Healing Schneider: On Merleau-Ponty’s Ethical System of Play
Abstract
:1. Introduction
- -
- First, that Merleau-Ponty comes to treat agnosia as a normative paradigm: the project of a Merleau-Pontian ethic and politics is to oppose agnosiastic tendencies and heal them. This is what I call “healing Schneider.” (Section 2).
- -
- Second, that this project is bound up with the elaboration of a hermeneutic ontology (Section 3.1).
- -
- Third, that the existential stance that results from this realization is best characterized in terms of play (Section 3.2)
2. Agnosia as a Normative Counter-Ideal
2.1. The Case of Schneider as an Axiological Case Study
2.2. Agnosia in Politics
Thus individuals who suffer from agnosia are incapable of improvising in conversation, and they lack any initiative, or freedom, in sexual conduct. They are incapable of structuring and handling a given element under different conditions, and of varying their point of view”
Being and Nothingness is largely a description of the serious man and his universe”– Sartre: freedom without action = “dried up branch”. Abstract independence and authentic freedom–Perception as mediation between the in-itself and the for-itself. Not to will but to exist–Existence as spontaneity—Independence and freedom.
All of this proves that communism fails in its intention to overcome the antithesis of the objective and the subjective […]. The problem bureaucracy-masses, = the problem spontaneous history-voluntary history, revolutionary freedom- revolutionary discipline, proletariat in fact-proletariat in right or in idea. Have either of these two ever coincided apart from some very short periods? In any case the actions of Lenin and Trotsky already showed that the balance was difficult to achieve.[14], Vol. 2, 341.
Subjectivity, in this case [means] violence and not the spontaneous course of things. Compromise and violence. Lenin: against leftism of provocation, one must know how to retreat– before the facts what must be done? Brest-Litovsk, Marxist theory– but this can be costly. And besides: how far must one take party loyalty?
3. Humanism: Hermeneutics and Play
3.1. Meaning-Making as the Nature of Politics
“art and philosophy together are precisely not arbitrary fabrications in the universe of the “spiritual” (of “culture”), but contact with Being precisely as creations. Being is what requires creation of us for us to experience it.”([21] p. 197)
3.2. Play: A Healthy Relation to the Arbitrary
[the normal subject] role-plays with his own body, he amuses himself by playing the soldier, he ‘irrealizes’ himself in the role of the soldier just as the actor slides his real body into the ‘great phantom’ of the character to be performed. ([1] p. 106) [but] [t]here is something meticulous and serious in all of [Schneider’s] behavior, which comes from the fact that he is incapable of playing. To play is to place oneself momentarily in an imaginary situation, to amuse oneself in changing one’s ‘milieu.’
Cases of ambiguous perception, where we can choose our anchorage as we please, are cases in which our perception is artificially cut off from its context and its past, in which we do not perceive with our entire being, in which we play with our body and with that generality that allows it to break at any time with all historical engagement, and to function on its own account.[1] p. 255 (trans. amended).
When I want to go from this interrogation to an affirmation and, a fortiori, when I want to express myself, I crystallize a collection of indefinite motives in an act of consciousness, I enter back into the implicit, that is, into the equivocal andthe play of the world.[1] p. 271 (trans. amended).
To this demand for a serious, perceptive, and attentive kind of prehension, one can oppose the ‘serious man’ who is under the philosopher’s watch”, […] Sartre […] criticizes ‘the spirit of seriousness’ in which the ‘serious man’ takes refuge and conceals his engagement,’ like a utilitarian and bourgeois spirit. But he appeals to a kind of seriousness that is proper to engagement.”([14], vol. 2 Note 1191).
We have been the first to replace the liberal ethics of the 19th century, based on fair play, with the revolutionary ethics of the 20th century. [...] A revolution that plays by the rules of tennis is an absurdity. The struggle may remain relatively honest in the moments in which history follows a lazy course; when it encounters critical junctures however, the only possible rule is the ancient saying to the effect that the end justifies the means. We have introduced neo-Machiavellianism in this century.([14] vol. 1, note 864).
If we consider the internal character of these games [ces jeux] we observe first that play opposes seriousness, dependency and necessity. […] Labour is serious insofar as it is concerned with needs; be it myself or nature, we must perish; if one must remain, the other must yield. Or, compared to this kind of seriousness, play belongs nonetheless to a higher seriousness for in it, nature in informed in spirit.
