Next Article in Journal
Modeling Inequity Aversion in a Dictator Game with Production
Previous Article in Journal
Quantum Type Indeterminacy in Dynamic Decision-Making: Self-Control through Identity Management
 
 
Font Type:
Arial Georgia Verdana
Font Size:
Aa Aa Aa
Line Spacing:
Column Width:
Background:
Article

Incomplete Information about Social Preferences Explains Equal Division and Delay in Bargaining

Institute for Social Medicine, Epidemiology and Health Economics, Charité University Medical Center, Luisenstrae 57, 10117 Berlin, Germany
Games 2012, 3(3), 119-137; https://doi.org/10.3390/g3030119
Submission received: 30 July 2012 / Revised: 23 August 2012 / Accepted: 27 August 2012 / Published: 13 September 2012

Abstract

:
Two deviations of alternating-offer bargaining behavior from economic theory are observed together, yet have been studied separately. Players who could secure themselves a large surplus share if bargainers were purely self-interested incompletely exploit their advantage. Delay in agreement occurs even if all experimentally controlled information is common knowledge. This paper rationalizes both regularities coherently by modeling heterogeneous social preferences, either self-interest or envy, of one bargaining party as private information in a three period game of bargaining and preference screening and signaling.

1. Introduction

In bargaining situations, the price and terms of a transaction can be disputed by the seller and the buyer of a good or service before an eventual agreement. Thereby, each bargaining party has bargaining power that can shift, for instance, through credibly establishing a not directly observable quality like social preferences. In order to investigate how one of numerous individually rational and Pareto optimal divisions might be agreed, Ståhl [1] and Rubinstein [2] first proposed structural models of alternating-offer bargaining that postulate strategic interaction between two bargainers. The presumed bargaining outcome depends on both bargainers’ preferences and how bargainers capitalize on their relative impatience. For purely self-interested, similarly impatient bargainers and complete information, the equilibrium predicts immediate agreement on a larger share for the bargainer that starts the bargaining. This prediction is in contrast with the practical experience of delay in agreement and divisions more equal than forecast; both of which are well-documented regularities also studied in experiments (e.g., Bolton, Ochs and Roth, Weg et al. [3,4,5]).
This paper shows how equal division or one to two periods of delay occur in the equilibrium of a three period alternating-offer bargaining model with social preferences if a heterogeneity in one bargainer’s preferences is private information. Previous works explained either delay by incomplete information or the bias toward the equal division by social preferences that include a form of interpersonal comparison. Building on the framework of Ståhl, I assume that the first mover, who starts the bargaining and is arbitrarily called the seller, is commonly known to be entirely self-interested whereas the second mover, named the buyer, can be either self-interested or perfectly envious. Ample evidence indicates that at least some people compare themselves to others, which can include aspects of envy (e.g., Camerer, Cooper and Kagel, Smith [6,7,8]). The perfectly envious buyer prefers disagreement to anything less than the equal division. This simplified distributional concern stylizes the response to absolute and relative payoffs that motivates some social preferences. Envy can also be interpreted as loss aversion with respect to a fixed reference point at the equal division. Furthermore, bargaining with perfect envy is strategically equivalent to bargaining with a credible reputation of not accepting less than equal division.
The optimal behavior in the perfect Bayesian equilibrium of a three period alternating-offer bargaining model is either an immediate equal division of the surplus, and its certain acceptance, or gradual reduction of an initially high demand over the course of the game. Latter behavior leads to an occasional acceptance of the high demand by a self-interested buyer or to up to two periods of delay before an agreement on the equal division else. One period of delay is caused by the seller’s desire to discover the buyer’s true type allowing the interpretation of delay as the result of a failed first mover gamble that the second mover is self-interested. Further delay results from the signaling game in which the envious buyer wants to credibly show his type after an initial high demand by the seller. Whether the equilibrium of the three period alternating-offer bargaining model supports pooling or separating the two buyer types depends on their frequency and the bargainers’ impatience to reach agreement. The game only has an equilibrium in pure strategies if the share of self-interested buyers or the bargainers’ impatience remains low enough. As the perfectly envious buyer achieves at least the equal division, his situation is strategically equivalent to bargaining with an outside option of half of the surplus.
The next section reviews related literature. Section 3 presents the model and Section 4 derives the optimal behavior under uncertainty about the buyer preferences. Section 5 discusses the bargaining outcomes, then Section 6 concludes.

