15050562

Note that from the first issue of 2016, this journal uses article numbers instead of page numbers. See further details here.

Article Metrics

Back to TopTop