Next Article in Journal
Recent Developments in Copula Models
Previous Article in Journal
On The Interpretation of Instrumental Variables in the Presence of Specification Errors: A Causal Comment
 
 
Font Type:
Arial Georgia Verdana
Font Size:
Aa Aa Aa
Line Spacing:
Column Width:
Background:
Reply

On the Interpretation of Instrumental Variables in the Presence of Specification Errors: A Reply

by
P.A.V.B. Swamy
1,
Stephen G. Hall
2,3,
George S. Tavlas
2,3,* and
Peter Von zur Muehlen
4
1
Federal Reserve Board (Retired), 6333 Brocketts Crossing, Kingstowne, VA 22315, USA
2
Department of Economics, Leicester University, University Road, Leicester LEI 7RH, UK
3
Bank of Greece, 21 El. Venizelos Ave. 102 50, Athens, Greece
4
Federal Reserve Board (Retired), Washington, DC 20551, USA
*
Author to whom correspondence should be addressed.
Econometrics 2017, 5(3), 32; https://doi.org/10.3390/econometrics5030032
Submission received: 30 June 2017 / Revised: 10 July 2017 / Accepted: 12 July 2017 / Published: 19 July 2017
We appreciate the effort and thoughtfulness of Raunig’s (2017) attempted critique of Swamy et al. (2015). As we show below, however, it is based on a misunderstanding of the distinction between simultaneous and recursive modeling.
In Section 3 of his comment, Burkhard Raunig opens his argument with a reference to Pearl (2009b) and to Pearl’s treatment of structural models and causal inference in general. But it must be pointed out that in his book on causality, Pearl (2009b) (i) confined his analysis to Markovian (recursive) models and (ii) applied to them the concept of Bayesian subjective probability to answer questions of probabilistic causation. Related treatments of Bayesian and other types of probabilistic causation are by Skyrms (1988) and, most importantly for us, the work of Basmann (1988), who dealt with simultaneous equations models. Pearl’s (2009a, pp. 173–82) Bayesian subjective views implied that “if something is real then it cannot be causal, because causality is a mental construct that is not well defined”. By contrast, Basmann (1988, p. 73) found that causality strictly refers to a property of the real world and that causal relations and orderings are unique in the real world, and, since they are unique, they remain invariant under mere changes in the language (including algebraic symbols) used to describe them. Raunig appears to follow Pearl, whereas Swamy et al. (2015) strictly follow Basmann. We present our rebuttal as four comments, designated as (R1) to (R4).
(R1) The core of Raunig’s (2017) thesis is based on his Equation (11), presented as a structural model, for which he asserts that it “encodes the causal assumption that changing or manipulating x causes y to vary. The strength of this effect is β.” We now disprove this statement and, therefore, the assertion that his Equation (11) is a structural model.
Disproof. 
Equation (11) is a reformulation of Equation (2) which is
y t = α 0 + α 1 x 1 t + α 2 x 2 t
where the implicit assumption is that α 2 x 2 t = ε t is the error term with mean zero, and y t and x 1 t are the observed dependent variable and regressor, respectively. For Raunig, Equation (1) above is the true model.
Raunig would be correct in this assessment if (i) Equation (1) above were free of misspecifications and (ii) its coefficients and error term were unique. But do these conditions hold? To satisfy condition (i), let us assume that the linear functional form of Equation (1) above is correct and there is no omitted relevant regressor other than x 2 t . To check whether condition (ii) is satisfied, let us do what Pratt and Schlaifer (1984, p. 13) (hereafter PS) did in their paper. They added and subtracted the product of the coefficient ( α 2 ) of the omitted regressor ( x 2 t ) and the included regressor ( x 1 t ) on the right-hand side of Equation (1) above. Doing so gives
y t = α 0 + ( α 1 + α 2 ) x 1 t + α 2 ( x 2 t x 1 t )
This equation is the same as (1) above and yet x 1 t has two different coefficients, α 1 and ( α 1 + α 2 ) , while the error term has two different forms, α 2 x 2 t and α 2 ( x 2 t x 1 t ) . Since we cannot prove that the coefficients and the error term of Equation (2) above are inadmissible, the possibility that (1) above can be written as (2) above establishes that the coefficients and error term of (1) above and omitted regressor are not unique and hence (1) above is a false model with non-unique coefficients and error term. In light of Basmann’s (1988) insight, models such as (1) above cannot encode the causal information. And they can surely not be structural models.
Q.E.D.
