Could a Computer Learn to Be an Appeals Court Judge? The Place of the Unspeakable and Unwriteable in All-Purpose Intelligent Systems
Abstract
:“Formal logic must not be too formal. It must represent a fact of experience, or else it is in danger of degenerating into a mathematical recreation.”C. S. Peirce [1] (2. 710)
“You should never express yourself more clearly than you are able to think.”Niels Bohr to Abraham Pais, viva voce.
1. Fred
1.1. Beings like Fred
What Actually Happens Rule: In the first instance, attend with care to the observable regularities in Fred’s cognitive behaviour. In the second, make your best fist of their abductive accountancy, that is, of bringing them into some overall coherence. In the third instance, do not let theory override reality without just cause.
Corollary: And keep in mind that Fred’s role here is that of Everyman.
1.2. Abduction
“Proposals for hypotheses inundate us in an overwhelming flood while the process of verification to which each one must be subject before it can count as at all an item even of likely knowledge, is so very costly in time, energy, and money, the Economy here would override every other consideration even if there were any other serious considerations. In fact there are no others.” [1] (5. 602; emphasis mine.)
1.3. Some Legal Peculiarities
1.4. The Intentional and the Impalpable
1.5. Inconsistency-Management
Consequence-having: S’ follows of necessity from S1, …, Sn, just in case there is no respect in which it is in any way possible for the Si to be true and S’ not. 32[36]
- Which of these facts, beyond truth preservation, are dispositive for truth-preserving reasoning?
- The first law of proof-theory: Aside from truth-preservation, no fact about the entailment relation which follows from entailment itself is dispositive for truth-preserving and cognitively tenable proof.
- Corollary: Not, therefore, modus ponens, not modus tollens, and not either belief-closure.
1.6. Talking
1.7. Brains
“This special kind of ‘openness’ is physically rooted in the fundamental character of the brain as an open system constantly coupled with the environment (that is, [it is] an “open” or “dissipative” system): its activity in the uninterrupted attempt to achieve equilibrium with the environment in which it is embedded, and this interplay can never be switched off without producing severe damage to the brain.” [64,65,66] 51
“come within the range of every man’s normal experience, and for the most part in every wakening hour of his life.”[1] (1. 241)
Moreover, they constitute
“the universal data of experience that we cannot suppose a man not to know and yet be making enquiries.”[1] (4. 116)
So it is not clear whether Peirce can hold his intellectualist serve.
“In the dissipative quantum model of the brain the vacuum code is taken to be the memory code. Again memory is represented by a given degree of ordering. A huge number of memory records can thus be stored, each one in a vacuum of a given code …. In the dissipative model, all the vacua are available for memory printing.” [68,69,70] 53
1.8. Cognitive Economies
1.9. Jiu-Jitsu Advantage
“Recently, perceptual psychologists have developed Helmholtz’s suggestion by modeling perception as unconscience Bayesian inference. On a Bayesian approach, the perceptual system maintains prior probabilities regarding the distal environment (e.g., certain retinal inputs are deemed likelier than others) and prior likelihoods that relate the distal environment to sensory input (e.g., certain retinal inputs are deemed likelier given certain distal shapes and certain lighting conditions). The perceptual system deploys these prior to transit from sensory input to a posterior-probability (e.g., the posterior may assign high probability to the perceived object having a convex shape. Based on the perceptual system chooses a privileged estimate of distal conditions.”
1.10. Fallibilism and Epistemic Bubbles
1.11. The Causal-Response Epistemology
- The knowledge as causal thesis: Fred knows that S on information I when S is true; in processing I, Fred’s belief-forming devices were causally induced to produce the belief that S, Fred’s devices are in good working order and operating here in the way that nature designed them to, I is good information (up to date and accurate) and there is no interference caused by negative externalities (e.g., too many bourbon Manhattans).
1.12. The Place of Information in Knowing
“Information is raw data from any source, data that might be fragmentary, contradictory, unreliable, ambiguous, deceptive, or wrong. Intelligence I information that has been corrected, integrated, evaluated, analyzed and interpreted.” 72
“… what (if anything) is meant by these different ‘informations’—or whether they are related to each other at all. These questions seem to mark a most urgent challenge to philosophical analysis.” 73[98]
- Talk is epistemically freighted: Most of what Fred will ever know in life depends on someone having told someone something, and in doing so, causing him to know it. Most of what we know is the end product of a multi-agent manifold of epistemically productive tellings. In cost-benefit terms, telling is the highest yielding of one of our most expensive assets.
The phase-transition thesis: Information down below is subject to phase transitions from one state to a qualitatively different state up above, and is also capable of reverse phase transition back down. In the passage upwards, information loses properties and gains opposite ones. On the way down, properties acquired on the way up are lost and their opposites regained. In a more antique formulation, when information is in phase transition, it retains its haecceity and loses its prior quiddity in acquiring a new one.