2. Related Literature

Informational disparities between bargaining parties are understood as a fundamental reason for delay in agreement. Various models of alternating-offer bargaining (e.g., Chatterjee and Samuelson, Cramton, Grossman and Perry, Gul and Sonnenschein, Rubinstein [9,10,11,12,13,14]) and of one-sided offer bargaining (e.g., Cramton, Fudenberg et al., Sobel and Takahashi [15,16,17]) employ incomplete information about a characteristic of the bargainers to explain delay. Often the first mover is assumed to be uninformed (e.g., Ausubel and Deneckere, Grossman and Perry, Gul and Sonnenschein, Rubinstein, Sobel and Takahashi [12,13,14,17,18]). Valuation of the bargaining good, outside options, the individual cost of bargaining or personal risk attitude, all may be private information and have been studied. Ausubel et al. [19] and Roth [20] provide overviews. In a bargaining setting with asymmetrically informed inequality averse parties, a fully efficient mechanism in the form of a double auction exists only if compassion is strong. Less compassionate parties do not trade in the double auction in the limit of infinitely strong envy [21]. Given one-sided incomplete information in two sequential bargaining experiments, the role of inferences was tested by Srivastava [22] with experimentees who completed questionnaires that measured perceptions of fairness and opponent’s level of competitiveness. Srivastava conjectured that uninformed bargainers infer their opponents’ competitiveness rather than assess and refine a probabilistic assessment of the private information based on the informed bargainer’s behavior. Studying uncertainty about the opponent’s social preferences in an alternating-offer bargaining model supplements these literatures and bridges the theoretical gap between well-understood consequences of incomplete information in bargaining and the research that suggest that some players care about distributional aspects.
Uncertainty about social preferences has already been studied in different contexts. Von Siemens [23] considers investment incentives in a hold-up problem, in which the returns to relationship-specific investments are allocated by bargaining amongst individuals with heterogeneous social preferences that are private information. The investments can signal preferences and, thereby, influence beliefs and bargaining behavior. In consequence, bargainers might choose not to signal unfavorable information. Von Siemens [24] studies employment contracts if workers ability and their social preferences are private information. The paper finds that it is “not possible to screen workers according to their social preferences within the firm” but that “the firm can exclude inequity averse workers with low ability by offering employment contracts that do not compensate any suffering from rent differences in the firm.”
In alternating-offer bargaining, social preferences have been studied in a complete information context. De Bruyn and Bolton [25], Goeree and Holt [26], and Bolton [3] study the influence of distributional concerns and self-interest on finite horizon alternating-offer bargaining behavior. The first group of authors estimates quadratic inequality aversion preferences, introduced by Bolton and Ockenfels [27], for a representative agent based on preexisting data from different bargaining games. They conclude that self-interest and distributional concern “offer better predictions than traditional preference models that ignore fairness considerations.” Goeree and Holt [26] conducted an alternating-offer bargaining experiment in which, independently of the bargaining outcome, role-specific commonly known payments are made to the participants. In their experiment, average offers are biased toward the equal division of the overall income. They argue that a distributional concern is necessary to explain the observed behavior and estimate significant linear inequality aversion preferences as introduced by Fehr and Schmidt [28] based on the experimental data. How guilt or envy affects either party’s bargaining power and, thus, the outcome of open-ended alternating-offer bargaining is shown by Kohler [29,30]. Compassionate bargainers reach agreement in the first period. If guilt is strong, they divide the bargaining surplus equally. If guilt is weak, the bargaining outcome is tilted away from the Rubinstein [2] division towards a more unequal split. Also envious bargainers reach agreement in the first period. Bargaining shares increase in the strength of own envy. Envy can cause divisions more unequal than predicted by Rubinstein, but, if equally patient bargainers exhibit a similar degree of envy, then the bargaining outcome is tilted away from the Rubinstein division towards the equal split. Similarly, envy’s more generic form-loss aversion-may be a disadvantage in bargaining [31]. When comparisons with others cause guilt and envy, the underlying preferences are often called inequality or inequity aversion. Inequality aversion can also increase the asymmetry of the payoff division in bargaining games like legislative bargaining games, in which unanimity is not required [32]. None of these papers consider the influence of incomplete information about social preferences on bargaining.
Bolton’s [3] paper on fairness preferences in bargaining is the most closely related work. He collected data in a large scale bargaining experiment and postulated a formal model, in which bargainers receive utility from two sources. One source is the amount of money earned from agreement while the other is a relative comparison of money earnings incorporated into the utility function as an index. Utility includes this fairness index and is defined such that it combines self-interest with an additional utility gain from obtaining a division closer to the equal division for the bargainer who receives the smaller share. If a player can achieve an advantageous share, then, ceteris paribus, an earlier period agreement is preferred to a later agreement. This comparative model is consistent with five enumerated bargaining regularities. First, offers deviate from the narrow self-interest equilibrium in the direction of the equal division. Second, opening offers are frequently rejected. Third, disadvantageous counteroffers frequently come after rejected first period offers. Fourth, there is a consistent proposer advantage. Fifth, discounting affects the outcome. The comparative model predicts all but delay of agreement under complete information. Bolton emphasized that the “comparative model assumes that subjects have complete information about one another’s utility function. In reality, however, they do not. [...] The marginal rate of substitution between absolute and relative money most likely varies by individual, making utility functions private information.” Evaluating the observed experimental behavior, Bolton developed an intuition how subjects handle the supposable preference uncertainty: “Proposers must search. [...] Searching proceeds roughly as follows. Based on a subject’s prior, he makes an offer. If it is rejected, he makes a more generous offer in the next period.” The following analysis of the optimal behavior under that kind of incomplete information about heterogeneous preferences formally elicits the screening and signaling of preferences within bargaining at the cost of occasional delay of agreement in equilibrium conjectured by Bolton.

3. Model

Within three periods, two players, a seller and a buyer of a good, have to reach agreement on the division of a trade surplus, which is normalized to one, by naming a price pt ∈ [0, 1]. The price pt defines the share of the surplus that the seller receives and 1 − pt is the residual share of the surplus received by the buyer in period t ∈{1, 2, 3}. The surplus results from a potential buyer’s valuation of an object that exceeds the seller’s reservation price. It depreciates with a common discount factor 0 ≤ δ ≤ 1 after any disagreement.
Before the bargaining starts, nature moves by drawing the buyer preferences. By asking a price in periods 1 and 3, the seller proposes a sharing rule for the surplus that the buyer can accept or reject. The game ends once the buyer accepts a price. If the buyer rejects the seller’s price p1 in period 1, then the buyer can propose a new sharing rule p2 in period 2 that the seller can accept or reject. If the seller accepts the buyer’s counteroffer, the bargaining ends. If the buyer rejects the seller’s price in period 3, then the surplus shrinks to zero and the game ends.
The self-interested seller s derives utility from his absolute payoff us(pt) = pt. The buyer b ∈ {c, e}can be one of two types. With probability q ∈ (0, 1) he is self-interested (or competitive) and has utility uc(pt) = 1 - pt. With probability 1 − q he cares about absolute and relative payoffs such that his utility is affected by a loss factor of infinity, interpreted as envy, when receiving less than half of the surplus:
Games 03 00119 i059
The buyer type is private information, but the seller knows the distribution of the preferences in the population and, at any time, holds a belief µt that the other bargaining party is self-interested. The utility of the envious buyer represents an asymmetric limiting case of inequality aversion, put forward by Fehr and Schmidt or Bolton and Ockenfels [27,28], and extensions thereof [33,34] or loss aversion, introduced by Kahneman and Tversky [35], with respect to an equal split. The model of a perfectly envious buyer and a self-interested seller is included in Bolton’s [3] comparative model. Its implied inflexible demands have been studied before in the context of bargaining and reputation (e.g., Abreu and Gul, Myerson [36,37]). By simplifying some distributional social preferences, the model links different literatures and gives a behavioral reinterpretation the previous ad hoc assumption of inflexible demands.
A game with a maximum length of three periods is the shortest game to study different length of delay and in which the seller, who is the first mover, can make one counteroffer. If players share a common discount factor, stronger bargaining power is with the proposing player that also collects at least half of the surplus in open-ended alternating-offer bargaining.

4. Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium

The model is solved for a pure strategy equilibrium. Due to the incomplete information, the solution concept applied is a perfect Bayesian equilibrium (PBE). The PBE is one of two types depending on whether the self-interested seller can distinguish a self-interested from an envious buyer. In a separating equilibrium, the seller can infer the buyer’s private information completely. In a pooling equilibrium, the seller learns nothing about the buyer’s preferences. Whether there is a pooling or separating equilibrium is determined by the probability q of bargaining with a self-interested buyer, which is implied by the frequency of this preference in the population, and the players’ common discount factor δ (Figure 1).
Proposition 1.Let (pt,t) denote the bargaining outcome if a player accepts pt in period t:
(P) If δ ≤ 0.5 and Games 03 00119 i036, if 0.5 < Games 03 00119 i048 and Games 03 00119 i047 or if q ≤ 0.5, then there is a pooling equilibrium. Its outcome is (0.5,1).
(S1) If δ ≤ 0.5 and Games 03 00119 i031, then there is a separating equilibrium. Its outcome is ((1 − δ(1 − δ),1) if the buyer is self-interested. Its outcome is (δ, 2) if the buyer is envious.
(S2) If 0.5 < Games 03 00119 i048 and Games 03 00119 i042, then there is a separating equilibrium. Its outcome is (1 − δ(1 − δ), 1) if the buyer is self-interested. Its outcome is (0.5, 3) if the buyer is envious.
Proof Follows from lemmas 1-3 in the appendix.
Proposition 2.If Games 03 00119 i052 and 0.5 < q < 1, then no PBE in pure strategies exists.
Proof See appendix.
Proposition 3.The PBE in pure strategies is unique if Games 03 00119 i048 or q ≤ 0.5, and if the seller’s belief remains unchanged, i.e ., µt = µt1, whenever Bayesian updating is not possible.
Proof Solving the game by backward induction in lemmas 1-3 given the equilibrium beliefs rules out other equilibria in pure strategies.
Figure 1. Perfect Bayesian equilibrium for q ∈ (0, 1).
Figure 1. Perfect Bayesian equilibrium for q ∈ (0, 1).
Games 03 00119 g001
The strategies and seller beliefs supporting the equilibrium are formally reported in the appendix. Figure 2(a)-2(c) also summarize them, grouped by parameter values, in the game tree of the bargaining problem. The game trees start with the seller decision in period 1, in which he offers to a self-interested buyer with probability q or to an envious one with probability 1 − q. The seller’s respective belief to bargain with a self-interested buyer is denoted in square brackets at his decision nodes. Players’ utility values (rather than payoffs) are denoted in parentheses. The information sets and utilities of minor interest are suppressed. The game is truncated after period 2, but relevant period 3 continuation games are represented below the dotted line. Optimal behavior and the equilibrium outcomes are emphasized. Red lines indicate the paths to the pooling and separating equilibrium outcomes, which are marked with a dotted and dashed border, respectively. Blue lines indicate continuation games that are only reached by mistake (black lines) in equilibrium. The behavior after a division not represented in the game tree equals the behavior illustrated in the continuation game of the incrementally higher seller/lower buyer reservation price depicted in the corresponding period.
Figure 2. (a) Pooling equilibrium. (b) Pooling or separating equilibrium with one period of delay. (c) Pooling or separating equilibrium with two periods of delay.
Figure 2. (a) Pooling equilibrium. (b) Pooling or separating equilibrium with one period of delay. (c) Pooling or separating equilibrium with two periods of delay.
Games 03 00119 g002
Figure 2(a) corresponds to q ≤ 0.5, the lower rectangle in Figure 1, in which the equilibrium outcome is pooling the buyer types through an immediate proposal of the equal division that is instantly accepted by both buyer types. Figure 2(b) corresponds to q > 0.5 and δ ≤ 0.5, the upper left rectangle in Figure 1, in which, depending on the exact parameter values, the equilibrium outcome is either pooling or separating buyer types by risking one period of delay. Figure 2(c) corresponds to q > 0.5 and 0.5 <δ Games 03 00119 i058, the upper middle rectangle in Figure 1, in which, depending on the exact parameter values, the equilibrium outcome is either pooling or separating buyer types by risking two periods of delay. The dashed paths in the period 2 continuation games indicate omitted utility values.

