Next Article in Journal
The Race for Evolutionary Success
Next Article in Special Issue
Tragedy of the Commons, Business Growth and the Fundamental Sustainability Problem
Previous Article in Journal
The Contribution of Multilateral Nuclear Approaches (MNAs) to the Sustainability of Nuclear Energy
Previous Article in Special Issue
Why is There No Tragedy in These Commons? An Analysis of Forest User Groups and Forest Policy in Bhutan
 
 
Font Type:
Arial Georgia Verdana
Font Size:
Aa Aa Aa
Line Spacing:
Column Width:
Background:
Article

The Tragedy of the Commons from a Game-Theoretic Perspective

by
Florian K. Diekert
1,2
1
Centre for Ecological and Evolutionary Synthesis (CEES), Department of Biology, University of Oslo, Postbox 1066, 0316 Oslo, Norway
2
Department of Economics, University of Oslo, P.O. 1095, 0317 Oslo, Norway
Sustainability 2012, 4(8), 1776-1786; https://doi.org/10.3390/su4081776
Submission received: 25 June 2012 / Revised: 30 July 2012 / Accepted: 3 August 2012 / Published: 13 August 2012
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Tragedy or Transcendence: Reflections on 'The Tragedy of the Commons')

Abstract

:
Twenty years after the declarations from the Earth Summit in Rio, the world faces an unattenuated host of problems that threaten the goal of sustainable development. The challenge to cooperatively solve socio-ecological problems has been portrayed in Garrett Hardin’s essay “The Tragedy of the Commons”. While this paper remains controversial, it has inspired a vast number of theoretical, experimental, and empirical contributions that have clarified the mechanisms of collective action problems and suggested ways to overcome these. This article reviews the recent game-theoretic research in this field.

Graphical Abstract

1. A High-Impact Publication

Hardin’s paper “The Tragedy of the Commons” [1], which is cited more than 18,000 times (google scholar, June 2012), served as a catalyst for research on cooperation in face of collective action problems. Those type of problems are of considerable importance for resource managers in practice as well as it is of great theoretical interest for those that study the evolution of cooperation. Game Theory—the study of rational choice in interactive decision problems—has proved to be a significant tool for both normative and descriptive research on collective action problems. It has first been formally introduced into economics [2]. In its beginning, it has been used for studying strategic aspects during the Cold War and it has later been successfully applied to several scientific fields such as biology [3]. A central aspect that has emerged is that for collective and individual interest to align, coordination is sometimes sufficient, but sometimes genuine cooperation is necessary (see the examples below).
Hardin’s paper has in many ways coined the term for this very common problem where benefits from an action are private but the costs are borne by all. However, an analysis of the problem that Hardin formulated does in fact not yield a “Tragedy of the Commons” as it is conventionally understood in game-theoretic terms. Neither does “freedom in a commons bring ruin to all” [1, p. 1244], at least not necessarily. In the second part of this review, several contributions that highlight how the “tragedy” could be overcome by voluntary, mutually beneficial actions will be presented. Indeed, the tragedy is not inevitable, but the conditions under which the commons can be managed successfully may be demanding. In particular, cooperation may be the more difficult to establish, the higher the stakes. The third part of this review is therefore devoted to a discussion of three recent contributions that have looked at the aversion of dangerous climate change as a global collective action problem.