“The soul [= mind] then certainly does act dynamically on matter. It does not follow that it acts directly on matter, because there may be involved an endless series of transformations of energy from the motion of one fluid to another, all these fluids being spiritual [= mental], followed by the beginningless series of transformations of energy in one fluid to anergy in another. All these fluids being material.”(NEM, 3, 897)
2. Madam Justice Flanagan 81
Relevant Similarity
The rule of judge-made law: When a precedent arises from a juridical finding in a case framed around some particular facts, it is easy to state the rule of law that attends it. The rule says that in any future case whose facts bear a sufficiency of relevant similarity to the facts on which the original finding was based, then in the subsequent case the court must find as in the originating case.
- The facts material to the court’s original finding.
- The finding in the present case.
- The rule of law as just stated.
- The facts of the original cases do not travel; that is to say, they are not the facts material to future cases.
- The finding, however, does travel; that is to say, the finding of the first case retains re-application in the future case.
- The rule of law has standing general authority. In any subsequent case when new law, the finding must be not discomply with the prior finding.
The real source of the non scripta problem: The sense in which precedents are unspeakable and unwriteable is that the concepts embedded in the applicable rule of judge-made law—the concepts of sufficiency and similarity—are not subject to biconditional definition in law. The law rues the very idea of biconditional hook on words in common use. Wisely so.
Corollary: This is not a peculiarity of the law. Most words, expressions and sentential utterances in the working vocabulary of the common man is not only understood in the absence of a definitions, but efforts to give the meanings of those items full-voiced biconditional articulation would, with a striking frequency, misdescribe them. 84
The how-possible question: How is it possible for someone to know something without being able to say what it is that he knows? (St. Augustine on time.) Because it lies in the nature of the subject matter for some of its aspects to be known to their information processors, both expert and otherwise, and to be known to the non-expert tacitly and implicitly.
3. Frederika
How Things Are Now
The enablement-manifestation question: When a being operates or responds in a way that manifests intelligence, must the intelligence in question inherit the peculiarities of its means of enablement?
- Can Frederika go it alone in cognitive life independently of her fellow counterparts?
- Is Frederika susceptible to intuitively subpar performance for the good of cost-benefit compensatory payoff?
- Is Frederika bound by conditions under which TI-knowledge is the best outcome?
- In what does the larger virtuosity of intelligence inhere? In the skills possessed by the agent or in the agent’s natural resources?
- Judged in one way, Frederika would match or better the outcomes redounding to Fred’s application of his skills to the resources at his command.
- Judged in the other, the outcomes achieved by Fred would have the greater intelligence quotient.
- So is there any overall benefit to be achieved by Frederika by building into her the productive limitations of Fred and his jiu-jitsu manoeuvres—his cognitive sweeps so to speak?
- All these are questions of sufficient interest and importance, but the truly core question is: can Frederika be built with the instinct for truth-creation about beings impalpable to us and also to her?
- When Conan Doyle thinks up Sherlock and writes down things about him, he makes Sherlock, and makes things true of him, as a matter of real-world fact. Sherlock is a man, a real man, a real man of fiction, just as π is an actual number of mathematics.
- When an out-of-the-box mathematician is seized of a new idea and incorporates it into a hypothesis, then given the ways of the world, the hypothesis, if well-abduced, is gravid with young truth.
- This is fully half the semantic reality of mathematical truth. The other half is provided by the conditions, should they obtain, by which a young truth matures into the real thing.
- When all opposition subsides, we are left with an abduction problem. What hypothesis, if true, would account for such placement in a mathematical economy in wide reflective equilibrium? Since there is in such cases no question of testing the matter by direct observation of the real truth of the matter, what would Fred recommend as the answer?
- And could Frederika match this or better it?