5. Discussion

For a low probability of bargaining with a self-interested buyer q ≤ 0.5 the equilibrium strategies and belief support only a pooling outcome. Due to the low chance to bargain with a self-interested buyer, the expected utility of asking a price higher than half is never more than half. Thus, the seller prefers immediate agreement on the equal surplus division with all buyer types. In contrast, as it becomes more likely for the seller to bargain with a self-interested buyer, the equilibrium strategies and beliefs support either a pooling equilibrium or a separating outcome. If the proportion of self-interested buyers q > 0.5 is sufficiently large in relation to δ < Games 03 00119 i058, the seller maximizes his expected utility by offering such that only a self-interested buyer will accept in period 1. In such a separating strategy, delay results from disagreement and continuation of the bargaining with an envious buyer or an imitating self-interested type. If discounting δ ≤ 0.5 is low, imitation of envy is too costly for the self-interested buyer. He accepts the higher price 1 − δ(1 − δ) in the screening period 1. The envious buyer additionally signals his type by rejecting an unequal p1. His period 2 counteroffer δ will be accepted by the seller. Thereby the envious buyer’s counteroffer is less than half of the pie but the seller prefers the low price to the equal division in the final period due to the low patience. If discounting δ ∈ (0.5, Games 03 00119 i058] is moderate, it costs more time to exclude imitation by a self-interested type and agreement on equal division with an envious buyer follows in period 3 after he signaled his type by rejecting an unequal p1 and offering an unacceptable price p2 in period 2.
The preference between the pooling and separating outcomes depends on the seller’s patience in relation to the probability of bargaining with a self-interested buyer once the probability q > 0.5 is high. If δ Games 03 00119 i058 and q > 0.6, then both separating outcome are preferred to the pooling outcome. Whether separating the buyer types in equilibrium requires one or two periods of delay depends merely on the discount factor δ. As the perfectly envious buyer suffers infinitely from accepting any disadvantageous division, he never imitates self-interested behavior. In contrast, a self-interested buyer gains utility through being offered the equal division if he would pass undetected as an envious type. Therefore, the more patient the players become, the more time must pass between the disadvantageous opening price and the equal division that the seller would like to offer to the different buyers in order to separate buyer types.
If players are more patient, i.e., δ > Games 03 00119 i058, and the buyer is likely to be self-interested, i.e., q > 0.5, then a delay of two periods before dividing equally is no longer sufficient to deter the self-interested buyer from imitating the envious type. Yet, the seller does not maximize utility by offering the equal division to all buyer types for a sufficiently high chance to bargain with self-interested buyer. In an infinite horizon game, the incentive of a self-interested buyer to imitate envy could be eliminated by the seller and the envious buyer through delaying their agreement on the equal division beyond two periods. In the finite horizon game, the scope for delay is limited through the length of the game. Nevertheless, the players can reduce the incentive of the self-interested buyer to imitate the envious type in addition to a physical delay by playing mixed strategies that exclude, at least sometimes, an agreement between the envious buyer and the seller in period 3. Such equilibria are not considered in the paper, but I established that for sufficiently high q and high δ no pure strategy equilibria exist.
The model above postulates an uninformed self-interested seller and assumes perfect envy as the unknown social preferences of some buyers. The dynamics observed in this model, however, applies to a more general context. Suppose a different model of social preferences implied that some buyers accept also other divisions than the equal split while their behavior remains different from a self-interested buyer. Intuitively, when social preferences increase the attractiveness of the outside option to a buyer, then his obtainable share increases and the incentive of a self-interested buyer to imitate social preferences increases too. Therefore, in cases of lower envy, the seller has a lower incentive to separate the buyer types and a self-interested buyer has a reduced interest in imitating. That is, the seller’s incentive increases whereas a self-interested buyer’s incentive decreases the likelihood of observing the pooling equilibrium. For two bargainers with social preferences, Kohler [29,30] studied the impact of commonly known envy or guilt on the bargaining outcome in a model of open-ended alternating-offer bargaining. Even if both bargainers have similar social preferences, the bargaining outcome can differ from the division agreed by self-interested bargainers. The depicted deviations from the bargaining outcome of self-interested bargainers may cause imitating, screening and signaling when there is uncertainty about the opponent’s preferences like in the example of one-sided perfect envy.

6. Conclusion

This paper modeled heterogeneity of social preferences as the source of one-sided incomplete information in an alternating-offer bargaining problem. Assuming that a buyer who moves second is either perfectly envious (that is he rejects any offer less than the equal division of the trade surplus) or self-interested, equal as well as unequal division and occasional occurrence of delay have been rationalized in a perfect Bayesian equilibrium. In the studied three period game, the informed buyer may be screened by the uninformed seller in the first period, in which case the seller demands the larger share of the surplus accepted only by a self-interested buyer. An envious buyer is willing to forgo immediate agreement in order to signal his type. As the cost of learning the buyer type is one or more periods of delay if bargaining is with an envious buyer, the seller may not be interested in screening or receiving a signal. Therefore, two categories of optimal seller behavior exist depending on the players’ patience and the seller’s believed likeliness to encounter a buyer with the respective preferences. Confronted with a low probability to realize a large share against a self-interested buyer, the seller backs off from learning the buyer preferences and instantly offers the equal division, which is always accepted immediately in this pooling equilibrium. As the probability to bargain with a self-interested buyer increases, the risk-neutral expected utility maximizing seller no longer prefers immediate acceptance of all buyer types. If the probability of bargaining with a self-interested buyer is high (or the seller believes it is high), then the seller initially demands a large share and first period rejection by an envious buyer is observed. Through the delay of agreement the envious buyer signals his type. With relatively patient bargainers, a second rejection may be observed as the envious buyer must make an unacceptable counteroffer, after rejecting the seller’s opening offer, to deter the self-interested buyer from worthwhile imitating and to thereby signal his type. Unsettled bargaining goes on and ends with the equal division at latest in period 3 although in both cases the buyer has revealed his envious type by his period 2 offer. If discounting and the probability to bargain with a self-interested buyer are high, the finite game is too short to send a credible signal about the uncertain preferences and no pure strategy equilibrium exists. In addition to divisions more equal than forecast by Rubinstein [2] and delay, the model reproduces further regularities of bargaining behavior not explicitly discussed in the paper: The bargaining outcome, inter alia, depends on the bargainers’ impatience. The payoff distribution on the equilibrium paths uniquely favors the proposing player who demands at least half of the surplus. In a separating equilibrium the seller eventually accepts disadvantageous counteroffers by an envious buyer or asks for less than the equal division himself after he learned the buyer type. As the highly stylized model of social preferences allows for alternative interpretations, relaxing the assumption of perfect envy (or its alternative interpretations) in different directions may help to either further discriminate or to unify competing explanations of bargaining behavior in future research.

Appendix

Definition A perfect Bayesian equilibrium (PBE) is a strategy pair Games 03 00119 i003 and a set of beliefs of the seller that the buyer is self-interested satisfying the following requirements:
  • (E1) The seller’s equilibrium strategy Games 03 00119 i004 maximizes the seller’s discounted expected utility given the buyer’s equilibrium strategy Games 03 00119 i005.
  • (E2) For each buyer type b ∈ {c, e}, the buyer’s equilibrium strategy Games 03 00119 i005 maximizes the buyer’s discounted utility given the seller’s equilibrium strategy Games 03 00119 i004.
  • (E3) The seller belief Games 03 00119 i006 in period t is formed by Bayes’ theorem from the equilibrium strategies at each information set.
Notation Games 03 00119 i007 indicates the utility uit of player i in period t if player j adopts his strategy sj = {sj1,sj2,sj3}, in which the t-th element is substituted by Games 03 00119 i008 given the other player’s equilibrium strategy Games 03 00119 i009. As ∂ubt/∂pt ≤ 0 and ∂uts/∂pt > 0, it is sufficient to look at the maximal/minimal prices at which behavior of the buyer types/seller changes. πH := 1 − δ(1 − δ) denotes the division that corresponds to the backwards induction outcome of a three period bargaining game with a self-interested buyer. πL := 1 − δ(1 − 0.5δ) denotes the division a self-interested buyer just accepts in period 1 if he could obtain the share of an envious buyer in the continuation game.