1.1. Illustrative Examples of a Coordination and a Cooperation Game

Two themes run through this review, namely the issues of coordination and cooperation. Let me introduce these concepts with the help of two examples. Consider first the following situation: There are two actors (players): One who likes to listen to Stravinsky, and another, who likes to listen to Bach. Now picture that both are at work and agree to go a concert (both prefer to go to a concert together rather than alone) but they have not decided where to meet. So, if Player 1 goes to the Bach concert and his partner goes there, too, 1 gets a payoff of 2 and Player 2 gets a payoff of 1. If Player 1 go to the Stravinsky concert and Player 2 goes there too, 1 get a payoff of 1 and 2 gets a payoff of 2. But if Player 1 goes to the Bach concert and Player 2 goes to the Stravinsky concert (or vice versa), both are alone and get a payoff of zero. (See Figure 1 for a tabulation of the payoff-matrix.) So, even though there is a slight conflict of interest, this game is mainly about coordination. For if Player 1 goes to the Bach concert, Player 2 can do no better than going there, too, and if Player 2 goes to the Stravinsky concert 1 cannot gain from not going there as well. In technical terms, the game has two Nash equilibria and the problem consists really only of which one to select.
Figure 1. Bach or Stravinsky: A game of coordination.
Figure 1. Bach or Stravinsky: A game of coordination.
Sustainability 04 01776 g001
This is very different in the second example, the “Prisoner’s dilemma”. The story here is that there are two robbers that have been caught, but the police have no evidence who the main culprit is. If both robbers cooperate and do not talk, the police cannot do anything and both robbers get only a slight punishment. If however one of the robbers defects and speaks to the police and tells the officers that the other one did it while he was merely standing by, the defector will be set free and the other robber will go to jail for a long sentence. If both robbers talk to the police, both will get punished, although they do get some reduction as they have talked to the police. (See Figure 2 for an exemplary tabulation of the payoff-matrix.) The problem is now that, even though it is jointly optimal to hold tight, doing so is not individually rational. Suppose the players have agreed to hold tight, and player 1 does honor the agreement, player 2 can gain from defecting. Since the same reasoning is true for player 1, the only Nash equilibrium in this game is that both robbers talk to the police. In this situation, no player can gain from unilaterally deviating from his strategy.
Figure 2. Prisoner’s dilemma: A game of cooperation.
Figure 2. Prisoner’s dilemma: A game of cooperation.
Sustainability 04 01776 g002