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
1 | The correct spelling is “unwritable”, as with “undecidable”. I misspell it on purpose to bring the inscription more in line with the spoken word. |
2 | While the usual expression is “cognitive agent”, it suggests agency when there often is none, and overlooks the frequency with which knowledge just happens to one. You check your inbox and find: “Nancy just called. Could you give her a ring at her office when you get a chance?” Now you know that Nancy called, and you did not lift a finger to know it. All you needed were some functioning eyes and a basic command of English. The more accurate alternative to “cognitive agent” would be “cognant”. Still, since “cognant” is unlikely to have much take-up in the research community, I’ll go with the flow and stick with “cognitive agent”, and leave it to context to determine when agency is involved. |
3 | My ascription of intelligence to Fred is without prejudice to the disputed questions of nonhuman and nonlinguistic cognition. See here Bermúdez [2], and “Animal reasoning and proto-logic” in Bermúdez [3] (pp. 127–137). For a good examination of future prospects, readers are invited to consult Park [4] (pp. 1–32). My own position can be put this way: Spend a fortnight with a social ecologist examining the activities at a bumblebee colony. It will soon be noticeable how causal forces dominate bumblebee economies. See here Heinrich [5]. |
4 | In its most widely circulated form, here is Peirce’s schematization: “The surprising fact C is observed. But if A were true, C would be a matter of course./Hence there is reason to suspect that A is true.” [1] (5. 189). The line-breaks are mine. The schema gives a sample of Peirce’s thinking, but is not to be considered the final word. |
5 | In routine diagnostic settings, symptoms present themselves and are already known to be of this or that or some other malady in the general case. But, as in law, so in medicine, facts of a given case often differ from facts of like kind in the general case. The abducing physician must select this or that or the other, or do some fresh thinking. |
6 | These days, it is impossible to be unmindful of the large pockets of resistance to these ways of speaking. If amends could be made by speaking instead of the woman in the street or the common woman, I would contemplate adopting them. But since they do not work, I shall not adopt them, and will not deign to feign acquiescence to the imagined singularity of the plural pronoun “they”. |
7 | “Abduction is the process of forming an explanatory hypothesis. It is the only logical operation which introduces any new idea; for induction does nothing but determine a value, and deduction merely evolves the necessary consequences of a pure hypothesis.” [1] (5. 171) |
8 | The point is argued in my “Abduction and inference to the best explanation”, in [7]. |
9 | Note the resemblance to certain readings of verificationist criterion of meaning. |
10 | Inference is “the conscious and controlled adoption of a belief as a consequence of other knowledge.” [1] (2. 442) |
11 | Note that these considerations cleanse Peirce’s understanding of guessing of any connotation of shots in the dark. Peirce’s guesses are educated guesses. |
12 | For consciousness without attention, see Mole [8]. |
13 | Details can be found in Woods [9]. |
14 | Details can be found in [9]. |
15 | See [1] (2. 58). |
16 | |
17 | See [15]. |
18 | In the jurisdictions of my acquaintance, it is customary to refer to members of the appellate bench as “justices” rather than “judges”. We can be more flexible in our usage here. It is customary to refer to a high court judge as, for example, Madam Justice A. T. Flanagan or, more briefly, as Flanagan J. |
19 | |
20 | Lower court decisions from other common law jurisdictions can have “persuasive authority” for sister courts at home. Such decisions are not binding. Also, in some jurisdictions, for example Canada and the United States, the Supreme Court can sometimes find a way to reverse some of its own findings. This is a constitutionally tricky thing to do, since the Supreme Courts are the tribunals of last resort. |
21 | Considerable credit is due computer scientists for having spotted the logico-epistemic importance of the administration of justice. It is a matter of regret that the same cannot be said for epistemologists or logicians. To this day in English-speaking countries, university courses on the philosophy of law are wholly absorbed with issues in ethics as well as social and political theory. Journals of logico-epistemic note include Artificial Intelligence and Law and JURIX. |
22 | Woods [18]. |
23 | |
24 | The meaning here is that from any logically false proposition, every statement of the language in which the inconsistency arose is thereby logically entailed. |
25 | Think here of the Erdös discrepancy problem, some attempted proofs of which require more gigabytes than that of Wikipedia in its entirety. |
26 | |
27 | Morris [25]. |
28 | |
29 | |
30 | See Frege [33], and Frege [34]. The difference between the paraconsistent and Fregean response to inconsistency lies in the fact that they were responding to different things. For paraconsistents, the bête noir was not a given inconsistency but rather what any given inconsistency logically entails, namely the inconsistency of every statement in the system, proved by the theorem called ex falso quodlibet (from a [logical] falsehood everything follows). So any system thus afflicted simply blows up (“explodes”, “detonates”). Ex falso is derivable in Frege’s system, but this is damage to a system that had already collapsed. The trouble was local, Frege’s comprehension axiom for sets (value ranges of functions). Under Russell’s prodding, Frege was able to prove that his axiom entailed a contradiction. With the axiom now disabled, every theory of the system whose proof depends on that axiom is also disabled, as in turn any further theorem depending on those theorems, and so on. In short, the system simply falls down. It does not blow up. |
