A Vitalist Shoal in the Mechanist Tide: Art, Nature, and 17th-Century Science
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Cavendish against Mechanists on the Art-Nature Distinction
Of things that exist, some exist by nature, some from other causes. By nature the animals and their parts exist, and the plants and the simple bodies (earth, fire, air, water)—for we say that these and the like exist by nature.
Aristotle’s examples of things that have their principle of motion outside of themselves—a bed and a coat—are stereotypical artifacts. That is, they are the kinds of things produced by artisans. He contrasts such artifacts with natural things, like animals, plants, and the elements.All the things mentioned plainly differ from things which are not constituted by nature. For each of them has within itself a principle of motion and of stationariness (in respect of place, or of growth and decrease, or by way of alteration). On the other hand, a bed and a coat and anything else of that sort, qua receiving these designations—i.e., in so far as they are products of art—have no innate impulse to change. (Physics, Book II, ch. 1, 192b9-20; [32], vol. 1, p. 329)
the work of creation and annihilation, is a divine action, and belongs only to God([25], Part 2, ch. 8, 212)
Thus, far from regarding the artisan as an artifex in the image of God, neither particular artisans nor even infinite nature itself is capable of genuinely creating or generating anything.As for nature, she being eternal and infinite, is not subject to new generations and annihilations in her particulars([25], Part 3, ch. 2, para. 8, 255)
As we will see below, this is not merely a terminological stipulation. Cavendish’s insistence that generation is a divine prerogative is backed up by at least two commitments that can be made clear by comparison with Scholastic metaphysical views: a conceptually Ockhamist understanding of (at least artificial) productions as rearrangements, and a conceptually Ockhamist commitment to the numerical identity of figure and figured bodies. (The “conceptually Ockhamist” label will be justified in Section 4, and the parenthetical restriction to “(at least artificial)” productions will be illuminated in Section 5).it is manifest that I am not of the opinion of that experimental writer who thinks it no improbability, to say, that all natural effects may be called artificial, nay, that nature herself may be called the “art of God”19([25], Part 2, ch. 2, p. 198)
While artifacts are thus inferior, they are still produced by nature, and in particular by their own animate matter, which is the internal vital principle of their own self-motion, as well as a constitutive part of nature as a whole.20 Cavendish does not offer an explicit interpretation of what she means when she calls artificial things “toys” produced by “nature’s sporting or playing actions”, nor of the other metaphors for the inferiority of artifacts offered in this passage. It is clear from her texts that Cavendish connects nature’s playing with human playing: for example, she dismisses experimental scientists as boys playing with toys.21 But finding an interpretation of these metaphors in terms of more official categories of her metaphysics is part of the work of this paper. As a step towards that interpretation, it will help to see what it is that Cavendish thinks human artisans can actually do.as much as a natural man differs from an artificial statue or picture of a man, so much differs a natural effect from an artificial, which can neither be so good, nor so lasting as a natural one. If Charles’ Wain, the axes of the earth, and the motions of the planets, were like the pole, or axes, or wheels of a coach, they would soon be out of order. Indeed, artificial things are pretty toys to employ idle time: Nay, some are very useful for our conveniency; but yet they are but nature’s bastards or changelings, if I may so call them: and though nature takes so much delight in variety, that she is pleased with them, yet they are not to be compared to her wise and fundamental actions…her artificial works, are her works of delight, pleasure and pastime: Wherefore those that employ their time in artificial experiments, consider only nature’s sporting or playing actions([25], Part 1, ch. 26, p. 105)
3. The Artisan’s Skill and Knowledge
Aristotle takes the “origin” (arche) of an artifact to be “in the maker” because he takes the efficient cause of an artifact’s coming into being to be “the application of the [artisan’s] expertise (techne)” ([48], p. 70, internal italics modified). But the previous section established that, for Cavendish, artifacts are made by nature, in the sense that they’re made by animate matter, which is nature’s principle of (self-)motion. So no Cavendishian artifact can have an “origin in the maker and not in the thing made” in the Aristotelian sense: her metaphysics does not appear to leave room for the application of an artisan’s expertise to be the efficient cause of an artifact’s coming into being.… art is identical with a state of capacity to make, involving a true course of reasoning. All art is concerned with coming into being, i.e., with contriving and considering how something may come into being which is capable of either being or not being, and whose origin is in the maker and not in the thing made; for art is concerned neither with things that are, or come into being, by necessity, nor with things that do so in accordance with nature (since these have their origin in themselves).(Nicomachean Ethics, Book VI, ch. 4, 1140a9-15; [32], vol. 2, p. 1800)
I will refer to this passage below as the artists passage. The artists passage makes both positive and negative claims. On the positive side, it says that artisans “may dissolve and compose several parts several ways”. The question of what the artisan does is thus really the question of what this “dissolv[ing] and compos[ing] several parts several ways” amounts to. As discussed in the previous section, it will not amount to generation, though as yet it remains to be seen that there is more to this claim than an unearned terminological stipulation. But before discussing this positive side of the artists passage, its negative side, Cavendish’s emphasis on the artisan “not mak[ing] the materials”, or not making the matter of the parts of nature that are composed in the production of an artifact, deserves an excursus.though art may be an occasion of the changes of some parts or motions, of their compositions and divisions, imitations, and the like; like as a painter takes a copy from an original, yet it cannot alter infinite nature; for a man may build or pull down a house, but yet he cannot make the materials, although he may fit or prepare them for his use: so artists may dissolve and compose several parts several ways, but yet they cannot make the matter of those parts; and therefore, although they may observe the effects, yet they cannot always give a true or probable reason why they are so, nor know the several particular causes which make them to be so([25], Part 2, ch. 22, pp. 241–242)
The best reason can do is to “probably guess” at such motions ([25], Part 1, ch. 25, p. 100).28 Cavendish shares this commitment to our epistemic limitations with the proto-mechanist Mersenne and the mechanist Hobbes.29 But as will shortly be seen, she draws a different conclusion than they do from our epistemic situation.For example, our sensitive perception patterns out an animal, a mineral, a vegetable, etc.; we perceive they have the figure of flesh, stone, wood, etc. but yet we do not know what is the cause of their being such figures: for, the interior figurative motions of these creatures, being not subject to the perception of our exterior senses, cannot exactly be known([25], Part 1, ch. 37, Q12, p. 175)