2. Game Theory and Common Property

How do non-cooperative games play out in situations where a good is shared by all? Let me start out by quoting the original passage in Hardin’s article that is the basis of his metaphor. It is a situation where a group of herdsmen put cows on a common pasture:
As a rationale being, each herdsman seeks to maximize his gain. Explicitly or implicitly, more or less consciously, he asks, “what is the utility to me of adding one more animal to my herd?” This utility has a negative and a positive component.
(1) The positive component is a function of the increment of one animal. Since the herdsman receives all the proceeds from the sale of the additional animal, the positive utility is nearly +1.
(2) The negative component is a function of the additional overgrazing created by one more animal. Since, however, the effects of overgrazing are shared by all [...], the negative utility for any particular decision-making herdsman is only a fraction of −1.
Adding together the component particular utilities, the rational herdsman concludes that the only sensible course for him to pursue is to add another animal to his herd. And another; and another... But this is the conclusion reached by each and every rational herdsman sharing a commons. Therein is the tragedy. Each man is locked into a system that compels him to increase his herd without limit—in a world that is limited. Ruin is the destination towards which all men rush, each pursuing his own best interest in a society that believes in the freedom of the commons. Freedom in a commons brings ruin to all. [1, p. 1244]
Partha Dasgupta [4, p. 13] writes about this passage that “it is difficult to locate a passage of comparable length and fame that contains as many errors as the one above.” What should one think of this criticism? To answer this question, consider Figure 3 which captures Hardin’s game in a payoff-matrix: If all players cooperate and have one cow each on the pasture, everybody receives a payoff of 1. (Note that Figure 3 depicts the payoff for any one of all the other players that are presumed to behave identically.) However, player 1 can increase his payoff by putting another cow on the pasture. This player would then receive a payoff of almost two (2 − c, since putting another cow on the pasture causes some costs which are shared by all, including himself). All other players would receive a payoff of slightly less than one. They only carry the cost of the additional animal but derive no benefit from it. Since the situation is the same for all, Hardin says, everyone will defect and the result is a payoff of zero for everyone. Investigating the payoff-matrix, one realizes that everybody defecting is actually not a Nash-equilibrium. Rather it seems that we face a coordination problem (as in the “Bach or Stravinsky” example of Figure 1). But this is obviously not what Hardin had in mind.
Figure 3. An essay to capture Hardin’s game in normal form.
Figure 3. An essay to capture Hardin’s game in normal form.
Sustainability 04 01776 g003
There are several issues with Hardin’s metaphor. First, it is not clear who is “all”. Commonly, “all” is interpreted as “open-access”, meaning that there are no barriers to enter the pasture and that the number of players is in fact indeterminate. Under open access, effort will enter until all rents/profits are dissipated. There are two things to say about this argument: First, common property is not nobody’s property. Quite to the opposite, common property belongs to an often well-defined group of people and in many cases institutions and social norms exist that regulate the harvesting/extraction of the communally owned property, so that it is managed in a more or less sustainable way. Second, if the characterization of open-access is correct, then the individual actor plays such a small part that his actions have only a negligible effect on the other players. In this case, Game Theory plays no role.
Furthermore, Hardin’s metaphor is criticized on the grounds that it contains a dynamic dimension which should be treated explicitly. For example, Brekke et al. [5] discuss how the tragedy might lead to destabilized ecosystems when temporal dynamics are added to the analysis. Moreover, it is not necessarily the case that all rents are dissipated when the numbers of players are fixed and they play a non-cooperative game.
In order to discuss the effect of non-cooperative harvesting, one needs a benchmark of optimal dynamic resource management. Consider therefore the canonical model of renewable resource use [6], which has most often been applied in the context of fisheries:
Sustainability 04 01776 i001
Sustainability 04 01776 i002
Equation (1) says that the objective of a social planner is to maximize the Net-Present-Value from harvesting the resource by choosing the appropriate level of effort E between zero and some maximum effort level Emax. Effort causes cost according to some function c(E) and produces, for a given resource stock S, an amount H of harvest that can be sold at price p. Current profits (the term in the squared brackets) are exponentially discounted at rate r. The stock of the resource is governed by the dynamic Equation (2), where g(S) is the “natural” growth function of the resource. So, when growth is larger than harvest, the stock will increase, and when growth is smaller than harvest, the stock will decline. When re-growth and harvest are equal, the stock will not change over time. The Net-Present-Value is the discounted sum of profits: revenue (the harvest multiplied by its price per unit) minus the cost of effort that is required for harvesting. To keep things very simple it is common to assume that cost and harvest are proportional to effort and that the latter depends on the existing state of the resource according to some function q(S), so that H(S, E) = q(S)E. The Hamiltonian of this problem can then be written as:
Sustainability 04 01776 i006
We can see that it is linear in the control variable E so that whenever the term in the squared brackets is negative, it is best to set effort to zero, and whenever the term in the squared brackets is positive, it is best to set effort to its maximum level (technically, the optimal strategy is of the bang/bang type):
Sustainability 04 01776 i003
In other words, when the initial stock level is low, it is optimal to let the stock grow until it has reached the optimal level and then just take out what is re-growing in equilibrium. In contrast, with a high initial stock size, the stock is “harvested down” to the optimal level as fast as possible.
Turning to a dynamic game, one sees that the problem for player i looks very much like the social planner’s problem, only that the stock development depends on the harvest of all players (Equations 3 and 4). This is of course exactly where the tragedy comes in. The benefits from harvesting are private, but the cost—in terms of a reduced stock size—are borne by all.
Sustainability 04 01776 i004
Sustainability 04 01776 i005
Let me illustrate the outcome of a game with two symmetric players (see, for example [6, ch.5.4], by symmetric I mean that they have the same marginal cost of effort c, apply the same discount rate r, and face the same price p). If the two players now start at a very high stock level and harvest the stock down to the optimal level, can they then agree to keep the stock at the optimal level? The players might agree, but without the possibility to make and enforce a binding agreement, each player has an incentive to deviate: Given that the opponent restrains his harvesting effort, it is in each player’s individual interest to expand effort, benefiting from a high stock size. Since this is true for both players, the stock will be depleted to a level where no player makes any profit. Hence, in this simple model, two symmetric players are sufficient to dissipate all rents. This situation, as depicted in Figure 4b, stands in stark contrast to the optimal management (Figure 4a, where µ is the shadow value of the stock, i.e., the difference between marginal revenue and cost which is attributable to the stock size).
Figure 4. Stock development under optimal and non-cooperative management. (a) Social planner; (b) Two symmetric players.
Figure 4. Stock development under optimal and non-cooperative management. (a) Social planner; (b) Two symmetric players.
Sustainability 04 01776 g004
Now let me turn to a game where the players are asymmetric in the sense that player i is more efficient than player j. That is, the cost of using one additional unit of effort are lower for one player than for the other (in symbols: ci <cj). Suppose the game starts and the players harvest the stock down to a level where the less efficient player makes no more profits. He or she would then leave the fishery. Would the other player then want to deplete the stock further? No, of course not; but player i cannot let the stock increase either because then the less efficient player would want to enter again. So in effect, when the players are asymmetric in this simple game, some rents remain in equilibrium (but less than in the social optimum). The situation is illustrated in Figure 5a, where λ refers to the marginal profit of the most efficient player.
Figure 5. Stock development under non-cooperative management. (a) Two asymmetric players; (b) Three asymmetric players.
Figure 5. Stock development under non-cooperative management. (a) Two asymmetric players; (b) Three asymmetric players.
Sustainability 04 01776 g005
Considering a situation where there are three or more asymmetric players, the stock will be reduced until the first (least efficient) player leaves the fishery. But the two remaining players can also not cooperate on keeping the stock at that level. The situation will be just as before and only the most efficient player will remain in the fishery. He or she obtains some rents, but these are limited by the threat of re-entry of the second-most efficient player. It is plain to see that as the number of players with unique marginal effort cost increases, rents will be dissipated, but all rents will only be dissipated as this number tends to infinity.
To sum up, although Hardin’s simile of the pasture’s problem does not lend itself to a formal model while maintaining the same properties that Hardin claimed, formal dynamic models can be constructed that lead to the total dissipation of rents.