Proof of Proposition 1

The proof of proposition 1 follows from three lemmas. Lemma 1 establishes the PBE for q ≤ 0.5 (Figure 2(a)), lemma 2 for q > 0.5 and δ ≤ 0.5 (Figure 2(b)) and lemma 3 for q > 0.5 and Games 03 00119 i010 (Figure 2(c)). In each lemma, I show for each player and type that there is no profitable deviation from the equilibrium strategy, emphasized in the figures, given the beliefs at the decision nodes and the equilibrium strategy of the other player. Afterwards, I prove that the assumed beliefs follow from Bayes’ theorem given the equilibrium strategies.
Lemma 1. If q ≤ 0.5, then there is a pooling equilibrium with outcome (0.5,1). The equilibrium is supported by the strategy pair Games 03 00119 i003 and beliefs Games 03 00119 i006 given in Table 1.
Table 1. Strategies and beliefs if q ≤ 0.5.
Table 1. Strategies and beliefs if q ≤ 0.5.
The seller’s equilibrium strategy Games 03 00119 i004 and belief Games 03 00119 i006
t Games 03 00119 i060 Games 03 00119 i006
10.5q
2Y if p2 ≥ 0.5δ else N0 if p1 = πL and p1 = 0.5δ, else q
30.5μ2
The buyer’s equilibrium strategy Games 03 00119 i005
t Games 03 00119 i061 Games 03 00119 i062
1Y if p1πL, else NY if p1 ≤ 0.5, else N
20.5δ0.5δ
3YY if p3 ≤ 0.5, else N
Proof I show that the strategy pair Games 03 00119 i003 and belief Games 03 00119 i006 satisfy the PBE requirements:
  • (E1) In period 3, both buyer types maximize utility by accepting the equal division. Given Games 03 00119 i011 and q ≤ 0.5, the seller maximizes expected utility with Games 03 00119 i012 because us3(ss\0.5) = 0.5 is weakly larger than Games 03 00119 i013. In period 2, the utility of ss2 ∈{Y, N} is us2 = p2 and us2 = 0.5δ, respectively. Hence, Games 03 00119 i014 if p2 ≥ 0.5δ as implied by Games 03 00119 i015. In period 1, the utility of ss1 ∈ {0.5,πL,1} is maximized by Games 03 00119 i016 as us1(ss\0.5) = 0.5, Games 03 00119 i017 if Games 03 00119 i018 and Eus1 (ss\1) = 0.5δ2 ≤ 0.5.
  • (E2) In period 3, the self-interested buyer’s best response Games 03 00119 i019 is to accept any price as, otherwise, the bargaining ends in disagreement with zero payoff. In period 2, the utility of sc2 ∈{0, 0.5δ} is maximized by Games 03 00119 i020 as uc2(sc\0.5δ) = 1 − 0.5δ is larger than uc2(sc\0) = 0.5δ. In period 1, the utility of sc1 ∈ {Y, N} is uc1(sc\Y ) = 1 − p1 and uc1(sc\N) = δ(1 − 0.5δ), respectively. Hence, Games 03 00119 i021 if p1πL as implied by Games 03 00119 i022. In period 3, the envious buyer’s best response Games 03 00119 i023 is to accept any price equal or less than half and to reject otherwise as, afterwards, the bargaining ends with zero payoff to both. In period 2, Games 03 00119 i024 equals Games 03 00119 i025 because payoffs are larger than half and similar for both buyer types in this subgame. In period 1, the utility of se1 ∈ {Y, N} is ue1(se\Y ) = 1 − p1 if p1 ≤ 0.5, else −∞, and ue1(se\N) = δ(1 − 0.5δ), respectively. Hence, Games 03 00119 i027 if p1 ≤ 0.5 as implied by Games 03 00119 i023.
  • (E3) In period 1, the seller’s unconditional belief is the frequency of the self-interested buyer in the population. Both buyer types accept an price p1 ≤ 0.5 and reject p1 ∈ (πL, 1]. In period 2, after rejection of p1 ∉ (0.5,πL] both types make counteroffer p2 = 0.5δ and the seller receives no information, i.e., Games 03 00119 i028. If p1 ∈ (0.5,πL], then only the self-interested buyer accepts and, hence, Games 03 00119 i029. In period 3, the seller moves between information sets and receives no information.
Lemma 2. If Games 03 00119 i030 and δ ≤ 0.5, then there is a pooling equilibrium with outcome (0.5,1). If Games 03 00119 i031 and δ ≤ 0.5, then there is a separating equilibrium. Its outcome is (πH ,1) if bargaining is with a self-interested buyer. Its outcome is (δ,2) if bargaining is with an envious buyer. The equilibrium is supported by the strategy pair Games 03 00119 i003 and beliefs Games 03 00119 i006 given in Table 2.
Table 2. Strategies and beliefs if Games 03 00119 i030 and δ ≤ 0.5.
Table 2. Strategies and beliefs if Games 03 00119 i030 and δ ≤ 0.5.
The seller’s equilibrium strategy Games 03 00119 i004 and belief Games 03 00119 i006
t Games 03 00119 i060 Games 03 00119 i006History
10.5 if Games 03 00119 i030, else πHq-
2Y if p2 ≥ δ, else Nqp1 ∉ (0.5,πH]
Y if p2 ≥ δ, else N0 if p2 = δ, else qp1 ∈ (πL,πH]
Y if p2 ≥ 0.5δ, else N0 if p2 = 0.5δ, else qp1 ∈ (0.5,πL]
31μ2p1 ∉ (0.5,πH]
0.5 if p2 = δ, else 1μ2p1 ∈ (πL,πH]
0.5 if p2 = 0.5δ, else 1μ2p1 ∈ (0.5,πL]
The buyer’s equilibrium strategy Games 03 00119 i005
t Games 03 00119 i061 Games 03 00119 i062History
1Y if p1πH, else NY if p1 ≤ 0.5, else N-
2δδp1 ∉ (0.5,πL]
0.5δ0.5δp1 ∈ (0.5,πL]
3YY if p3 ≤ 0.5, else NAny
Proof I show that the strategy pair Games 03 00119 i003 and belief Games 03 00119 i006 satisfy the PBE requirements:
  • (E1) In period 3, the action of one or both buyer types changes if ss3 ∈ {0.5, 1}. Given Games 03 00119 i011 and q > 0.5, the seller maximizes expected utility Games 03 00119 i032 with Games 03 00119 i033 because us3(ss\0.5) = 0.5 is smaller than Eus3(ss\1) = q if Games 03 00119 i034, i.e., for histories other than p1 ∈ (0.5,πL] and p2 = 0.5δ or p1 ∈ (πL,πH] and p2 = δ. In period 2, the utility of ss2 ∈ {Y, N} is us2 = p2 and Eus2 =0.5δ or Games 03 00119 i035, respectively. Hence, Games 03 00119 i014 if p1 ∈ (0.5,πL] and p2 ≥0.5δ or p1 ∈ (πL,πH] and p2 = δ as implied by Games 03 00119 i015. In period 1, the utility of SS1 ∈ {0.5, πL , πH} is maximized by Games 03 00119 i016 if Games 03 00119 i036 and by Games 03 00119 i037 otherwise as, for Games 03 00119 i038 and q > 0.5, the expected utility Games 03 00119 i017 is weakly smaller than us1(ss\0.5) = 0.5 and Eus1(ss\πH) = H + (1-q)δ2. The comparison of latter implies the threshold.