The kind (or maybe depth) of knowledge involved in the natural production (or framing) of creatures is thus inconceivable to humans, and so perforce to artisans.38the General actions of Nature are both life and knowledg, which are the architects of all Creatures, and know better how to frame all kinds and sorts of Creatures then man can conceive([26], Part 2, Letter 7, p. 152)
The full import of the knowingness of sympathy in particular will become clear in Section 5. But already it can be appreciated that Cavendish is consistently committed to the claim that parts can act only because they know what to do.But to return to knowledge and perception: I say, they are general and fundamental actions of nature; it being not probable that the infinite parts of nature should move so variously, nay, so orderly and methodically as they do, without knowing what they do, or why, and whether they move; and therefore all particular actions whatsoever in nature, as respiration, digestion, sympathy, antipathy, division, composition, pressure, reaction, etc. are all particular perceptive and knowing actions([25], Part 1, ch. 35, p. 139)
A kind of knowledge inconceivable to human artisans is thus not only implicated in natural productions, but is a prerequisite for all action.the sensitive parts do not only know their own work, but are also directed by the rational([25], Part 1, ch. 37, Q5, p. 159)
although every part hath its own knowledge and perception; yet, when many parts are conjoined into one figure, then, by reason of that twofold relation of their actions and near neighbourhood, they become better acquainted. And, as many men assembled in a church, make but one congregation, and all agree to worship one God, in one and the same manner or way; so, many parts conjoined in one figure, are, as it were, so many communicants, all agreeing, and being united in one body. For example, all parts concurring to compose the figure of the eye, agree together, not only in the composition, but in the act of seeing or perception, and in all other things, if regular, that are proper to that figure. The same may be understood of the parts composing the ear, and requisite to its perception; and in like manner to the rest of the senses. So that, though the parts of the eye be ignorant of the parts of the ear, as being wholly and only employed about their own composition, and the properties thereof, yet are they not ignorant of what their own adjoining parts do.([25], Part 1, ch. 37, Q5, pp. 159–160)
Of course, Cavendish does not limit her favorable comparison of the knowledge of parts to entire creatures to just our species.For example, a man knows he has a digestion in his body, which being an interior action, he cannot know, by his exterior senses, how it is made; but those parts of the body where the digestion is performed, may know it; nay, they must of necessity do so, because they are concerned in it, as being their proper employment([25], Part 1, ch. 37, Q12, p. 175)
So, eye parts, ear parts, digestive organs, and the matter that makes up bees all have the relevant kind of knowledge. In an ironic twist, though Cavendish often compares rational matter to a designer or architect, human designers and architects themselves apparently lack the kind of knowledge required to guide the particular motions required to frame creatures. Still, for Cavendish’s comparisons with humans to be instructive, we must know something. But I take it that we know things like how to saw and how to hammer, and not things like what our stomachs are doing, or (to return to artifacts) what an artisans’ materials are doing.And why may not the sensitive and rational part of Matter know better how to make a Bee, then a Bee doth how to make Honey and Wax? or have a better communication betwixt them, then Bees that fly several ways, meeting and joyning to make their Combes in their Hives?([26], Part 2, Letter 7, p. 153)
4. Mere Rearrangement, Production, and Generation
If the house is only in the power of the parts when it’s not still there, then when it is there, that power has been actualized. Further, if composing house parts actualizes a power, then an artificial production is an actuality. But this should be a case of generation, namely, the generation of the actuality. It may bear saying here that actualities are not obviously part of Cavendish’s official ontology. Further, Cavendish clearly aims to avoid the conclusion that anything, actuality or otherwise, is generated in the production of a house:the house being not there, it cannot be said that either place or house are annihilated, viz, when the materials are dissolved, no not when transformed into millions of several other figures, for the house remains still in the power of all those several parts of matter([26], Part 1, Letter 17, p. 57)
This passage has a nominalist, or at least linguistic, tinge. Things like houses “may be called new” without being genuinely new creations. Cavendish thus shares nominalists’ metaphysical parsimony, avoiding metaphysical profligacy via an appeal to language. But Cavendish is not straightforwardly a nominalist; unlike Hobbes, for example, she never talks about names explicitly.46 Nevertheless, the transformation-generation distinction in this passage is conceptually Ockhamist. For Ockham, artifacts are, as Zupko puts it, “essentially rearrangements” so that “no new thing is thereby created” ([70], p. 88). Moreover, as [69] notes, philosophers like Bacon and Descartes, whose works Cavendish definitely knew, who wanted to “avoid positing creation and annihilation of modes” could “accept rearrangement of parts” as an alternative (p. 483).47 So this conceptually Ockhamist move was historically accessible to Cavendish, despite her monolingualism.changing into such or such a figure is not the motion of Generation, which is to build a new house with old materials, but onely a Transformation; I say a new house with old materials; not that I mean there is any new Creation in nature, of any thing that was not before in nature; for nature is not God, to make new beings out of nothing, but any thing may be called new, when it is altered from one figure into another.([26], Part 1, Letter 21, p. 71)
When I say, That Place, Space, Measure, Number, Weight, Figures, &c. are mixed with Substance, I do not mean they are incorporeal, and do inhere in substance as so many corporeal modes or accidents; but my meaning is, they are all corporeal parts and actions of Nature…; for Place, Figure, Weight, Measure, &c. are nothing without Body, but Place and Body are but one thing, and so of the rest.([26], Part 4, Letter 33, pp. 535–536)
By “so of the rest” in the former passage, Cavendish means (among other things) that figure and body are but one thing. The former thoughts of the “Argumental Discourse” also say that figure and body are one thing. That is, for Cavendish, figures and bodies are just numerically identical.51 So, if conceptual space is set up in the way that Bakker’s Buridan set it up, Cavendishian rearrangements are not new generations. Moreover, this is not just an unearned terminological stipulation, but a commitment reflected in Ockhamist features of Cavendish’s metaphysics. That is, her transformation-generation distinction is cashed out in terms of mere rearrangement and then metaphysically grounded in her identification of figures and bodies.The former answered, that motion and body were not two several substances; but motion and matter made one self-moving body; and so was place, colour, figure, etc. all one and the same with body.([25], “An Argumental Discourse”, p. 37)
5. Love and Art