3. Cooperation in the Commons

Among the most prominent scholars who have criticized Hardin’s essay and its dismal implications is the Nobel laureate Elinor Ostrom. She highlights that Hardin’s essay is overly pessimistic and warns that those who blindly advocate formal property rights solutions might do more harm than good. There are many empirical examples of successful community management and introducing formal property rights and other external laws in these regimes might crowd out existing informal arrangements. There is by now also ample evidence from lab-experiments that people are not only rational, narrowly self-interested maximizers. In many lab-games, where self-interest would dictate zero contributions to a public good, many people actually do contribute significant sums. Thus, there are not only “rational maximizers” but also “conditional cooperators” and “willing punishers”. To quote Ostrom [7, p. 138]: “In all known self-organized governance regimes that have survived for multiple generations, participants invest resources in monitoring and sanctioning the actions of each other so as to reduce the probability of free-riding.”
In her work, Ostrom identifies a series of factors that are crucial for success, which can be paraphrased as follows (for an original elaboration see [8]): (1) membership can be controlled; (2) social networks exist; (3) actions are observable; (4) graduated sanctions are feasible; and (5) the resource is not too variable. Here, I will focus on the ability to sanction behavior, i.e., the ability to promote cooperative actions and in particular to punish non-cooperative behavior. Cooperation can be made self-enforcing by threatening defectors with punishment.
To illustrate, imagine that a prisoner’s dilemma game (Section 1.1) would be played many times. Then cooperation could be obtained if the players start out by playing “cooperate” and threat to respond to any defection by retaliating and playing defection forever. A deviator would then have to weigh the current gains from defection against the future losses from playing “defect/defect” instead of “cooperate/cooperate” forever. Clearly, if the players are not too impatient, they would abstain from defecting. This strategy—aptly called “grim trigger”—has one shortcoming: the threat is not credible. As all parents learn very quickly, any threat of punishment has to be credible to be effective. (As an aside, the evolution of cooperation in the context of repeated Prisoner’s Dilemma games is an extensively studied field. The original science paper from Axelrod and Hamilton [9] acquires more than 20,000 citations on google scholar, some 2000 more than “The tragedy of the commons”.) A paper which proposes a credible, renegotiation-proof (a dynamic Nash equilibrium is said to be renegotiation-proof when no player, or group of players, has an incentive to deviate from its path of actions at a later point in time) threat strategy in the dynamic game that was discussed above is from Polasky et al. [10]. The idea is the following (see Figure 6): The players start the game and harvest cooperatively at the socially optimal stock level, equally sharing the ensuing surplus. If now, for some reason, some player defects and grabs all the surplus rents for himself, a two-phase punishment regime is enacted. The players agree on the following procedure: First, the defecting player has to make a loss by harvesting with high effort for some time. The punishment period is so long that the defector loses exactly the same amount that he has previously gained by defecting. After this punishment phase, the resource stock is not harvested so that it recovers and eventually all players return to harvesting cooperatively.
Figure 6. Illustration of two-phase punishment scheme in [10]. (1) cooperation; (2) defection; (3) punishment; (4) cooperation.
Figure 6. Illustration of two-phase punishment scheme in [10]. (1) cooperation; (2) defection; (3) punishment; (4) cooperation.
Sustainability 04 01776 g006
When all players follow this two-phase punishment scheme, no player has an incentive to stray from the path of cooperation, but also note that—and this is important—a deviating player has no incentive to not accept the punishment and all other players have no incentive to not punish. This two-phase punishment strategy ensures cooperation as long as the rents from cooperating are large enough, there are not too many players, and the future is not discounted too heavily.