4. Conclusions
Funding
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | I use Landes’ translation (with amendments when noted). |
2 | See also [10] p. 7. |
3 | Samantha Matherne [12], distinguishes between the “motor-centric” interpretation of Hubert Dreyfus, Sean Kelly, Taylor Carman, and Komarine Romdenh-Romluc from her own “imagination-centric” interpretation of PP. I agree with her that the narrow “motor-centric” view is insufficient as long as it fails to include cognitive processes such as imagination. It seems to me however that Matherne’s idea that one must choose between these two accounts is grounded in the idea, that she shares with her opponents, that for Merleau-Ponty, comportment and perception must be transcendentally grounded in one or the other of the basic faculties (embodiment for the ones, imagination for the others). In my view, Merleau-Ponty’s aim is to talk about perception and action as grounding the emergence of the subject who possesses these capacities. Therefore, this subject does not precede perception and action, and there is no genuine competition between the motor-centric and the “imagination-centric” models. I thank an anonymous Reviewer for pointing out Matherne’s article to me. |
4 | See also [10] p. 4. |
5 | |
6 | |
7 | See also [14], Vol. 1, pp. 293, 352. |
8 | See also [14], Vol. 2. 380. |
9 | See also [14], Vol. 2, p. 307. |
10 | |
11 | See also [14], Vol. 1, p. 198. |
12 | |
13 | Rajiv Kaushik has recently presented a magisterial analysis of this idea in the second chapter of [24]. |
14 | As corroborating evidence, one could refer to Merleau-Ponty’s analysis of the Machiavelli case, a case tightly connected to HT, and as we now can see thanks to the new Inédits, connected to PP. For Merleau-Ponty, Machiavelli’s chief insight was that power was subjected to exactly this hermeneutic structure: obedience is both a response to power and what makes this power be. The unity of institution and recognition is bread-and-butter of politics. |
15 | See also 61/87, 245/283. |
16 | In his own study of play, Johan Huizinga [25] also insists that play achieves a kind of higher seriousness because it transcends the naïve seriousness Merleau-Ponty associates to the Yogi and what Huizinga calls “frivolity,” a kind of irresponsible action associated with the commissar. |
17 | The Inédits (especially [14] vol. 1, p. 198) seem to suggest that the famous “Note on Machiavelli” of 1949 is a direct extension of Merleau-Ponty’s polemic with Koestler in [4]. Against Koestler’s idea to the effect that Machiavellianism is a kind of materialism of force, Merleau-Ponty argues that for Machiavelli, power is of the order of meaning and maintained by a kind of play [26]. |
18 | The emphasis is Merleau-Ponty’s. As is well known, this definition of play as involving a higher kind of seriousness, combined with freedom, has been elaborated by Huizinga explicitly, although we can find traces of it in Nietzsche and Schiller among others. |
19 | The affinity between hermeneutics and play has since been well-documented by Gadamer, who also emphasises the way that play, because it embraces indeterminacy and arbitrariness, is a crucial dialectical device towards what he calls the “transformation of the world into structure” ([27] p.120). On the relations between meaning-making and play, see also, Wittgenstein’s famous analyses of language-games ([28], §23–32). |
References
- Merleau-Ponty, M. Phenomenology of Perception; Landes, D.A., Translator; Routledge: New York, NY, USA; London, UK, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Merleau-Ponty, M. Phénoménologie de la Perception; Gallimard: Paris, France, 1945. [Google Scholar]
- Merleau-Ponty, M. Sartre and Ultrabolshevism. In Adventures of the Dialectic; Bien, J., Translator; Northwestern University Press: Evanston, IL, USA, 1973. [Google Scholar]
- Merleau-Ponty, M. Le Rationalisme de Trotsky. In Humanisme et Terreur; Gallimard: Paris, France, 1947. [Google Scholar]
- Merleau-Ponty, M. The Dialectic in Action. In Adventures of the Dialectic; Bien, J., Translator; Northwestern University Press: Evanston, IL, USA, 1973. [Google Scholar]
- Merleau-Ponty, M. From the Proletarian to the Commissar. In Humanisme et Terreur; Gallimard: Paris, France, 1947. [Google Scholar]
- Mooney, T. Temporality, Subjectivity and Idealisation. In Merleau-Ponty’s Phenomenology of Perception: On the Body Informed; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2022; pp. 206–232. [Google Scholar]