What makes artificial figures “hermaphroditical” is that they are “partly artificial, and partly natural” ([25], Part 1, ch. 3, p. 50).54 This is related to the artisan not making the matter of the parts that are rearranged: the artisan takes natural objects, like pieces of wood, and occasions their rearrangement into artificial productions, like houses. The artisan does not thereby make something fully artificial; the house parts are still natural pieces of wood. The Cavendishian artisan is thus unlike the Aristotelian carpenter who has the expertise to make wood first into beams so that the beams can then be used to build houses. That is, while Cavendish allows that artisans can produce houses and microscopes, she holds that their artistic powers are limited by the affordances of (potentially somewhat stubborn) natural materials. But it is not as if Cavendish thinks that natural productions never dissolve, or that parts of one natural production cannot become fully natural parts of some other natural production.55 What is lacking in the case of artificial productions, this section aims to establish, has to do with a lack of creaturely unity in artificial productions as complex wholes, which is related to the Cavendishian artisan’s inability to simply make their materials.art is not only gross in comparison to nature, but, for the most part, deformed and defective, and at best produces mixt or hermaphroditical figures([25], Part 1, ch. 3, p. 53)
The parts effect this association by working together sympathetically or, as Cavendish sometimes puts it, by “consent and agreement”.The Self-moving Parts, or Corporeal Motions, are the Producers of all Composed Figures, such as we name Creatures …such Composed Figures which we name Creatures, are produced by particular Associations of Self-moving Parts, into particular kinds, and sorts([45], Part 3, ch. 1, p. 27)
Further, the parts of a sympathetically united creature love one another passionately, and the creatures love themselves.all Natural Creatures are produced by the consent and agreement of many Self-moving Parts, or Corporeal Motions, which work to a particular Design, as to associate into particular kinds and sorts of Creatures.([45], Part 3, ch. 4, p. 31)
Sympathy is involved for a second time at this stage. For example, in a relatively early text, the 1655 edition of Philosophical and Physical Opinions, Cavendish claims that the “Sympathetical” and “Antipathetical” motions involved in war and peace “proceed from Self-preservation” as “motion in every Figure strives to maintain what [it] has created” ([19], ch. 22, p. 6). Her more mature texts return to this theme. For example, she attributes a drive for self-preservation to the passionate love between parts.Passionate Love belongs to several Parts, so that the several parts of one Society, as one Creature, have both Passionate Love, and Self-love, as being sympathetically united in one Society
She attributes agreement and disagreement, terms in which she sometimes talks about sympathy and antipathy, directly to creatures’ overarching self-love.60the Self-moving Parts of a Human Creature, being associated, love one another, and therefore do endeavour to keep their society from dissolving([45], Part 6, ch. 5, p. 75)
Both forms of love thus play a role in preserving of the creature by encouraging continued sympathy between its parts, as [67] has argued. This is a social account of creaturely unity.61 As such, it reflects Cavendish’s panpsychism, that is, her view that every part of nature is minded in virtue of containing animate (i.e., sensitive and rational) constitutive parts.62 What I want to claim here is that the artisan’s lack of control over the parts and how they behave undermines the possibility of achieving this kind of social unity among the parts of artificial productions. In particular, the artisan cannot control whether the parts love one another or behave sympathetically with one another.all Creatures have self-love … when Parts agree or disagree, it is out of Interest and Self-love.([26], Part 1, Letter 8, p. 35)
Cavendish’s literary works are non-trivially polyphonous.67 This makes identifying voices in her poems as Cavendish’s own voice rather difficult, but what it makes easy is recognizing voices as belonging to Cavendish’s characters. That is, the oak’s objections to being made into a house can be taken as reflecting Cavendish’s attempt at characterizing oak trees. They therefore reveal that Cavendish thinks that oak trees would rather not be forced into artifactual shapes. (The poem is long, and the tree also objects to being made into a ship). The oak tree’s preferences are relevant for present purposes because whether the artisan can produce a house as a unified creature depends on whether the wood of the house is prepared to behave in sympathy with, and to love, the other parts of the house. “A Dialogue between an Oake, and a Man cutting them downe” suggests fairly clearly that Cavendish would take the answer to be no.68Both Brick, and Tiles, upon my Head are laid,Of this Preferment I am sore afraid.And many times with Nailes, and Hammers strong,They peirce my Sides, to hang their Pictures on.My Face is smucht with Smoake of Candle Lights,In danger to be burnt in Winter Nights.No, let me here a poor Old Oake still grow;I care not for these vaine Delights to know.For fruitlesse Promises I do not care,More Honour tis, my owne green Leaves to beare.More Honour tis, to be in Natures dresse,Then any Shape, that Men by Art expresse.I am not like to Man, would Praises have,And for Opinion make my selfe a Slave.([18], “A Dialogue between an Oake, and a Man cutting them downe”, p. 69)
This instability, I want to suggest, is why art is only “nature’s sporting or playing actions” and why the products of art are merely toys.duration is the measure of every thing’s excellence…that a thing perishes it hath from art; that it lasts more or less, it hath from nature”
6. Conclusions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
1 | |
2 | See [3]’s analysis of continuities between mechanist and Scholastic views in connection with the art-nature distinction. |
3 | |
4 | |
5 | In a similar vein, [11] presents Cavendish’s account of epigenesis, and more broadly the rationality of nature, by comparison with William Harvey, whose commitments in these areas were, as Goldberg reconstructs them, Aristotelian. |
6 | |
7 | For Cavendish’s famous description of the limits of her childhood education, see [17], pp. 279–280. For her professions of monolingualism, see [18], “To Naturall Philosophers”, sig. A6r and [19], “An Epiloge to my Philosophical Opinions”, sig. B3v. Liam Semler has in [20,21,22] been concerned to account for Cavendish’s 1650s-era knowledge of philosophy in terms of what she might have read, including hypothesized but otherwise unknown manuscripts, while [23] claims that Cavendish “drew on Aristotelian-Scholastic sources” (p. 157), but attributes her knowledge at various points of her life to conversation (pp. 276–277) and “reading English commentaries” (p. 23). See also [24], pp. 6–9 for a discussion of Cavendish’s philosophical education as dependent upon personal interactions with her family members and exposure to their impressive circle (including Mersenne, Gassendi, Descartes, and Hobbes, among others). |
8 | The interpretation is thus a version of the “radically nominalist” interpretation of Cavendish that Colin Chamberlain has characterized as “difficult to understand” at [27], pp. 327–328, note 67. |
9 | |
10 | |
11 | |
12 | |
13 | Ref. [2], pp. 101–102. [38], p. 119ff. emphasizes similarities between the Platonic Demiurge and human artisans as early as Cicero. But see [39], p. 362 and [40], pp. 81–87 for the expression of doubts about whether the cosmos was thereby seen as a machine already in ancient times. Thanks to Miira Tuominen for discussion of this last point. |
14 | |
15 | |
16 | It is easy to think Cavendish is confused here, insofar as things that are moved cannot move themselves: “is moved” is a passive construction for a reason, so things that move themselves are not, in the relevant (passive) sense, moved. But Cavendish knows this, and plays with the distinction elsewhere (see, e.g., [25], “An Argumental Discourse”, pp. 26–27). She is just using her discussion of the Aristotelian principle to make a point she makes often, viz., that all motion is self-motion. |