4. Game Theory, Cooperation, and Climate Change

In many ways, the climate problem is the “tragedy of the commons” in inverse: Here the benefits (avoidance of dangerous climate change) are public but the costs (of abatement) are private. Hence every country has an incentive to free-ride on the abatement effort of the others. As the local commons analyzed in the previous section, the climate problem is essentially a dynamic stock problem. That is, the strategic interactions play out over the level of the stock variable that is shared by all players. However, cooperation in the climate commons is extremely difficult to establish and enforce. It fails on almost all aspects that Ostrom found to be critical for successful management. In particular, the climate system differs from the local commons discussed above, namely, it is a global commons. This implies that the damages from climate change are potentially unbounded, whereas in a local commons the players could always secure themselves a payoff of zero. They could simply leave the fishery, but one cannot leave this planet (at least not today).
In the following, I will discuss three recent papers that deal with different aspects of establishing cooperation in the commons. In the first paper, Heitzig et al. [11] propose a “relative punishment scheme”, which they call linC. This punishment scheme works in the following way: At the beginning the players coordinate on a given target and the shares that each player has to contribute. If some player falls short of his contribution, he has to repay in the next period by taking some share of the other player’s contributions on his shoulder so that the overall contributions stay the same. In the third period, cooperation is re-established and the game continues as before the defection of the player. The authors argue that their proposed strategy can implement any allocation of target contributions in a renegotiation-proof way. However, the model is a “repeated game” where the benefits from reduced emissions are the same every period. In other words, actions of one player have no consequence for the total payoff in the next period.
In contrast, Mason et al. [12] (basically the same authors as in [10]) model a truly dynamic game where the benefits from reduced emissions depend on the stock of pollution which accumulates over time. As in the renewable-resource game, they propose a two-phase scheme with a harsh punishment (which is arbitrarily set at some constant level). This allows for sustainable cooperation, but only in some cases. These cases depend on the parameters in a non-stationary way. For example, cooperation is only self-enforcing when the discount rate is neither too high nor too low.
The last paper I want to mention on this topic is a working paper from Scott Barrett [13]. He analyses, in a static framework, the effect of catastrophes on the ability to establish cooperation in the climate commons. The basic idea is that there is a threshold and a catastrophe happens upon crossing it (think of walking over a cliff). Now when the location of this threshold is known, the static climate game changes its structure fundamentally. Instead of a cooperation problem like in the Prisoner’s Dilemma (Figure 2) one now only has a coordination problem (like in the Bach-or-Stravinsky game, Figure 1). It is clear that if the players want to avoid the catastrophe, they only have to share the burden of doing so. Once the burden sharing agreement is in place, no agent has an incentive to over-emit, as this would cause a discontinuous jump in the damages. In a way, “nature herself enforces the agreement [13, p.1].”
However, when the location of the threshold is uncertain, then coordination is ineffective. Technically speaking, the expected damage function is continuous again. Figuratively speaking, the players are walking towards the edge of a cliff, but it is so foggy that they do not see anything and do not know where exactly to stop. Then each individual has an incentive to just take one more tiny step. We are back again in a situation where cooperation is necessary, but very difficult to enforce.