31 | |
32 | Let us keep in mind that it was Tarski, after all, in his classic and ground-breaking paper of 1936 on logical consequence, who insisted that when adapted to the special needs of the metamathematics of classes, the results must preserve as much of this meaning as possible. The sole exception was the theory’s use of the uniform substitutivity of nonlogical terms for other nonlogical terms of the grammatically admissible type. See here, in excellent translation, Alfred Tarski, “On the concept of following logically” [36] translated by Magda Stroińska and David Hitchcock, with an introduction by Hitchcock. |
33 | Making such a logic is the primary object of Woods [9]. |
34 | |
35 | For example, von Neumann computers cannot handle higher order logics, but Vladimir Lifschitz has pointed out that McCarthy’s Circumscription can be computed for a class of separable formulas which contains only quantifier-free formulas. See, for example, Gershan et al. [40], Adams et al. [38], Clark [16], and Park [42]. An important exception is Bruza and Gibson [43]. My own view is that Fred’s cognition is the unmediated causal outcome of largely subconscious information processing devices. See here Busemeyer et al. [39], and Kirkhof and Robertson [41]. |
36 | Representationist theories are thick on the ground and often at significant variance with one another. See, for example [16,38,40,42]. An important alternative is [43]. My own view is that Fred’s cognition is the unmediated causal outcome of largely subconscious information processing devices. See here [39,41]. |
37 | As its students will know, as the Second World War was coming to an end in Europe, and Allied soldiers were more widely dispersed than ever, there would appear on walls and fences without apparent surcease the drawn figure of two hands clutching the top of the structure, betwixt a pair of large eyes and overhanging large beak, and just below the inscription “Kilroy was here”. No one reading those words with understanding will not have known that the string inscribed under the cartoon asserted the recent presence of someone called “Kilroy”. |
38 | A good account of how this came about is Everett [44]. |
39 | In announcing “l’état, c’est moi”, Louis XIV was more venturesome than accurate. Louis XVI was spot on with the dire prediction, “Après moi, le déluge”. |
40 | There are notable resemblances between Peirce and Schopenhauer, author of the famous The World as Will and Representation. One day during a pleasant Ann Arbor lunch, Arthur Burks quipped to the present author that Peirce’s semiotics could be entitled The World as Willful Misrepresentation. |
41 | |
42 | |
43 | |
44 | In the late 1990s, during a visit from the University of Toronto to Dov Gabbay’s Logic and Computation Group at King’s College London, Ray Reiter, the mathematician who founded the computational logic of default reasoning in 1980, mentioned to the two of us that he, Reiter, would not then make the long-list for appointment to a computer science department even at a second-tier university. |
45 | |
46 | Cobb [57]. |
47 | |
48 | There were exceptions of course. See, for example, Fukushima [59]. |
49 | Automated taxi-drivers are a bit trickier to sort out. Although here, too, there were some early successes, as witness the VaMoRs van of automatic mobiling based on the work of Ernst Dickmanns. As anyone familiar with London’s black cab fleet, drivers are held to a very high expectations of cartographic memory. There are also the sundry obligations of law and social convention to observe. But no London cabbie will prosper if he does not master the art of breaking the traffic laws systematically, safely and without too much notice. In our plans for Frederika, is it contemplated that she would be thus accoutered? For more on taxi-driving robots, see Gabbay et al. [60]. |
50 | |
51 | |
52 | In this paragraph and the next I draw upon Woods [67]. |
53 | |
54 | |
55 | Simon [8]. |
56 | From the nursery rhyme “Hey diddle-diddle, the cat and the fiddle”, and not really a fable at all. |
57 | With a respectful nod to Hamlet, Act 3, scene 2. |
58 | For more on the importance of commonness for Fred’s cognitive well-being, readers could consult Woods [74]. |
59 | I hope that it needs no saying that no such indictment is intended of Alexander Grothendiek, author of the splendid [75]. In a way, it is regrettable that “stupid” also means unintelligent, not-smart or, as in the vulgate, dumb. The usage proposed here bears some likeness to “foolish” which, in some contexts, carries connotations of the comic or amusing. “Unwise” is best here, meaning “of unsound judgement”. |
60 | |
61 | Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews, 2017. 01. 15, 1–10. |
62 | Helmholtz [77]. |
63 | Not to be overlooked is the threefold ambiguity of “fallibilism”. In its epistemic sense, it is the doctrine according to which it is possible that some given proposition, which presently I experience myself as knowing, I actually do not. In its logically independent alethic sense, it is possible that the thing I presently experience myself as knowing is actually false. (Note that instantiation of sense one does not entail the instantiation of sense, but the entailment does hold in reverse. In its synechist sense endorsed by Peirce, fallibilism is the doctrine that no proposition of whatever modality currently known to be true will stay true no matter what.) |
64 | |