17 | But see, for example, [25], Part 1, ch. 28, p. 119. |
18 | Cf. [29], p. 132. The relationship between Cavendish’s version of the art-nature distinction and that distinction in Aristotle may be subtler than this claim suggests. A proper understanding of the distinction in Aristotle might also grant nature(s) a determinative role even when it comes to art, so that Cavendish’s position here is more properly considered a mere rejection of mechanism than an innovation in its own right. But as the consideration of making materials in the next section further confirms, Cavendish seems to at least intend to put some distance between her position and orthodox Aristotelianism about art. Thanks to Ekrem Çetinkaya for discussion of this issue. |
19 | |
20 | Cf. note 15 above. |
21 | |
22 | There continues to be controversy over how to understand Cavendish’s theory of causation. Ref. [31] reads Cavendish as intentionally but esoterically adopting a Chrysippean theory of occasional causation, while [7] attributes to Cavendish a theory of genuine mind–body interactions. For a recent discussion that vindicates Cavendish’s occasionalist language, see [49]. |
23 | Aristotle consistently counts bricks among the materials of a house: see also Physics, Book II, ch. 9, 200a24-26 ([32], vol. 1, p. 341); De Anima, Book I, ch. 1, 403b1-8 ([32], vol. 1, p. 643); and Metaphysics, Book VII, ch. 7, 1033a19-21 ([32], vol. 2, p. 1631). Thanks to Ekrem Çetinkaya for directing me to the Physics, Book II, ch. 2 and De Anima, Book I, ch. 1 passages. |
24 | Of course, there is a sense in which Aristotle himself does not think that artisans make their materials: they do not make the material cause of the bricks themselves (say, the elements). But insofar as he and Cavendish share the distinction between simply making and making serviceable, and Aristotle alone endorses the claim that artisans simply make (for example) bricks as a material out of which houses can be made, he holds the view which I take Cavendish to intend to reject in the artists passage. Thanks to an anonymous referee for Philosophies for pressing me on this point. |
25 | The basic distinction between things that exist by nature and those that exist by art, drawn at Physics, Book II, ch. 1, 192b9-20 ([32], vol. 1, p. 329), is described in [50], Part 6, “The Doctrine of Aristotle”, ch. 3, p. 44, sig. (fff 3)v, a work that Cavendish describes reading at [25], Part 3, p. 249. It’s unclear where she might have picked up her further apparent knowledge of Aristotle’s commitment to artisans making their materials, as [50] does not to my knowledge discuss it, and Cavendish does not return to the negative side of the artisans passage in her explicit discussion of Aristotle at [25], Part 3, ch. 5, pp. 267–272. It’s possible she knows the distinction but does not associate it with Aristotle. For example, she might mean to express agreement with the position that “Art can make nothing but by the help of natural and perfect bodies…which it only divides or conjoynes; as when the Architect builds a House” ([51], Conference 82.1, p. 483). (Though scholars sometimes talk as though Cavendish’s reading in contemporary philosophy was a different project than her study of Thomas Stanley’s history of philosophy (see, e.g., [42], p. xv), some of the contemporary texts she read themselves functioned as secondary sources on the history of philosophy. [52], for example, typically runs through various historical positions before taking a side. One scholar to have recognized this role of contemporary texts is [23], who discusses Cavendish’s reading of Stanley at length, but nevertheless also counts works by William Harvey and Meric Casaubon as among the “most momentous for Cavendish’s understanding of Aristotle” (p. 276). As for [51], Cavendish praises it at [26], Part 4, Letter 22, p. 496. Further, of course, as noted at, e.g., [24], pp. 6–9, she learned a lot from participating in or just being present for philosophical conversations between cognoscenti). |
26 | |
27 | For a particularly scathing indictment of van Helmont for “superficial knowledg in the Art of Physick[,]” see [26], Part 3, Letter 42, p. 405. |
28 | See also [25], Part 1, ch. 37, Q3, p. 158 and Part 1, ch. 37, Q12, p. 175. Comments like these are sometimes construed in the literature as if they are mere reflections of Cavendish’s general probabilism ([56]) or fallibilism ([7]) about her philosophical system as a whole, but the claim is quite strong: we can never do more than guess at the interior motions that actually cause—as opposed to merely occasionally causing—anything. Cavendish is explicit about this in the very first work she wrote: “[natural philosophy] is of little or no use, onely to exercise their Opinions at the guessing at the Causes of Things, for know them they cannot” ([57], Lib. 3, Part 2, p. 158 [actually p. 160]). Cavendish becomes more sanguine about the probability of her guesses over time, but she never really abandons this view. For discussion of Cavendish as a mitigated skeptic, see [58], Section 7. |
29 | On Mersenne’s relationship to mechanism, see [59], Section 4.3. |
30 | See, e.g., [35], ch. 1, art. 5, p. 5. |
31 | See [62], Section 1.1. |
32 | On the relationship between Mersenne’s and Hobbes’s epistemology and their mathematization of physical space, see [62], Section 1.2. |
33 | On the extent of Hobbes’s “antirealism” about accidents, see [63]. |
34 | |
35 | See the definition of philosophy at [35], ch. 1, art. 2, p. 2. |
36 | |
37 | Perhaps here again the Hobbes comparison is instructive, as Hobbes held that we could definitely know the effects of known causes. |
38 | The relevant notion of inconceivability here is a matter of what humans can understand, and in particular does not track any kind of possibility. As Cavendish employs the notion of (in)conceivability, it does not even constrain actuality. On the actual variety of nature outrunning human conceptual capacities, see, e.g., [25], Part 1, ch. 13, p. 65 and Part 1, ch. 14, p. 68. On the actual infinity and wisdom of nature defying human conceivability, see [25], Part 2, ch. 14, p. 220 and Part 1, ch. 9, p. 60, respectively. |
39 | It also raises a more general question: how can artisans (or anyone) do anything? The short answer is by serving as occasions, and in particular as occasions for parts of nature to do what they (and not we) know how to do, as will be discussed below in Section 4. This paper is focused mostly on the negative side of the story, since the positive side is presumably just a special case of Cavendish’s more general theory of causation. (On controversies surrounding that theory, see note 22 above). But it may be that future work finds a more interesting story to tell, as [66] has done for Ockham in this issue. |
40 | |
41 | As an anonymous reviewer for Philosophies notes, artisans’ not making their materials is, on the present account, both explained by artisans’ epistemic limitations and invoked by Cavendish to explain certain of those limitations. I take it that Cavendish reasons as follows: If artisans had (counterfactually or perhaps counterpossibly) made their materials, they would know (as the artists passage puts it, in what I take to be a Hobbesian inference) “the several particular causes” underlying their behavior. But they did not make their materials, because they lack the knowledge required to do so, and the artisans’ ignorance only grows from there. |
42 | Ref. [69] identifies division and composition in Cavendish with mereological change. This identification implies a more trivial conception of wholes than the substantive conception of unified complex bodies with which this paper operates. |