- Reynolds, J.M. Merleau-Ponty, World-Creating Blindness, and the Phenomenology of Non-Normate Bodies. Chiasmi Int. 2017, 19, 419–434. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Weiss, G. The normal, the natural, and the normative: A Merleau-Pontian legacy to feminist theory, critical race theory, and disability studies. Cont. Philos. Rev. 2015, 48, 77–93. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Merleau-Ponty, M. Child Psychology and Pedagogy: The Sorbonne Lectures 1949–1952; Welch, T., Ed. and Translator; Northwestern University Press: Evanston, IL, USA, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Razavi, S. From substitute to supplement: Towards a normative reading of Merleau-Ponty’s Schneider case. Philos. Psychol. 2023, 1, 19. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Matherne, S. The Kantian Roots of Merleau-Ponty’s Account of Pathology. Br. J. Hist. Philos. 2014, 22, 137–138. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Zahavi, D. Locked-In Syndrome: A Challenge to Standard Accounts of Selfhood and Personhood? Neuroethics 2020, 13, 221–228. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Merleau-Ponty, M. Inédits 1946–1949; Dalissier, M., Matsuba, S., Eds.; Mimesis: Milan, Italy, 2022. [Google Scholar]
- Merleau-Ponty, M. Preface. In Humanisme et Terreur; Gallimard: Paris, France, 1947. [Google Scholar]
- Merleau-Ponty, M. On Indochina. In Signes; Gallimard: Paris, France, 1960. [Google Scholar]
- Gibson, J.J. The Theory of Affordances. In The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception; Psychology Press: New York, NY, USA, 1979. [Google Scholar]
- Chouraqui, F. The Body and Embodiment, A Philosophical Guide; Rowman and Littlefield: London, UK, 2021. [Google Scholar]
- Mace, W.M. Introduction, in J.J. Gibson The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception; Psychology Press: New York, NY, USA, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Merleau-Ponty, M. The Crisis of Understanding. In Adventures of the Dialectic; Bien, J., Translator; Northwestern University Press: Evanston, IL, USA, 1973. [Google Scholar]
- Merleau-Ponty, M. The Visible and the Invisible. Lingis, A., Translator; Northwestern University Press: Evanston, IL, USA, 1968. [Google Scholar]
- Chouraqui, F. The Paradox of Power. Chiasmi Int. 2018, 19, 69–85. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kovaly, P. Maurice Merleau-Ponty and the Problem of Self-Accusations. Stud. Sov. Thought 1977, 17, 225–241. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kaushik, R. The Preface to Merleau-Ponty’s Phenomenology of Perception: A Re-Introduction; Palgrave McMillan: Basingstoke, UK, 2024. [Google Scholar]
- Huizinga, J. Homo Ludens: Proeve Eener Bepaling Van Het Spel-Element der Cultuur; Willink: Haarlem, The Netherlands, 1938. [Google Scholar]
- Korsten, F.-W.; Chouraqui, F. Using Spielraum for a Normative Definition of Politics: Obama’s Play Politics and Trump’s Asceticism. Hum. Stud. 2024, 47, 573–590. [Google Scholar]
- Gadamer, H.-G. Truth and Method. Weinsheimer, J.; Marshall, D.G., Translators; Continuum: London, UK, 1975. [Google Scholar]
- Wittgenstein, L. Philosophical Investigations; Anscombe, E., Ed. and Translator; Blackwell: Oxford, UK, 1953. [Google Scholar]
- Mackie, J.L. Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong; Penguin Books: London, UK, 1977. [Google Scholar]
- Hassan, P. Nietzschean Moral Error Theory. Hist. Philos. Q. 2021, 38, 375–396. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Merleau-Ponty, M. Eloge de la Philosophie; Gallimard: Paris, France, 1960. [Google Scholar]
- van der Veken, J. Merleau-Ponty on the Ultimate Problems of Rationality. Ultim. Real. Mean. 1989, 12, 202–209. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Berman, M.P. Merleau-Ponty and God: Hallowing the Hollow; Lexington Books: Lanham, MD, USA, 2017. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2025 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Chouraqui, F. Healing Schneider: On Merleau-Ponty’s Ethical System of Play. Philosophies 2025, 10, 3. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies10010003
Chouraqui F. Healing Schneider: On Merleau-Ponty’s Ethical System of Play. Philosophies. 2025; 10(1):3. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies10010003
Chicago/Turabian StyleChouraqui, Frank. 2025. "Healing Schneider: On Merleau-Ponty’s Ethical System of Play" Philosophies 10, no. 1: 3. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies10010003
APA StyleChouraqui, F. (2025). Healing Schneider: On Merleau-Ponty’s Ethical System of Play. Philosophies, 10(1), 3. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies10010003