65 | A classic work is Cohen [81]. In some writings “assent” is a third meaning. In a fourth sense, belief is “commitment”, concerning which see Walton and Krabbe [82], and for a different perspective Woods [83]. As the book was ready for production, Hermes was shutting down its English-language operations, and it took some doing to get the book published. When the time came for a second and revised edition with College Publications in 2014, I unwisely omitted this chapter, the first edition being long out of print and virtually impossible to find. Time permitting, I will refresh the chapter on induction and republish it on its own. |
66 | Woods [84]. |
67 | Floridi [90]. Perhaps the best single-volume treatments of the current state and future prospects of the philosophy of information are Adriaans and van Benthem [85] and Floridi [89]. Also important is Dretske [88]. Older but still in fine fettle is Cover and Thomas [87]. For early applications to psychology, see Attneave [86]. |
68 | |
69 | |
70 | |
71 | Adriaans and van Benthem [85] (p. 12). |
72 | See here Adriaans and van Benthem [85] (p. 7). |
73 | Hintikka [98]. |
74 | Jaakko Hintikka [99] “What is abduction?” The fundamental problem of contemporary epistemology”, Transactions of the Charles Peirce Society, 34 (1998), 503–533. Reissued with revisions in Socratic Epistemology (2007), as “Abduction—inference, conjecture, or answer”, pages 38–60. |
75 | Note here the resemblance to the endless wash of entailment-inconsistency, and the dab hand we are in making highly selective and hugely productive uses of it. |
76 | Zimmerman [100]. |
77 | See, for example, Schiffrin [101]. |
78 | In “Four-grades of ignorance-involvement and how they nourish the cognitive economy” [102], I launched the idea of anselmian knowledge, St. Anselm is well-known for his declaration “Credo, ut illelligam”, which I translate as saying that he believes in order that he might be assisting in coming to understand. As striking as the incidence of told-knowledge is Fred’s cognitive economy; not far behind is the incidence of Anselmian knowledge. Consider what most people know about the constitution of energy. It is conveyed by the sentence “E = mc2”. Some people have a deep understanding of what the equation provides. But what the man in the street knows of it is that it expresses a law of physics about energy and mass. People who know just that of it are not in the same boat as someone who has no idea of what it says. Two things, beyond its great frequency, stand out about Anselmian sentences. One is their semantic lightness and, with it, the propensity to travel cheaply. The other is that in the passage from the Anselmian to be more fully grasped, the way is eased by what is implicitly and tacitly known. It also travels cheaply. |
79 | Excluding those that arise from partisan-ridden branches of enquiry or, worse, sectors of enquiry routinely hobbled by government agencies that cook the books and issue lying reports of the known facts. |
80 | |
81 | Flanagan J is a creature of imaginary convenience, standing in for the bench of which she is a member. Justice Flanagan won a substantial reputation as corporate crimes trial counsel, followed by a six-year tenure as provincial court judge. She is currently the Chief Justice of her court. Here initials stand for “Anne Theresa”, and she is known as Theresa. |
82 | The doctrine of stare decisis is under current duress in Canadian courts by activist judges in courts below. See here Woods [18], appendix H. |
83 | Beyond the intention of the legislators (roughly speaking). |
84 | Think here of the classical definition of deductive implication: Propositions S1, …, Sn deductively imply proposition S’ if and only if it is in no sense possible for the Si to be jointly true and S’ concurrently not. When read from left to right, the definition is met with widespread communal approval. But when read from right to left, the approval rate goes down; and if attention is called to ex falso, approval rates tumble. Ex falso is the doctrine that a contradiction deductively implies every proposition whatever. This does not, of course, falsify the definition. But it does suggest that when people make the correct consequence-attributions, they are implementing the left to right reading. |
85 | I have drawn these remarks from the Report on Business section of Toronto’s Globe and Mail, 25 April 2022, section B, pp. 1 and 8. |
86 | With a population one-tenth the size of the American population, this represents a cost in US terms of ≈ 220 USD p/a. It is not chump-change, and the thing does not work. |
87 | More of this is on view in the closing chapter of Woods [9]. |
88 | See, for example, Tappenden [105]. |
References
- Peirce, C.S. Collected Papers; Hartshorne, C., Weiss, P., Burks, A.W., Eds.; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1958. [Google Scholar]
- Bermúdez, J.L. Thinking Without Words; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Bermúdez, J.L. Animal reasoning and proto-logic. In Rational Animals? Hurley, S., Nudds, M., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2006; pp. 127–137. [Google Scholar]
- Park, W. What proto-logic could not be. Axiomathes 2021, 1–32. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Heirich, B. Bumblebee Economics; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1979. [Google Scholar]
- Peirce, C.S. Philosophy of Mathematics: Selected Writings of Charles Sanders Peirce; Moore, M.E., Ed.; Indiana University Press: Bloomington, IN, USA, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Woods, J. Abduction and inference to the best explanation. In The Critical Thinking Book; Blair, J.A., Ed.; WSIA: Windsor, ON, USA, 2018; pp. 405–430. [Google Scholar]
- Mole, C. Attention and consciousness. Conscious. Stud. 2008, 15, 86–104. [Google Scholar]
- Woods, J. The Three Dimensions of Deductive Involvement and How They Matter for Proof Theory; forthcoming in 2023; Department of Philosophy, University of British Columbia: Vancouver, Canada.