43 | Ref. [69] denies that composition and division are local motions on the basis of Cavendish’s denial that bodies can change places (Section 2.2), and argues that all motion for Cavendish is rather mereological change or “compositional motion” (Section 3.1). Though engaging with the details of Peterman’s arguments is outside of the scope of this paper, suffice it here to say that Cavendish repeatedly asserts that all motions are local motions (at, e.g., [25], “An Argumental Discourse”, p. 28 and [45], Part 11, ch. 8, p. 171) and that she explicitly denies (at [25], Part 1, ch. 30, p. 125) that contraction and dilation involve mereological change. (I discuss Cavendish’s theory of place and its implications for her understanding of local motion elsewhere). |
44 | |
45 | While this section is focused on artificial productions, many of Cavendish’s claims are stated with fuller generality. Detailed discussion of how natural production goes beyond artificial production requires diving deeply into the panpsychist elements of Cavendish’s vitalism, and so will have to wait for Section 5. |
46 | By way of contrast, ch. 2 of [35] is entirely about names. |
47 | Robert Boyle, whose work Cavendish also definitely knew, likewise denied that rearrangement resulted in new creations, and advanced the nominalist claim that rearrangement merely justified “a new Denomination” or name, though he was willing to call what is produced “a new modification or manner of existence” ([71], p. 81). For comparison of Boyle’s view here with a position considered (but not ultimately endorsed) by Abelard, see [72], pp. 124–126. |
48 | See, e.g., [25], Part 1, ch. 3, p. 53. |
49 | The remainder of this section depends on the claim that Cavendish’s “one and the same” and “but one thing” claims are meant to express numerical identity claims. I give this interpretation an elaborate exposition and defense in another work-in-progress, but here readers who do not accept the claim may have to doubt the depth of the Ockhamist credentials of Cavendish’s generation-transformation distinction. That said, in deference to referees’ interest in a more elaborate discussion, I offer the following motivation of the numerical identity reading: Both Hobbes and Digby—philosophers Cavendish personally knew, and with whose works she was definitely familiar—avoid metaphysical commitments to accidents or properties by referring them to our mental representations, insisting on the oneness of substances out there in the world. Thus, Digby, discussing his sense impressions of an apple in a passage that [74], p. 241 suggests Cavendish knew, notes that “what is but one entire thing in it selfe, seemeth to be many distinct thinges in my understanding” ([75], Treatise 1, ch. 3, p. 3) and warns against the error of “a multiplying of things, where no such multiplication is really found” ([75], Treatise 1, ch. 3, p. 2). (For Hobbes, see [35], ch. 8, art. 2, pp. 75–76; for a reading of Hobbes as eliminating metaphysical commitment to accidents, see [76], Section 7.1; for criticism of [76], see [63]). Cavendish’s intellectual milieu was thus clearly marked by a concern to avoid metaphysical commitment to accidents as additional entities over and above bodies. So it is at least reasonable to consider that her assertions that various Scholastic accidents are “but one thing” with body might indeed be numerical identity claims. |
50 | |
51 | On this interpretation of “but one thing” claims, see note 49 above. |
52 | The members of this category are variously described not only as “bodies”, “figures”, and (especially when pounding the table about what is not to be admitted) “things”, but also as “parts (of nature)” and (most idiosyncratically) “corporeal figurative motions”. Whether all of these locutions are intended to pick out the same things is, of course, a matter for future scholarly controversy. |
53 | Peterman attempts to rebuild via mereology, a project begun in earnest with [69]. |
54 | Whereas I take the partly artificial, partly natural character of artificial productions to exhaust what Cavendish intends by her labelling of them as “hermaphroditical”, [79], pp. 37ff. makes much more of the sexual and gendered nature of the metaphor, attributing to Cavendish historical knowledge of connections between art and hermaphroditism in Paracelsian thought. (It is perhaps worth noting that the discussion of hermaphrodites at [51], a work Cavendish knew, covers debates about the possibility of natural hermaphroditism in Conference 100.2, pp. 577–580, but does not make the Paracelsian connection to art explicit). |
55 | See the discussion of Cavendish’s commitment to a “transmutability thesis" at [80], p. 184. |
56 | The initial version of this paragraph merely invoked Deborah Boyle’s reconstruction of Cavendish’s account at [67], pp. 93–94, which focuses on the role of (passionate and self-)love in motivating a drive for self-preservation which leads, in turn, to sympathetic motions. The present version considers more explicitly how creatures are initially produced, though I rely in no small part on textual evidence compiled in [67]. Credit for encouraging me to go into further detail here is due to two anonymous referees for Philosophies. |
57 | See also [55], Part 1, ch. 1, p. 30 and Part 1, ch. 2, p. 32; [26], Part 2, Letter 7, pp. 151–152 and Part 4, Letter 2, p. 248; and [45], Part 3, ch. 5, p. 32; Part 4, ch. 2, p. 40; Part 7, ch. 11, p. 101; and Appendix, Part 5, ch. 8, p. 302, as well as [25], “An Argumental Discourse”, p. 26 and p. 29. |
58 | Cf. Benny Goldberg’s attribution of natural productions to nature as a whole, appealing to passages describing nature’s governance of her parts at [11], p. 16. Goldberg’s picture is thus top-down whereas the picture presented here is bottom-up. The two pictures are often seen as in tension with one another—see, e.g., [49]’s distinction between top-down, bottom-up, and for that matter lateral causal relations in Cavendish—but it is unclear that Cavendish would have seen them that way, given her claim that “a whole and its parts differ not really, but only in the manner of our conception” ([25], “An Argumental Discourse”, p. 31). That is, Cavendish can be read as understanding the claim that nature produces creatures, on the one hand, and the claim that parts of nature produce creatures, on the other, as made true by the same features of reality. Resolving the puzzles invited by this view is, of course, well beyond the scope of this paper. |
59 | |
60 | See, e.g., [55], Part 7, ch. 1, p. 307 for the conception of sympathy as agreement. |
61 | On “quasi-social” features of Cavendish’s metaphysics, see [81], p. 220. |
62 | What exactly follows from containing sensitive and rational constitutive parts is a difficult question, the full resolution of which lies outside the scope of this paper. As early as [82], the ubiquity of sense and reason is suggested to imply that “Vegetables & Minerals may know/As Man, though like to Trees and stones they grow” (“Of Sense and Reason exercised in their different shapes”, p. 56). [42], expressing the standard view (as also seen in, e.g., [83], p. 499; [84], p. 459; [85], p. 87, note 15 and p. 90, note 23; [10], Section 2; [86], Section 1; [87], p. 286; [5], esp. Section 2c; [88], pp. 28–30; and [89], p. 22), held that panpsychism follows “directly from Cavendish’s application of the theory of blending" as applied to sensitive and rational matter (p. xxv). [90] notes that, for Cavendish, “every part of nature contains the same rational principle as humans”, so that when she “wants to give an explicit account of the rational souls of humans, all she has to do is identify the rational soul with a person’s rational animate matter” (pp. 636–637). (In addition to [25], Part 2, ch. 15, p. 221, cited at [90], p. 637, see, e.g., the claim that “the Mind is Animate matter” at [55], Part 6, ch. 27, p. 296). The main textual complication is that Cavendish distinguishes between animal sense and reason, on the one hand, and (e.g.) vegetable, mineral, and elemental varieties of