  • (E2) In period 3, the self-interested buyer’s best response Games 03 00119 i019 is to accept any price as, otherwise, the bargaining ends in disagreement with zero payoff. In period 2, the utility of Sc2 ∈ {0,0.5δ, δ} is maximized by Games 03 00119 i020 if p1 ∈ (0.5,πL] and by Games 03 00119 i039 otherwise as, depending on the history, these prices are the discounted period 3 agreements just accepted by the seller who rejects Sc2 = 0 giving the buyer utility uc2(ss\0) = 0. In period 1, the utility of sc1 ∈ {Y, N} is uc1(ss\Y) = 1 - p1 and uc1(ss\N) = δ(1-0.5δ), respectively. Hence, Games 03 00119 i021 if p1πL as implied by Games 03 00119 i022. In period 3, the envious buyer’s best response Games 03 00119 i023 is to accept any price equal or less than half and to reject otherwise as, afterwards, the bargaining ends with zero payoff to both. In period 2, Games 03 00119 i024 equals Games 03 00119 i025 because payoffs are larger than half and similar for both buyer types in this subgame. In period 1, the utility of se1 ∈ {Y, N} is ue1(se\Y) = 1 - p1 if p1 ≤ 0.5, else −∞, and ue1(se\N) = δ(1-0.5δ), respectively. Hence, Games 03 00119 i027 if p1 ≤ 0.5 as implied by Games 03 00119 i040.
  • (E3) In period 1, the seller’s unconditional belief is the frequency of the self-interest buyer in the population. Both buyer types accept a price p1 ≤ 0.5 and reject p1 ∈ (πH,1]. In period 2, after rejection of p1 ∉ (0.5,πH] both types make the same counteroffer p2 ∈ {0.5δ,δ}and the seller receives no information, i.e., Games 03 00119 i028. If p1 ∈ (0.5,πH],then only the self-interested buyer accepts p1 ∈ (0.5,πH]. Hence, Games 03 00119 i029 if his acceptance is followed by rational action. In period 3, the seller moves between information sets and receives no information.
Lemma 3. If Games 03 00119 i041 and Games 03 00119 i010, then there is a pooling equilibrium with outcome (0.5,1). If Games 03 00119 i042 and Games 03 00119 i010, then there is a separating equilibrium. Its outcome is (πH,1) if bargaining is with a self-interested buyer. Its outcome is (0.5,3) if bargaining is with an envious buyer. The equilibrium is supported by the strategy pair Games 03 00119 i003 and beliefs Games 03 00119 i006 given in Table 3.
Table 3. Strategies and beliefs if Games 03 00119 i041 and Games 03 00119 i010.
Table 3. Strategies and beliefs if Games 03 00119 i041 and Games 03 00119 i010.
The seller’s equilibrium strategy Games 03 00119 i004 and belief Games 03 00119 i006
t Games 03 00119 i060 Games 03 00119 i006History
10.5 if Games 03 00119 i030, else πHq-
2Y if p2δ, else N0 if p2 = 0, 1 if p2 = δ, else qp1 ∉ (0.5,πL]
Y if p2 ≥ 0.5δ, else N0 if p2 = 0.5δ, else qp1 ∈ (0.5,πL]
30.5 if p2 = 0, else 1μ2p1 ∉ (0.5,πL]
0.5 if p2 = 0.5δ, else 1μ2p1 ∈ (0.5,πL]
The buyer’s equilibrium strategy Games 03 00119 i005
t Games 03 00119 i061 Games 03 00119 i062History
1Y if p1πH, else NY if p1 ≤ 0.5, else N-
2δ0p1 ∉ (0.5,πL]
0.5δ0.5δp1 ∈ (0.5,πL]
3YY if p3 ≤ 0.5, else NAny
Proof I show that the strategy pair Games 03 00119 i003 and belief Games 03 00119 i006 satisfy the PBE requirements:
  • (E1) In period 3, the action of one or both buyer types changes if ss3 ∈ {0.5, 1}. Given Games 03 00119 i043 and q > 0.5, the seller maximizes expected utility with Games 03 00119 i033 because us3(ss\0.5) = 0.5 is smaller than Games 03 00119 i044, i.e., for histories other than p1 ∉ (0.5,πL] and p2 = 0 or p1 ∈ (0.5,πL] and p2 =0.5δ. In period 2, the utility of ss2 ∈ {Y, N} is us2 = p2 and Eus2 =0.5δ or Games 03 00119 i035, respectively. Hence, Games 03 00119 i014 if p1 ∈ (0.5,πL] and p2 ≥0.5δ or p1 ∉ (0.5,πL] and p2 = δ as implied by Games 03 00119 i015. In period 1, the utility of SS1 ∈ {0.5, πL , πH} is maximized by Games 03 00119 i016 if Games 03 00119 i047 and by Games 03 00119 i037 otherwise as, for Games 03 00119 i038 and q > 0.5, the expected utility Games 03 00119 i017 is weakly smaller than us1(ss\0.5) = 0.5 and Eus1(ss\πH) = H +0.5δ2 (1-q). The comparison of latter implies the threshold.
  • (E2) In period 3, the self-interested buyer’s best response Games 03 00119 i019 is to accept any price as, otherwise, the bargaining ends in disagreement with zero payoff. In period 2, for Games 03 00119 i048, the utility of Sc2 ∈ {0,0.5δ,δ} is maximized by Games 03 00119 i020 if p1 ∈ (0.5,πL] and by Games 03 00119 i039 otherwise as, depending on the history, these prices are the discounted period 3 agreements just accepted by the seller who rejects Sc2 = 0 giving the buyer utility uc2(ss\0) = 0.5δ. In period 1, the utility of sc1 ∈ {Y, N} is uc1(ss\Y) = 1-p1 and uc1(ss\N) = δ(1-δ), respectively. Hence, Games 03 00119 i021 if p1πH as implied by Games 03 00119 i022. In period 3, the envious buyer’s best response Games 03 00119 i023 is to accept any price equal or less than half and to reject otherwise as, afterwards, the bargaining ends with zero payoff to both. In period 2, the envious buyer utility of asking an acceptable price p2 may be lower than the utility he gets from a rejection if he can thereby signal his type. The utility of Se2 ∈ {0,0.5δ, δ} is maximized by Games 03 00119 i049 if p1 ∈ (0.5,πL] and by Games 03 00119 i050 otherwise because, depending on the history, ue2(ss\0.5δ) = 1-0.5δ is larger than ue2(ss\0) = 0 if p1 ∈ (0.5,πL] but ue2(ss\δ) = 1-δ is smaller than ue2(ss\0) = 0.5δ if p1 ∉ (0.5,πL]. In period 1, the utility of se1 ∈ {Y, N}is ue1(se\Y) = 1-p1 if p1 ≤ 0.5, else −∞, and ue1(se\N) = δ(1-0.5δ), respectively. Hence, Games 03 00119 i027 if p1 ≤ 0.5 as implied by Games 03 00119 i040.
  • (E3) In period 1, the seller’s unconditional belief is the frequency of the self-interest buyer in the population. Both buyer types accept a price p1 ≤ 0.5 and reject p1 ∈ (πH,1]. In period 2, after a p1 ∈ (0.5,πL] both types would make the same counteroffer p2 ∈ 0.5δ but the seller updates his belief on the equilibrium path to Games 03 00119 i029 from the self-interested buyer’s acceptance of this price. If p1 ∉ (0.5,πL], each types may make a different counteroffer p2 ∈ {0,δ} and the seller updates his belief to Games 03 00119 i029 after p2 = 0,made only by the envious buyer, and to Games 03 00119 i051 after p2 = δ, made only by the self-interested buyer. In period 3, the seller moves between information sets and receives no information.