- Peirce, C.S. The Charles S. Peirce Papers; Harvard University Photographic Service: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1966. [Google Scholar]
- Kakas, A.C.; Kowlaski, R.A.; Toni, F. Abductive logic programming. J. Log. Comput. 1992, 2, 719–770. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pople, H.E., Jr. On the methanization of abductive logic. In Proceedings of the International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence (IJCAI-73), Stanford, CA, USA, 20–23 August 1973; pp. 147–152. [Google Scholar]
- Poole, D.; Goebel, R.; Aleixunas, R. Theorist: A logical reasoning system for defaults and diagnosis. In The Knowledge Frontier: Essays in the Representation of Knowledge; Cercone, N.J., McCalla, G., Eds.; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 1987; pp. 331–353. [Google Scholar]
- Burks, A.W. Peirce’s theory of abduction. Philos.Sci. 1946, 13, 301–306. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Shannon, C.E.; Weaver, W. The Mathematical Theory of Communication; University of Illinois Press: Urbana, IL, USA, 1949. [Google Scholar]
- Clark, A. Surfing Uncertainty: Prediction, Action, and the Embodied Mind; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Cantwell Smith, B. The Promise of Artificial Intelligence: Reckoning and Judgment; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2019. [Google Scholar]
- Woods, J. Is Legal Reasoning Irrational? An Introduction to the Epistemology of Law; College Publications: London, UK, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Hewitt, C. Formalizing common sense reasoning for scalable inconsistency-robust information coordination using Direct Logic Reasoning and the Actor Model. In Inconsistency Robustness; College Publications: Rickmansworth, UK, 2015; pp. 3–103. [Google Scholar]
- Hewitt, C.; Woods, J. Inconsistency Robustness; Studies in Logic; College Publications: London, UK, 2015; Volume 52. [Google Scholar]
- Benaceraff, P. Mathematical truth. J. Philos. 1973, 70, 661–679. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Goldman, A.I. A causal theory of knowing. J. Philos. 1967, 64, 357–372. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Quine, W.V. Epistemology naturalized; (pre-printed in Quine, Relativity and Other Essays); Columbia University Press: New York, NY, USA, 1969; pp. 69–90. [Google Scholar]
- Kripke, S. Naming and Necessity; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1982. [Google Scholar]
- Morris, C.W. Writings on the General Theory of Signs; Mouton: Hague, Netherlands, 1971. [Google Scholar]
- Lewis, D.K. Convention: A Philosophical Study; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1969. [Google Scholar]
- Austin, J.L. How to do Things With Words; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 1961. [Google Scholar]
- Grice, H.P. Studies in the Way of Words; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1989. [Google Scholar]
- Batens, D.; van Bendegem, J.P.; Priest, G. Frontiers of Paraconsistency; Research Studies Press: Baldock, UK, 2000. [Google Scholar]
- Priest, G.; Routley, R.; Norman, J. Paraconsistent Logic: Essays on the Inconsistent; Philosophia: Munich, Germany, 1989. [Google Scholar]
- Priest, G. Paraconsistency and dialetheism. In The Many Valued and Nonmonotonic Turn in Logic; Gabbay, D.M., Woods, J., Eds.; Elsevier: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 2007; pp. 129–204. [Google Scholar]
- Schotch, P.; Brown, B.; Jennings, R. On preserving: Essays on Preservationism and Paraconsistent Logic; University of Toronto Press: Toronto, ON, Canada, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Frege, G. Letter to Russell. In From Frege to Gödel. A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879–1931; van Heijenoort, J., Ed.; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1902; pp. 127–128. [Google Scholar]
- Frege, G. Philosophical and Mathematical Correspondence; Basil Blackwell: Oxford, UK, 1980; pp. 130–170. [Google Scholar]
- Woods, J. How paradox fares in inconsistency-robust logic and beyond: Computational and naturalized approaches. J. Appl. Log. 2021, 8, 2119–2172. [Google Scholar]
- Tarski, A. On the concept of following logically (trans. Magda Stroińska and David Hitchcock). Hist. Philos.Log. 2002, 23, 155–196. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Aristotle. The Complete Works of Aristotle. The Revised English Translation; Barnes, J., Ed.; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1984. [Google Scholar]
- Adams, R.; Shipp, S.; Friston, K. Predictions, not commands: Active infeeds in the motor system. Brain Struct. Funct. 2013, 218, 611–643. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Busemeyer, J.R.; Bruza, P.D. Quantum Cognition and Decision; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Gershman, S.; Vul, E.; Tanenbaum, J. Multistability and perceptive inference. Neural Comput. 2012, 24, 1–24. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Kirkhof, M.D.; Robertson, I. Enactivism and predictive Processing: A nonrepresentational view. Philos. Explor. 2018, 21, 264–281. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Park, W. Abduction in Context: The Conjectural Dynamics of Reasoning; Springer: Cham, Switzerland, 2019. [Google Scholar]
- Bruza, P.D.; Gibson, A. Abduction beyond representation. In Handbook of Abductive Cognition; Magnani, L., Ed.; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, (Forthcoming).