sense and reason, on the other. She thus denies that stones feel pain, for example, but goes on to insist that stones, like everything else, has “sense and reason, according to the nature and propriety of their figure, as well as man has according to his” ([26], Part 2, Letter 20, p. 193). Scholarly consensus on how to understand these passages is a long way off, while [90] joins [91], p. 194 and [89], pp. 22–24 in going so far as to ascribe “consciousness” to all parts of nature, this is plausibly something Cavendish could have said herself if she had wanted to, and she also forbears from calling herself a panpsychist. Against such views, ref. [7] holds that Cavendish thinks much of even human behavior is “unconscious or at least non-conscious” (p. 11). Fortunately, all that will actually matter below is that Cavendish takes parts of nature to be able to resist changes in what they love or what they move in sympathy with, which could be doubted only on interpretations of Cavendish’s talk of “sense” and “reason” so deflationary as to render her terminological choices seemingly unmotivated. For very recent, in-depth discussions of the nature and extent of Cavendish’s panpsychism, see [92], which allows that a case for ubiquitous consciousness could be made but remains unusually careful about the distinction between being conscious and merely having “mental capacities” (p. 37), and [93], which characterizes “Cavendishian panpsychism” as “attribut[ing] a mind to all bodies” and “see[ing] each mind as just as mental as every other” (p. 274). |
63 | |
64 | Cf. [2], p. 69 on “the specious unity” of “the animal-machine and its mechanisms" that is “projected onto it by us when we treat them as if they were human artifacts[.]” |
65 | This question verges on difficult issues relating to the relationship between freedom and causation, which are still unsettled in the literature. If parts of nature have libertarian freedom, as [8,67,81] have argued, artisans may lack control simply because parts of nature generally lack the power to necessitate other parts of nature to do anything. But I set this aside here to focus on issues relating to artificial production in particular. |
66 | One referee questions the relevance of this poem, as predating Cavendish’s development of her vitalist materialism. First, it is unclear whether the poems of [18] do meaningfully predate her development of vitalist materialism: ref. [82] is a vitalist materialist work, and we know that Cavendish, intending to publish both works together, was hurriedly finishing its composition even as [18] was being printed. Second, Cavendish republished these lines essentially unchanged in subsequent editions of [18] in both 1664 and 1668, i.e., in the midst and at the end of her mature period. Third, as [98], p. 90 notes, Cavendish quotes and endorses her atomist poems in her other serious works as late as 1664, even as she is often thought to have moved decisively beyond them as early as 1655. Fourth, and finally, I know of no textual evidence to suggest that Cavendish’s theory of the preferences of oak trees changed meaningfully at any point in her career. |
67 | Ref. [99] was the first, to my knowledge, to broach an explicitly Bakhtinian analysis of Cavendish’s literary output. |
68 | One anonymous referee challenged the generality of this particular oak tree’s preferences, and another observes that Cavendish’s system suggests no logical or physical impossibility in the tree’s parts voluntarily forming a society with other potential house parts. Nothing injurious to the paper follows from conceding either point. On the first point, there are reasons, connected to Cavendish’s mature account of creaturely unity, to defend the generality of the oak tree’s desire to continue its treely existence. But Cavendish’s poetic conceits are often polysemous, and the oak tree does at certain moments of the poem seem to serve as a stand in for something more specific, viz., a king, perhaps Charles I. On the second point, the referee is straightforwardly correct. If parts of an oak tree experienced passionate love for other potential house parts (and their surroundings either cooperated or were compelled to yield), the resulting house might enjoy full-blown creaturely unity. But the point of the paper, here, is that the unity of an artifact depends in this way on the passions of its parts. |
69 | On Cavendish’s relation to this text, see note 25 above. |
70 | |
71 | |
72 |
References
- Shapin, S. The Scientific Revolution; University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 1996. [Google Scholar]
- Des Chene, D. Spirits & Clocks: Machine & Organism in Descartes; Cornell University Press: Ithaca, NY, USA, 2001. [Google Scholar]
- Sangiacomo, A. Modelling the history of early modern natural philosophy: The fate of the art-nature distinction in the Dutch universities. BJHP 2019, 27, 46–74. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- James, S. The Philosophical Innovations of Margaret Cavendish. BJHP 1999, 7, 219–244. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Marshall, G. Margaret Cavendish (1623–1673). Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available online: https://iep.utm.edu/margaret-cavendish/ (accessed on 22 September 2022).
- Cunning, D. Cavendish on the Intelligibility of the Prospect of Thinking Matter. HPQ 2006, 23, 117–136. [Google Scholar]
- Cunning, D. Cavendish; Routledge: New York, NY, USA, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Detlefsen, K. Reason and Freedom: Margaret Cavendish on the Order and Disorder of Nature. AGP 2007, 89, 157–191. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wilson, C. Two Opponents of Material Atomism: Cavendish and Leibniz. In Leibniz and the English-Speaking World; Phemister, P., Brown, S., Eds.; Springer: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 2007; pp. 35–50. [Google Scholar]
- Duncan, S. Debating Materialism: Cavendish, Hobbes, and More. HPQ 2012, 29, 391–409. [Google Scholar]
- Goldberg, B. Epigenesis and the Rationality of Nature in William Harvey and Margaret Cavendish. Hist. Philos. Life Sci. 2017, 39, 1–23. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Des Chene, D. Physiologia: Natural Philosophy in Late Aristotelian and Cartesian Thought; Cornell University Press: Ithaca, NY, USA, 1996. [Google Scholar]
- Rozemond, M. Descartes’s Dualism; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1998. [Google Scholar]
- Leijenhorst, C. The Mechanization of Aristotelianism: The Late Aristotelian Setting of Thomas Hobbes’ Natural Philosophy; Brill: Leiden, The Netherlands, 2002. [Google Scholar]
- Hattab, H. Descartes on Forms and Mechanisms; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Schmaltz, T. The Metaphysics of the Material World: Suárez, Descartes, Spinoza; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2020. [Google Scholar]
- Cavendish, M. The Life of William Cavendish, Duke of Newcastle, to Which Is Added the True Relation of My Birth, Breeding, and Life; John C. Nimmo: London, UK, 1886. [Google Scholar]
- Cavendish, M. Poems and Fancies; T.R. for J. Martin, and J. Allestrye: London, UK, 1653. [Google Scholar]
- Cavendish, M. The Philosophical and Physical Opinions; J. Martin and J. Allestrye: London, UK, 1655. [Google Scholar]
- Semler, L.E. The Magnetic Attraction of Margaret Cavendish and Walter Charleton. In Early Modern Englishwomen Testing Ideas; Wallwork, J., Salzman, P., Eds.; Ashgate Publishing: Burlington, MA, USA, 2011; pp. 55–72. [Google Scholar]
- Semler, L.E. Margaret Cavendish’s Early Engagement with Descartes and Hobbes: Philosophical Revisitation and Poetic Selection. IHR 2012, 22, 327–353. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Semler, L.E. Stories of Selves and Infidels: Walter Charleton’s Letter to Margaret Cavendish (1655). In Storytelling: Critical and Creative Approaches; Shaw, J., Kelly, P., Semler, L.E., Eds.; Palgrave Macmillan: New York, NY, USA, 2013; pp. 191–210. [Google Scholar]