Proof of Proposition 2

I show that the best pure strategy of the seller is dominated by a mixed strategy for q > 0.5 and Games 03 00119 i052: For Games 03 00119 i052, the self-interested buyer will reject p1 = πH if he can realize either outcome (0.5δ,2) or outcome (0.5,3) in a later period pooling equilibrium. An optimal strategy of the seller Games 03 00119 i004, however, must include a starting price that is at least accepted by the self-interested buyer. Thus, the seller’s best pure strategy candidate either asks p1 = 0.5 in a pooling strategy, or it asks p1 = πL in a separating strategy, or it asks p1 = πH, accepts p2δ and demands p3 = 1 in another separating strategy. Comparing the seller utility of the two separating strategies, qπL + 0.5(1-q)δ2 < qπH implies that immediate agreement on πH at the cost of excluding the envious buyer from trade is preferred. Yet, the seller can further gain utility by choosing a mixed separating strategy Games 03 00119 i033 that divides equally in period 3 with probability l such that the envious buyer accepts sometimes but the self-interested buyer continues to weakly prefer immediate acceptance. That is, Games 03 00119 i053 with probability l such that uc1(ss\πH,sc\Y) = πH is just equal to uc1(ss\πH,sc\N) = 0.5lδ2. In period 1, the seller utility is maximized by the equal division if Games 03 00119 i054 and by the mixed separating strategy Games 03 00119 i055 otherwise. The comparison of us1(ss\0.5) = 0.5 and Games 03 00119 i056 implies the threshold. The preference for a pooling strategy is bounded by Games 03 00119 i057(dashed red curve in Figure 1). As sequential rationality requires the mixed strategy in the separating continuation game even if the pooling outcome is preferred, no PBE exists in pure strategies for Games 03 00119 i052 and q > 0.5.

Acknowledgments

I thank Karl Schlag, Pascal Courty, Simon Gächter, Jordi Brandts, Ulrich Berger and the anonymous reviewers for helpful and constructive comments. I gratefully acknowledge the financial support provided by the European University Institute and the German Academic Exchange Service at an early stage of this research.