- Everett, D.L. How Language Began: The Story of Humanity’s Greatest Invention; Liveright Publishing: New York, NY, USA, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Russell, B. The Principles of Mathematics; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1903. [Google Scholar]
- Gabbay, D.M.; Woods, J. Agenda Relevance: A Study in Formal Pragmatics; Elsevier: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Morton, A. Bounded Thinking: Epistemic Virtues for Limited Agents; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Woods, J. Errors of Reasoning: Naturalizing the Logic of Inference; Studies in Logic; College Publications: London, UK, 2013; Volume 45. [Google Scholar]
- Haugeland, J. Artificial Intelligence: The Very Idea; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1985. [Google Scholar]
- Thagard, P. Bots and Beasts: What Makes Machines, Animals and People Smart? MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2021. [Google Scholar]
- Hinton, G.E.; McClelland, J.L.; Rumelhart, D.E. Distributed representations. In Parallel Distributed Processing: Exploring the Microstructure of Cognition; Rumelhart, D.E., McClelland, J.L., Eds.; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1986; pp. 77–109. [Google Scholar]
- Perconti, P.; Plebe, A. Deep learning and cognitive science. Cognition 2020, 203, 104365. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Rumelhart, D.E.; McClelland, J.L.; PDP Research Group. Parallel Distributed Processing: Explorations of the Microstructure of Cognition; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1986; Volume 2. [Google Scholar]
- Harman, G. Induction: A discussion of the relevance of Knowledge to the theory of induction. In Induction, Acceptance and Rational Belief; Swain, M., Ed.; Reidel: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 1970; pp. 83–99. [Google Scholar]
- Harman, G. Change in View: Principles of Reasoning; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1986. [Google Scholar]
- Woods, J. Epistemology mathematicised. Informal Log. 2013, 33, 292–331. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Cobb, M. The Idea of the Brain: The Past and Future of Neuroscience; Basic Books: London, UK, 2020. [Google Scholar]
- Mole, C. Mind the gaps. Times Lit. Suppl. 2021, 27, 6153. [Google Scholar]
- Fukushima, K. Neocognition: A self-organizing neural network model for a mechanism of pattern recognition unaffected by a shift in position. Biol. Cybern. 1980, 36, 93–202. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Gabbay, D.; Cramer, M.; Dauphin, J.; Farjami, A.; Rivlin, L.; van der Toore, L. Machine argumentation: Can we replace taxi drivers by robots? In Natural Arguments; Gabbay, D., Magnani, L., Park, W., Pietarinen, A.-V., Eds.; Tributes series; College Publications: London, UK, 2019; Volume 40, pp. 177–194. [Google Scholar]
- Doya, K.; Ishii, S.; Pouget, A.; Rajesh Rao, P.N. Bayesian Brain: Probabilistic Approaches to Neural Coding; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2007. [Google Scholar]
- Hohwy, J. The Predictive Mind; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Hooker, C.A. Handbook of the Philosophy of Science; Elsevier: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 2011; Volume 10. [Google Scholar]
- Magnani, L. Abduction, Reason and Science: Processes of Discovery and Explanation; Kluwer: Dordrecht, The Netherlands; Plenum: New York, NY, USA, 2001. [Google Scholar]
- Magnani, L. Abductive Cognition: The Epistemological and Eco-Cognitive Dimensions of Hypothetical Reasoning; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Magnani, L. Human abductive cognition vindicated: Computational locked strategies, dissipative brains, and eco-cognitive openness. Philosophies 2022, 7, 15. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Woods, J. How abduction fares in mathematical space. In Handbook of Abductive Cognition; Magnani, L., Ed.; Springer: Cham, Switzerland, 2022. [Google Scholar]
- Bruza, P.; Widdows, D.; Woods, J. A quantum logic of down below. In Handbook of Quantum Logic and Quantum Structures; Engesser, K., Gabbay, D., Lehman, D.L., Eds.; Elsevier: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 2009; Volume 2, pp. 625–660. [Google Scholar]
- Bruza, P.; Woods, J. Quantum collapse in semantic space: Interpreting natural language argumentation. In Proceedings of Quantum Integration 09; College Publications: London, UK, 2009; pp. 59–80. [Google Scholar]
- Vitiello, G. The dissipative brain. In Brain and Being: At the Boundary Between Science, Philosophy, Language and Arts; Globus, G., Pribram, K.H., Vitello, G., Eds.; John Benjamins: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 2012; pp. 317–338. [Google Scholar]
- Goodman, N. The new riddle of induction. In Fact, Fiction and Forecast; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1953; pp. 59–83. [Google Scholar]
- Lycan, W.G. On Evidence in Philosophy; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2019. [Google Scholar]
- Rawls, J. A Theory of Justice; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1971. [Google Scholar]
- Woods, J. The role of the common in cognitive prosperity: Our command of the unspeakable and the unwriteable. Log. Univers. 2021, 15, 399–443. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Grothendiek, A. Topological Vector Subspaces; Gordon and Breach: New York, NY, USA, 1973. [Google Scholar]
- Rescorla, M. Clark’s Surfing Uncertainty. Notre Dame Philos. Rev. 2017, 15, 1–10. [Google Scholar]
- Von Helmholtz, H. Handbuch der Physiologischen Optik; Voss: Leipzig, Germany, 1867. [Google Scholar]