- Begley, J. Margaret Cavendish, The Last Natural Philosopher. Ph.D. Thesis, Oxford University, Oxford, UK, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Sheehan, R.J.; Tillery, D. Margaret Cavendish, Natural Philosopher: Negotiating between Metaphors of the Old and New Sciences. In Eighteenth-Century Women: Studies in Their Lives, Work, and Culture; Troost, L.V., Ed.; AMS Press, Inc.: New York, NY, USA, 2001; Volume 1, pp. 1–18. [Google Scholar]
- Cavendish, M. Observations upon Experimental Philosophy; O’Neill, E., Ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2001. [Google Scholar]
- Cavendish, M. Philosophical Letters: Or, Modest Reflections upon Some Opinions in Natural Philosophy, Maintained by Several Famous and Learned Authors of This Age, Expressed by Way of Letters; William Wilson: London, UK, 1664. [Google Scholar]
- Chamberlain, C. Color in a Material World: Margaret Cavendish against the Early Modern Mechanists. PhilRev 2019, 128, 293–336. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Chao, T. “Between Nature and Art”—The Alchemical Underpinnings of Margaret Cavendish’s Observations upon Experimental Philosophy and The Blazing World. EurAmerica 2012, 42, 45–82. [Google Scholar]
- Dear, P. A Philosophical Duchess: Understanding Margaret Cavendish and the Royal Society. In Science, Literature and Rhetoric in Early Modern England; Cummins, J., Burchell, D., Eds.; Ashgate Publishing: Burlington, MA, USA, 2007; pp. 125–142. [Google Scholar]
- Sarasohn, L.T. The Natural Philosophy of Margaret Cavendish: Reason and Fancy during the Scientific Revolution; The Johns Hopkins University Press: Baltimore, MD, USA, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- O’Neill, E. Margaret Cavendish, Stoic Antecedent Causes, and Early Modern Occasional Causes. Revue philosophique de la France et de l’étranger 2013, 138, 311–326. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Aristotle. The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation; Barnes, J., Ed.; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1984; Volume 1–2. [Google Scholar]
- Descartes, R. Oeuvres de Descartes: Principia Philosophiae; Adam, C., Tannery, P., Eds.; Léopold Cerf: Paris, France, 1905; Volume 8. [Google Scholar]
- Descartes, R. The Philosophical Writings of Descartes; Cottingham, J.; Stoothoff, R.; Murdoch, D., Translators; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1985; Volume 1. [Google Scholar]
- Hobbes, T. Elements of Philosophy, The First Section, Concerning Body; R. & W. Leybourn, for Andrew Crooke: London, UK, 1656. [Google Scholar]
- Locke, J. Elements of Natural Philosophy. In A Collection of Several Pieces of Mr. John Locke, Never before Printed, or Not Extant in His Works; Des Maizeaux, P., Ed.; J. Bettenham: London, UK, 1720; pp. 179–230. [Google Scholar]
- Cook, M.G. Divine Artifice and Natural Mechanism: Robert Boyle’s Mechanical Philosophy of Nature. Osiris 2001, 16, 133–150. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Breen, K. Machines of the Mind: Personification in Medieval Literature; University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 2021. [Google Scholar]
- Berryman, S. Ancient Automata and Mechanical Explanation. Phronesis 2003, 48, 344–369. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Berryman, S. The Mechanical Hypothesis in Ancient Greek Natural Philosophy; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Fricke, B. Artifex and Opifex—The Medieval Artist. In A Companion to Medieval Art: Romanesque and Gothic in Northern Europe, 2nd ed.; Rudolph, C., Ed.; Wiley Blackwell: Hoboken, NJ, USA, 2019; pp. 45–69. [Google Scholar]
- O’Neill, E. Introduction. In Observations upon Experimental Philosophy; O’Neill, E., Ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2001; pp. x–xxxvi. [Google Scholar]
- Shaheen, J.L. Part of nature and division in Cavendish’s materialism. Synthese 2019, 196, 3551–3575. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Power, H. Experimental Philosophy, In Three Books: Containing New Experiments Microscopical, Mercurial, Magnetical; T. Roycroft for John Martin and James Allestry: London, UK, 1664. [Google Scholar]
- Cavendish, M. Grounds of Natural Philosophy: Divided into Thirteen Parts: With an Appendix Containing Five Parts; A. Maxwell: London, UK, 1668. [Google Scholar]
- Smith, H.L. Margaret Cavendish and the Microscope as Play. In Men, Women, and the Birthing of Modern Science; Zinsser, J., Ed.; Northern Illinois Press: Dekalb, IL, USA, 2005; pp. 35–47. [Google Scholar]
- Lascano, M.P. Margaret Cavendish and the New Science: “Boys that play with watery bubbles or fling dust into each other’s eyes, or make a hobbyhorse of snow”. In The Routledge Handbook of Feminist Philosophy of Science; Crasnow, S., Intemann, K., Eds.; Routledge: New York, NY, USA, 2020; pp. 28–40. [Google Scholar]
- Cameron, M. The Moving Cause of Artefacts: The role of techne in metaphysical explanation. Anc. Philos. Today DIALOGOI 2019, 1, 64–83. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lascano, M.P. Cavendish and Hobbes on Causation. In A Companion to Hobbes; Adams, M.P., Ed.; Wiley-Blackwell: New York, NY, USA, 2021; pp. 413–430. [Google Scholar]
- Stanley, T. The History of Philosophy, The Second Volume; Humphrey Moseley and Thomas Dring: London, UK, 1656. [Google Scholar]
- Havers, G. A General Collection of Discourses of the Virtuosi of France, Upon Questions of all Sorts of Philosophy, and Other Natural Knowledg; Thomas Dring and John Starkey: London, UK, 1664. [Google Scholar]
- Charleton, W. Physiologia Epicuro-Gassendo-Charltoniana: Or A Fabrick of Science Natural upon the Hypothesis of Atoms; Tho. Newcomb: London, UK, 1654. [Google Scholar]
- Cavendish, M. Political Writings; James, S., Ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Van Helmont, J.B. Oriatrike or, Physick Refined; Lodowick Loyd: London, UK, 1662. [Google Scholar]
- Cavendish, M. Philosophical and Physical Opinions; William Wilson: London, UK, 1663. [Google Scholar]
- Clucas, S. Variation, Irregularity and Probabilism: Margaret Cavendish and Natural Philosophy as Rhetoric. In A Princely Brave Woman: Essays on Margaret Cavendish, Duchess of Newcastle; Clucas, S., Ed.; Ashgate Publishing: Burlington, MA, USA, 2003; pp. 199–209. [Google Scholar]
- Cavendish, M. The Worlds Olio; J. Martin and J. Allestrye: London, UK, 1655. [Google Scholar]
- Boyle, D. Margaret Cavendish on Perception, Self-Knowledge, and Probable Opinion. Philos. Compass 2015, 10, 438–450. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hamou, P. Marin Mersenne. SEP 2018, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Galilei, G. De Motu. In Le Opere di Galileo Galilei: Edizione Nazionale; Favaro, A., Ed.; G. Barbèra: Florence, Italy, 1890; Volume 1, pp. 243–419. [Google Scholar]
- Westfall, R.S. Force in Newton’s Physics: The Science of Dynamics in the Seventeenth Century; Science History Publications: New York, NY, USA, 1971. [Google Scholar]
- Baldin, G. Hobbes and Galileo: Method, Matter and the Science of Motion; Springer: Cham, Switzerland, 2020. [Google Scholar]
- Joakim, S.; Ragland, C.P. Is Hobbes Really an Antirealist about Accidents? EJAP 2018, 14, 11–25. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Horstmann, F. Hobbes on Hypotheses in Natural Philosophy. Monist 2001, 84, 487–501. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mersenne, M. Nouvelles Observations Physiques et Mathematiques. In Seconde Partie De L’Harmonie Universelle; Mersenne, M., Ed.; Pierre Ballard: Paris, France, 1637; pp. 1–28. [Google Scholar]