References

  1. Ståhl, I. Bargaining Theory; Stockholm School of Economics: Stockholm, Sweden, 1972. [Google Scholar]
  2. Rubinstein, A. Perfect equilibrium in a bargaining model. Econometrica 1982, 50, 97–109. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  3. Bolton, G.E. A comparative model of bargaining: Theory and evidence. Am. Econ. Rev. 1991, 81, 1096–1136. [Google Scholar]
  4. Ochs, J.; Roth, A.E. An experimental study of sequential bargaining. Am. Econ. Rev. 1989, 79, 355–384. [Google Scholar]
  5. Weg, E.; Rapoport, A.; Felsenthal, D.S. Two-person bargaining behavior in fixed discounting factors games with infinite horizon. Games Econ. Behav. 1990, 2, 76–95. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  6. Camerer, C.F. Behavioral Game Theory. Experiments in Strategic Interaction (The Roundtable Series in Behavioral Economics); Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 2003. [Google Scholar]
  7. Cooper, D.J.; Kagel, J.H. Other Regarding Preferences: A Selective Survey of Experimental Results. In Handbook of Experimental Economics; Kagel, J.H., Roth, A.E., Eds.; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA; Volume 2.
  8. Smith, R. Envy: Theory and Research; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2008. [Google Scholar]
  9. Chatterjee, K.; Samuelson, L. Bargaining with two-sided incomplete information: An infinite horizon model with alternating offers. Rev. Econ. Stud. 1987, 54, 175–192. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  10. Chatterjee, K.; Samuelson, L. Bargaining under two-sided incomplete information: The unrestricted offers case. Oper. Res. 1988, 36, 605–618. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  11. Cramton, P.C. Strategic delay in bargaining with two-sided uncertainty. Rev. Econ. Stud. 1992, 59, 205–225. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  12. Grossman, S.J.; Perry, M. Sequential bargaining under asymmetric information. J. Econ. Theory 1986, 39, 120–154. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  13. Gul, F.; Sonnenschein, H. On delay in bargaining with one-sided uncertainty. Econometrica 1988, 56, 601–611. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  14. Rubinstein, A. A bargaining model with incomplete information about time preferences. Econometrica 1985, 53, 1151–1172. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  15. Cramton, P.C. Bargaining with incomplete information: An infinite-horizon model with two-sided uncertainty. Rev. Econ. Stud. 1984, 51, 579–593. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  16. Fudenberg, D.; Levine, D.K.; Tirole, J. Infinite-Horizon Models of Margaining with One-SidedIncomplete Information. In Game-Theoretic Models of Bargaining; Roth, A.E., Ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1985; pp. 73–98. [Google Scholar]
  17. Sobel, J.; Takahashi, I. A multistage model of bargaining. Rev. Econ. Stud. 1983, 50, 411–426. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  18. Ausubel, L.M.; Deneckere, R.J. A direct mechanism characterization of sequential bargaining with one-sided incomplete information. J. Econ. Theory 1989, 48, 18–46. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  19. Ausubel, L.M.; Cramton, P.; Deneckere, R.J. Bargaining with Incomplete Information. In Handbook of Game Theory with Economic Applications; Aumann, R.J., Hart, S., Eds.; Handbook of Game Theory with Economic Applications, Elsevier: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 2002; Volume 3, pp. 1897–1945. [Google Scholar]
  20. Roth, A.E. Bargaining Experiments. In Handbook of Experimental Economics; Kagel, J.H., Roth, A.E., Eds.; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1995; pp. 253–348. [Google Scholar]
  21. Rasch, A.; Wambach, A.; Wiener, K. Bargaining and inequity aversion: On the efficiency of the double auction. Econ. Lett. 2012, 114, 178–181. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  22. Srivastava, J. The role of inferences in sequential bargaining with one-sided incomplete information: Some experimental evidence. Org. Behav. Hum. Decis. Process. 2001, 85, 166–187. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  23. Von Siemens, F.A. Bargaining under incomplete information, fairness, and the hold-up problem. J. Econ. Behav. Org. 2009, 71, 486–494. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  24. Von Siemens, F.A. Heterogeneous social preferences, screening, and employment contracts. Oxf. Econ. Papers 2010, 63, 499–522. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  25. De Bruyn, A.; Bolton, G.E. Estimating the influence of fairness on bargaining behavior. Manag. Sci. 2008, 54, 1774–1791. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  26. Goeree, J.K.; Holt, C.A. Asymmetric inequality aversion and noisy behavior in alternating-offer bargaining games. Eur. Econ. Rev. 2000, 44, 1079–1089. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  27. Bolton, G.E.; Ockenfels, A. ERC: A theory of equity, reciprocity and competition. Am. Econ. Rev. 2000, 90, 166–193. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  28. Fehr, E.; Schmidt, K.M. A theory of fairness, competition, and cooperation. Q. J. Econ. 1999, 114, 817–868. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  29. Kohler, S. Envy can Promote More Equal Division in Alternating-Offer Bargaining. In MPRA Paper 40761; University Library of Munich: Munich, Germany, 2012. [Google Scholar]
  30. Kohler, S. Guilt Causes Equal or Unequal Division in Alternating-Offer Bargaining. In MPRA Paper 40760; University Library of Munich: Munich, Germany, 2012. [Google Scholar]
  31. Driesen, B.; Perea, A.; Peters, H. Alternating offers bargaining with loss aversion. Math. Soc. Sci. 2011, 64, 103–118. [Google Scholar]
  32. Montero, M. Inequity aversion may increase inequity. Econ. J. 2007, 117, C192–C204. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  33. Kohler, S. Altruism and fairness in experimental decisions. J. Econ. Behav. Org. 2011, 80, 101–109. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  34. Tan, J.H.W.; Bolle, F. On the relative strengths of altruism and fairness. Theory Decis. 2006, 60, 35–67. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  35. Kahneman, D.; Tversky, A. Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica 1979, 47, 1–263. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  36. Myerson, R.B. Game Theory: Analysis of Conflict; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1991. [Google Scholar]
  37. Abreu, D.; Gul, F. Bargaining and reputation. Econometrica 2000, 68, 85–117. [Google Scholar]

Share and Cite

MDPI and ACS Style

Kohler, S. Incomplete Information about Social Preferences Explains Equal Division and Delay in Bargaining. Games 2012, 3, 119-137. https://doi.org/10.3390/g3030119

AMA Style

Kohler S. Incomplete Information about Social Preferences Explains Equal Division and Delay in Bargaining. Games. 2012; 3(3):119-137. https://doi.org/10.3390/g3030119

Chicago/Turabian Style

Kohler, Stefan. 2012. "Incomplete Information about Social Preferences Explains Equal Division and Delay in Bargaining" Games 3, no. 3: 119-137. https://doi.org/10.3390/g3030119

Article Metrics

Back to TopTop