- Arfini, S. Ignorant Cognition: A Philosophical Investigation of the Cognitive Features of Not-Knowing; Springer: Cham, Switzerland, 2019. [Google Scholar]
- Arfini, S.; Bertolotti, T. Self-knowledge and self-knowledge: Further cognitive implications of epistemic and other bubbles. In Natural Arguments: A Tribute to John Woods; Gabbay, D., Magnani, L., Park, W., Pietarinen, A.-V., Eds.; Tribute Series; College Publications: London, UK, 2019; Volume 40, pp. 665–692. [Google Scholar]
- Woods, J. Epistemic bubbles. In We Will Show Them! Essays in Honour of Dov Gabbay on his 60th Birthday; Artemov, S., Barringer, H., d’Avila Garcez, A., Lamb, L.C., Woods, J., Eds.; College Publications: London, UK, 2005; Volume 2, pp. 731–774. [Google Scholar]
- Cohen, L.J. An Essay on Belief and Acceptance; Clarendon Press: Oxford, UK, 1992. [Google Scholar]
- Walton, D.; Krabbe, E.C.W. Commitment in Dialogue; SUNY Press: Albany, NY, USA, 1995. [Google Scholar]
- Woods, J. Aristotle’s Earlier Logic; Hermes Science: Oxford, UK, 2001. [Google Scholar]
- Woods, J. Truth in Fiction: Rethinking its Logic; Springer: Cham, Switzerland, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Adriaans, P.; van Benthem, J. Philosophy of Information. In Handbook of the Philosophy of Science; Gabbay, D., Thagard, P., Woods, J., Eds.; Elsevier: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Attneave, F. Applications of Information Theory to Psychology: A Summary of Basic Concepts; Holt: New York, NY, USA, 1959. [Google Scholar]
- Cover, T.M.; Thomas, J.A. Elements of Information Theory; John Wiley & Sons: Hoboken, NJ, USA, 1991. [Google Scholar]
- Dretske, F. Epistemology and information. In Handbook of the Philosophy of Science, Volume 8. Philosophy of Information; Adriaans, P., van Benthem, J., Eds.; Elsevier: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 2008; pp. 29–47. [Google Scholar]
- Floridi, L. The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Computing and information; Blackwell: Oxford, UK, 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Floridi, L. Philosophy of information and information ethics: Critical reflections on the state of the art. Ethics Inf. Technol. 2008, 10, 89–96. [Google Scholar]
- Bar-Hillel, Y. Language and Information: Selected Essays on Their Theory and Application; Addison-Wesley: Reading, MA, USA, 1964. [Google Scholar]
- Dretske, F. Knowledge and the Flow of Information; MIT Press: Cambridge MA, USA, 1981. [Google Scholar]
- Hartley, R.V.L. Transmission of information. Bell Tech. J. 1928, 7, 535–563. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Shannon, C.E. A mathematical theory of communication. Bell Syst. Tech. J. 1948, 27, 379–423, 623–656. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Chaitin, G.J. Algorithmic Information Theory; Cambridge University Press: New York, NY, USA, 1987. [Google Scholar]
- Li, M.; Itánge, P. An Introduction to Kolmogorov Complexity and Its Applications; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 1997. [Google Scholar]
- Solomonoff, R.J. The discovery of algorithmic probability. J. Comput. Syst. Sci. 1997, 55, 73–88. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hintikka, J. Socratic Epistemology: Explorations of Knowledge-Seeking by Questioning; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2007. [Google Scholar]
- Hintikka, J. Abduction-inference, conjecture, or an answer to a question? In Socratic Epistemology: Explorations of Knowledge-Seeking by Questioning; Cambridge University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2007; pp. 38–60. [Google Scholar]
- Zimmerman, M. The nervous system and the context of information theory. In Human Physiology; Schmidt, R.F., Thews, G., Eds.; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 1989; pp. 166–175. [Google Scholar]
- Schiffrin, R.M. Automatism and consciousness. In Scientific Approaches to Consciousness; Cohen, J.D., Schooler, J.W., Eds.; Erlbaum: Mahwah, NJ, USA, 1997; pp. 49–64. [Google Scholar]
- Woods, J. Four grades of ignorance-involvement and how they nourish the cognitive economy. Synthese 2021, 198, 3339–3368. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Callen, H.B. Thermodynamics and an Introduction to Thermostatistics, 2nd ed.; Wiley: Hoboken, NJ, USA, 1985. [Google Scholar]
- Pelletier, F.J. (Ed.) Kinds, Things and Stuff; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Tappenden, J. Mathematical concepts: Fruitfulness and naturalness. In The Philosophy of Mathematics and Mathematical Practice; Mancosu, P., Ed.; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2008; pp. 276–301. [Google Scholar]
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2022 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Woods, J. Could a Computer Learn to Be an Appeals Court Judge? The Place of the Unspeakable and Unwriteable in All-Purpose Intelligent Systems. Philosophies 2022, 7, 95. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7050095
Woods J. Could a Computer Learn to Be an Appeals Court Judge? The Place of the Unspeakable and Unwriteable in All-Purpose Intelligent Systems. Philosophies. 2022; 7(5):95. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7050095
Chicago/Turabian StyleWoods, John. 2022. "Could a Computer Learn to Be an Appeals Court Judge? The Place of the Unspeakable and Unwriteable in All-Purpose Intelligent Systems" Philosophies 7, no. 5: 95. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7050095
APA StyleWoods, J. (2022). Could a Computer Learn to Be an Appeals Court Judge? The Place of the Unspeakable and Unwriteable in All-Purpose Intelligent Systems. Philosophies, 7(5), 95. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7050095