5. Conclusions

This is clearly an exiting and most important area of research. One approach could be to merge the idea of a relative punishment scheme to enforce cooperation with a more realistic modeling of the climate change situation by means of a dynamic game. Progress towards solving the collective action problems that humanity faces will only be made if both the natural and social aspects of the respective problem are appreciated and understood. A deep understanding in turn is only possible when people with different points of view come together and discuss. It is exactly by raising discussion, by provoking research, and by providing a focal point of consent or dissent that Hardin’s metaphor of the “Tragedy of the Commons” has deeply influenced the way we think about current socio-ecological challenges. One may object to his analysis and his conclusions, but as pointed out in the epigraph to his article, achieving sustainable development still requires, at its root, a change of human relationships with the environment.

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Nils Christian Stenseth for his support and comments on earlier versions of this manuscript. This research is funded by NorMER, a Nordic Centre of Excellence for Research on Marine Ecosystems and Resources under Climate Change.

References

  1. Hardin, G. The tragedy of the commons. Science 1968, 162, 1243–1248. [Google Scholar]
  2. Von Neumann, J.; Morgenstern, O. Theory of Games and Economic Behavior; Wiley: New York, NY, USA, 1944. [Google Scholar]
  3. Maynard Smith, J. Evolution and the Theory of Games; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1982. [Google Scholar]
  4. Dasgupta, P. The Control of Resources; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1982. [Google Scholar]
  5. Brekke, K.A.; Øksendal, B.; Stenseth, N.C. The effect of climate variations on the dynamics of pasture-livestock interactions under cooperative and noncooperative management. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. 2007, 104, 14730–14734. [Google Scholar]
  6. Clark, C.W. Mathematical Bioeconomics: The Optimal Management of Renewable Resources, 2nd ed; Wiley: New York, NY, USA, 1990. [Google Scholar]
  7. Ostrom, E. Collective action and the evolution of social norms. J. Econ. Perspect. 2000, 14, 137–158. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  8. Ostrom, E. A general framework for analyzing sustainability of social-ecological systems. Science 2009, 325, 419–422. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  9. Axelrod, R.; Hamilton, W.D. The evolution of cooperation. Science 1981, 211, 1390–1396. [Google Scholar]
  10. Polasky, S.; Tarui, N.; Ellis, G.; Mason, C. Cooperation in the commons. Econ. Theory 2005, 29, 71–88. [Google Scholar]
  11. Heitzig, J.; Lessmann, K.; Zou, Y. Self-enforcing strategies to deter free-riding in the climate change mitigation game and other repeated public good games. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. 2011, 108, 15739–15744. [Google Scholar]
  12. Mason, C.F.; Polasky, S.; Tarui, N. Cooperation on climate-change mitigation. Unpublished working paper, 2011. [Google Scholar]
  13. Barrett, S. Climate Treaties and Approaching Catastrophes; Columbia University: New York, NY, USA, 2011. [Google Scholar]

Share and Cite

MDPI and ACS Style

Diekert, F.K. The Tragedy of the Commons from a Game-Theoretic Perspective. Sustainability 2012, 4, 1776-1786. https://doi.org/10.3390/su4081776

AMA Style

Diekert FK. The Tragedy of the Commons from a Game-Theoretic Perspective. Sustainability. 2012; 4(8):1776-1786. https://doi.org/10.3390/su4081776

Chicago/Turabian Style

Diekert, Florian K. 2012. "The Tragedy of the Commons from a Game-Theoretic Perspective" Sustainability 4, no. 8: 1776-1786. https://doi.org/10.3390/su4081776

Article Metrics

Back to TopTop