(R2) In their 1984 JASA paper, Pratt and Schlaifer (1984, p. 13) defined any linear equation with unique coefficients and error term to be “a linear stochastic law” and showed further that because neither the coefficients ( α 0 , α 1 , α 2 ) in (1) above nor its omitted regressor ( x 2 t ) are unique, the relation in (1) above cannot be considered “a linear stochastic law,” in contradiction to Raunig’s assertion that his Equation (11) “encodes the causal assumption” that changing or manipulating x causes y to vary. Swamy et al. (2015) use what is essentially Raunig’s Equation (3), x 2 t = λ 0 t + λ 1 t x 1 t , and his Equation (2) to obtain y t = α 0 + α 2 λ 0 t + ( α 1 + α 2 λ 1 t ) x 1 t . It can be shown that this equation has unique coefficients and error term and can be called “a stochastic law,” capable of encoding the causal assumption. Pratt and Schlaifer (1984, p. 13) treated α 2 λ 0 t as the random error term, as do Swamy et al. (2015), who, however, do not assume that this error term has mean zero, in contrast to Raunig who makes the potentially false assumption that α 2 x 2 t is the error term with mean zero. Swamy et al. (2015) also do not assume that the coefficients of (1) above are constant. Raunig’s assumption of the invariance of β is very strong because it is a non-unique coefficient, as is β in (1) and (2) above. However, non-unique coefficients cannot be invariant. Raunig’s claims that “the effect of a unit change in x on y is β , regardless of the values taken by the other variables in the model” and “Whether or not x is correlated with ν 0 plays no role” are false because his Equation (11) does not describe a causal mechanism. As in (1) and (2) above, we do not know whether the effect of a unit change in x on y is α 1 , ( α 1 + α 2 ) or some other number. The quantity β is not unique.
(R3) Pratt and Schlaifer (1984, p. 14) proved that although the included regressors cannot be uncorrelated with every omitted relevant regressor that affects y , they can be uncorrelated with the remainder of every such variable. Let us explain this sentence. The variable x 1 is the included regressor and x 2 is omitted regressor in Raunig’s Equation (13). What PS are saying is that x 1 cannot be uncorrelated with x 2 . Raunig also writes that x 1 is correlated with the error term ε = α 2 x 2 t . Yet Raunig and PS proceed differently from here. On the one hand, Raunig sets x 2 = λ 12 x 1 to obtain his Equation (14) and on the other hand Pratt and Schlaifer (1984, p. 13) show that in the regression y t = α 0 + α 2 λ 0 t + ( α 1 + α 2 λ 1 ) x 1 t with unique coefficient ( α 1 + α 2 λ 1 ) and unique error term ( α 2 λ 0 t ), the included regressor x 1 t can be uncorrelated with the remainder λ 0 t . In other words, PS used α 2 λ 0 t as the error term with mean 0. Since x 1 t can be uncorrelated with λ 0 t , assuming that x 1 t is uncorrelated with λ 0 t gives the result that the least squares estimator of the coefficient ( α 1 + α 2 λ 1 ) of x 1 t is consistent. Raunig’s result is different from PS’ result if λ 12 λ 1 . PS’s assumption that x 2 t = λ 0 t + λ 1 x 1 t is much more reasonable than Raunig’s assumption x 2 = λ 12 x 1 . In light of the logic underlying the argument of PS, Raunig’s assumption that x 2 = λ 12 x 1 is questionable and suggests that x 2 is a constant proportion of x 1 —an impossibility. Raunig makes the further strong assumption that x 1 = δ z to give an instrumental variable interpretation to his estimator (15). This is just an assumption and not a proof of the existence of z.
(R4) The so-called instrumental variable estimator in Raunig’s Equation (17) produces α 1 which is a non-unique coefficient of the false model with a non-unique error term in Raunig’s Equation (2). This proves that z in Raunig’s Equation (17) is not a valid instrument. Skyrms (1988, p. 59) proved that spurious correlations implied by Raunig’s Equation (2) disappear when we control for the confounding variable x 2 by controlling the included variable x 1 via Raunig’s Equation (3). Raunig writes that “Equation (3) in Section 2 is thus not consistent with the underlying structural model.” We have proved in (1) and (2) above that Raunig’s Equation (11) is not a structural model. Pratt and Schlaifer (1984, p. 14) disproved Raunig’s statement, “Varying x 1 does not affect x 2 ,” by proving that the included regressor x 1 cannot be uncorrelated with the omitted regressor x 2 that effects y . We have shown above that the error term of Raunig’s Equation (11) is non-unique. But then, how can a valid instrument be uncorrelated with a non-unique (arbitrary) error term? Thus, Raunig has not proved the existence of a valid instrument.
To summarize, using the model presented by Raunig, we have confirmed the non-existence of instrumental variables. Specifically, we have analyzed four aspects of Raunig’s true model and we demonstrated that in each aspect Raunig’s true, or structural, model is neither structural nor true. Under what we call R1, Raunig’s structural or true model has non-unique coefficients and error term, violating Basmann’s definition of causality. Under what we call R2, Raunig’s true model does not conform to PS’s definition of a stochastic law. Therefore, the model cannot be causal. Under what we call R3, Raunig’s assumption of proportionality between an omitted regressor and the included regressor is overly restrictive; PS provided a reasonable example of the relationship between an omitted regressor and the included regressor. Finally, under what we call R4, Raunig’s instrumental variable is assumed to be proportional to the included regressor. An instrumental variable estimator based on this instrument produces a non-unique coefficient of a false model with a non-unique error term.