- Pelletier, J. Getting Real: Ockham on the Human Contribution to the Nature and Production of Artifacts. Philosophies 2022, 7, 90. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Boyle, D. The Well-Ordered Universe: The Philosophy of Margaret Cavendish; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Borcherding, J. XV—`I Wish My Speech Were Like A Loadstone’: Cavendish on Love and Self-Love. Proc. Arist. Soc 2021, 121, 381–409. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Peterman, A. Margaret Cavendish on Motion and Mereology. JHP 2019, 57, 467–496. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Zupko, J. “Nothing in Nature Is Naturally a Statue”: William of Ockham on Artifacts. Metaphysics 2018, 1, 88–96. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Boyle, R. The Origine of Formes and Qualities, (According to the Corpuscular Philosophy,) Illustrated by Considerations and Experiments; H. Hall, for Ric: Davis: Oxford, UK, 1666. [Google Scholar]
- Henry, D.P. Medieval Mereology; B. R. Grüner Publishing Co.: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 1991. [Google Scholar]
- Bakker, P. John Buridan on the Ontological Status of Artifacts: Readings from his Commentaries on Aristotle’s Physics. In Proceedings of the Lomonsov-Radboud Colloquium on Medieval Logic, Metaphysics, and Science: Texts and Problems, Radboud, NL, USA, 10 November 2021. [Google Scholar]
- Georgescu, L. Bodies and Their Potential Parts: The Not-So-Friendly Reception of Digbean Quantity. In The Philosophy of Kenelm Digby (1603–1665); Georgescu, L., Adriaenssen, H.T., Eds.; Springer: Cham, Switzerland, 2022; pp. 223–246. [Google Scholar]
- Digby, K. Two Treatises in the One of Which, The Nature of Bodies; in the Other, The Nature of Mans Soule; Is Looked Into: In Way of Discovery, of the Immortality of Reasonable Soules; Gilles Blaizot: Paris, France, 1644. [Google Scholar]
- Pasnau, R. Metaphysical Themes: 1274–1671; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Majcherek, K. Paul of Venice’s metaphysics of artefacts. BJHP 2020, 28, 29–48. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Adams, M.P. Motion as an Accident of Matter: Margaret Cavendish and Thomas Hobbes on Motion and Rest. South. J. Philos. 2021, 59, 495–522. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- James, S. ‘Hermaphroditical Mixtures’: Margaret Cavendish on Nature and Art. In Early Modern Women on Metaphysics; Thomas, E., Ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2018; pp. 31–48. [Google Scholar]
- Lascano, M.P. The Power of Self-Motion in Cavendish’s Nature. In Powers: A History; Jorati, J., Ed.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2021; pp. 169–188. [Google Scholar]
- Detlefsen, K. Atomism, Monism, and Causation in the Natural Philosophy of Margaret Cavendish. In Oxford Studies in Early Modern Philosophy; Garber, D., Nadler, S., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2006; Volume 3, pp. 199–240. [Google Scholar]
- Cavendish, M. Philosophicall Fancies; Tho: Roycroft, for J. Martin, and J. Allestrye: London, UK, 1653. [Google Scholar]
- Broad, J. Margaret Cavendish and Joseph Glanvill: Science, religion, and witchcraft. Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 2007, 38, 493–505. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Broad, J. Is Margaret Cavendish worthy of study today? Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. Part A 2011, 42, 457–461. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Broad, J.; Sipowicz, M. Cavendish’s Philosophy of the Passions: Theory and Practice. In Margaret Cavendish: An Interdisciplinary Perspective; Walters, L., Siegfried, B.R., Eds.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2022; pp. 83–97. [Google Scholar]
- Duncan, S. Margaret Cavendish, Environmental Ethics, and Panpsychism. Available online: https://philarchive.org/rec/DUNMCE (accessed on 3 October 2022).
- Hustvedt, S. Afterword: Margaret Cavendish: A Grandmother for Twenty-First Century Philosophy of Science. In Margaret Cavendish: An Interdisciplinary Perspective; Walters, L., Siegfried, B.R., Eds.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2022; pp. 274–288. [Google Scholar]
- Merchant, C. Margaret Cavendish: Natural Philosopher and Feminist. In Margaret Cavendish: An Interdisciplinary Perspective; Walters, L., Siegfried, B.R., Eds.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2022; pp. 19–32. [Google Scholar]
- Thell, A.M. (Ed.) Introduction. In Cavendish, M. Grounds of Natural Philosophy; Broadview Press: Petersborough, ON, Canada, 2020; pp. 11–41. [Google Scholar]
- Shaheen, J.L. The Life of the Thrice Sensitive, Rational and Wise Animate Matter: Cavendish’s Animism. HOPOS 2021, 11, 621–641. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rogers, J. The Matter of Revolution: Science, Poetry, and Politics in the Age of Milton; Cornell University Press: Ithaca, NY, USA, 1996. [Google Scholar]
- Branscum, O. Recovering Matter’s “Most Noble Attribute”: Panpsychist-Materialist Monism in Margaret Cavendish, Anne Conway, and 17th-Century English Thought. Ph.D. Thesis, Columbia University, New York, NY, USA, 2022. [Google Scholar]
- McWeeny, J. Which Bodies Have Minds? Feminism, Panpsychism, and the Attribution Question. In Feminist Philosophy of Mind; Maitra, K., McWeeny, J., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2022; pp. 272–293. [Google Scholar]
- Brown, D.J.; Normore, C.G. Descartes and the Ontology of Everyday Life; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2019. [Google Scholar]
- Frigo, A. A very obscure definition: Descartes’s account of love in the Passions of the Soul and its scholastic background. BJHP 2016, 24, 1097–1116. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Des Cartes, R. The Passions of the Soule in Three Books; A.C.: London, UK, 1650. [Google Scholar]
- Sperber, D. Seedless Grapes: Nature and Culture. In Creations of the Mind: Theories of Artifacts and Their Representation; Margolis, E., Laurence, S., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2007; pp. 124–137. [Google Scholar]
- Walters, L. Margaret Cavendish: Gender, Science and Politics; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- Freidl, H. Creatoress, Duchess, Empress—A Narratological Mess: Problems of Discourse and Implied Worldview in Cavendish’s Description of the Blazing World. In Proceedings of the 13th International Margaret Cavendish Society Conference, Trondheim, Norway, 6 June 2019. [Google Scholar]
- Cunning, D. Margaret Cavendish on the Imagination and the Dramatic Force of the Imaginary World. In Early Modern Women on Metaphysics; Thomas, E., Ed.; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2018; pp. 188–210. [Google Scholar]
- Cunning, D. Cavendish on Material Causation and Cognition. In Causation and Cognition in Early Modern Philosophy; Perler, D., Bender, S., Eds.; Routledge: New York, NY, USA, 2020; pp. 145–170. [Google Scholar]
- Cavendish, M. A Collection of Letters and Poems: Written by Several Persons of Honour and Learning, Upon Divers Important Subjects, to the Late Duke and Dutchess of New Castle; Langly Curtis: London, UK, 1678. [Google Scholar]
- Dodds, L. The Literary Invention of Margaret Cavendish; Duquesne University Press: Pittsburgh, PA, USA, 2013. [Google Scholar]
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2022 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Shaheen, J.L. A Vitalist Shoal in the Mechanist Tide: Art, Nature, and 17th-Century Science. Philosophies 2022, 7, 111. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7050111
Shaheen JL. A Vitalist Shoal in the Mechanist Tide: Art, Nature, and 17th-Century Science. Philosophies. 2022; 7(5):111. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7050111
Chicago/Turabian StyleShaheen, Jonathan L. 2022. "A Vitalist Shoal in the Mechanist Tide: Art, Nature, and 17th-Century Science" Philosophies 7, no. 5: 111. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7050111
APA StyleShaheen, J. L. (2022). A Vitalist Shoal in the Mechanist Tide: Art, Nature, and 17th-Century Science. Philosophies, 7(5), 111. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7050111