Author Contributions

All authors contributed equally to the paper.

Conflicts of Interest

The authors declare no conflict of interest.

References

  1. Basmann, Robert L. 1988. Causality Tests and Observationally Equivalent Representations of Econometric Models. Journal of Econometrics 39: 69–104. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  2. Pearl, Judea. 2009a. Causal inference in statistics: An overview. Statistics Survey 3: 96–146. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  3. Pearl, Judea. 2009b. Causality: Models, Reasoning and Inference, 2nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
  4. Pratt, John W., and Robert Schlaifer. 1984. On the Nature and Discovery of Structure. Journal of the American Statistical Association 79: 9–21. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  5. Raunig, Burkhard. 2017. On the Interpretation of Instrumental Variables in the Presence of Specification Errors: A Causal Comment. Econometrics 5: 31. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  6. Skyrms, Brian. 1988. Probability and Causation. Journal of Econometrics 39: 53–68. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  7. Swamy, P.A.V.B., George S. Tavlas, and Stephen G. Hall. 2015. On the Interpretation of Instrumental Variables in the Presence of Specification Errors. Econometrics 3: 55–64. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]

Share and Cite

MDPI and ACS Style

Swamy, P.A.V.B.; Hall, S.G.; Tavlas, G.S.; Von zur Muehlen, P. On the Interpretation of Instrumental Variables in the Presence of Specification Errors: A Reply. Econometrics 2017, 5, 32. https://doi.org/10.3390/econometrics5030032

AMA Style

Swamy PAVB, Hall SG, Tavlas GS, Von zur Muehlen P. On the Interpretation of Instrumental Variables in the Presence of Specification Errors: A Reply. Econometrics. 2017; 5(3):32. https://doi.org/10.3390/econometrics5030032

Chicago/Turabian Style

Swamy, P.A.V.B., Stephen G. Hall, George S. Tavlas, and Peter Von zur Muehlen. 2017. "On the Interpretation of Instrumental Variables in the Presence of Specification Errors: A Reply" Econometrics 5, no. 3: 32. https://doi.org/10.3390/econometrics5030032

Note that from the first issue of 2016, this journal uses article numbers instead of page numbers. See further details here.

Article Metrics

Back to TopTop