The Triage of “Blameworthy” Patients
Abstract
:1. Peter Singer: The Vaccinated First
Hospitals that are at or near capacity should warn the populations they serve that, after a certain date—far enough in the future to allow ample time for people to get fully vaccinated—they will give vaccinated patients priority over unvaccinated patients with COVID-19.
Hospitals with sufficient capacity should, of course, continue to treat unvaccinated patients with COVID-19 as best they can. Despite the extra strain this puts on hospital staff, everyone should have sufficient compassion to try to save lives, even when those whose lives need saving have made foolish, selfish choices.[1]
Exceptions should be made for those few patients for whom vaccination is contra-indicated on medical grounds, but not for those who claim to have religious grounds for exemption. No major religion rejects vaccination, and if some people choose to interpret their religious beliefs as requiring them to avoid vaccination, then they, and not others, should bear the consequences.[1]
2. Gino Strada: Children and Women First
Years ago, Margaret, our Australian head nurse in Kabul, took me by the arm. “Come, there are already a hundred or so wounded people in the courtyard, you must do the triage.”
Among them were many fighters, an unusual situation, and those fighters looked somewhat familiar to us. They had been keeping us and our hospital under fire for days, with no respect for the wounded or for those who, like us, were only there to provide aid. I felt a mix of fear and rage, I felt the weight of having worked for days in the midst of machine-gun and mortar fire.
Not even when I came face to face with a mujahedin with a bullet in his stomach, did I manage to overcome my rage. My mind was swarming with emotions and feelings, but there was no room for pity, which instead always ought to be there in a doctor’s head.
It was tough to admit it, but I cared nothing at all about those wounded guerrilla fighters who had been terrorising us for days.
“The triage is over, Margaret—I told her a few minutes after we had started moving through that crowd of people lying on the ground—children and women first!”
“Whaaat?”
“That’s right: children and women first. If you don’t like it, then ask someone else to do the triage.” I went back to the operating theatre without even waiting for an answer.
Over the following days, I often found myself thinking about this choice, which had not been based on medical ethics or on any rational approach to the problem.
It is true that children and women there were the only blameless people—they had been on the receiving end of the violence. Those who wage war, I had told myself, those who shoot to kill, must certainly take account of the possibility of getting a bullet in the stomach.
And why should I have given precedence to those who only half an hour earlier had been shooting at me?
It took me some time to find the strength to tell myself that, ultimately, that had only been a kind of revenge, the transformation of a doctor into a ruthless and immovable judge.
And it frightened me.
That choice had nothing to do with my profession. I have searched for excuses, but in the end the verdict has remained the same: what would we call this, being an accessory to mass murder and failing to assist?[3] (pp. 57–58)
3. Ronald Dworkin and the Distinction between “Option Luck” and “Brute Luck”
Option luck is a matter of how deliberate and calculated gambles turn out—whether someone gains or loses through accepting an isolated risk he or she should have anticipated and might have declined. Brute luck is a matter of how risks fall out that are not in that sense deliberate gambles […]. If someone develops cancer in the course of a normal life, and there is no particular decision to which we can point as a gamble risking the disease, then we will say that he has suffered brute bad luck. But if he smoked cigarettes heavily then we may prefer to say that he took an unsuccessful gamble.[7] (p. 293)
children and women there were the only blameless people—they had been on the receiving end of the violence. Those who wage war, I had told myself, those who shoot to kill, must certainly take account of the possibility of getting a bullet in the stomach.[5] (p. 58)
4. Arguments in Support of Clinical Criteria
Deciding that an individual under our care or control is a terrorist without the restraint of legal due process, and under the impression that someone is essentially a terrorist, our enemy as it were metaphysically, justifies undermining both medical ethics and the rule of law, and corrodes the decency and legitimacy of our society in a fundamental way.[9] (p. 52)
Of course, there are theories of punishment that rely on forfeiture of rights, but physicians are not supposed to be agents of punishment. Forfeiture of rights is not part of medical ethics.[12] (p. 57)
Even if we accept the claim that, in effect, terrorists are simply criminals who have committed very serious crimes, they would nonetheless be entitled to the same medical treatment as others who commit serious crimes.[12] (p. 57)
Is it the unstated assumption that terrorists do not deserve good medical treatment because they are neither soldiers nor civilians but a sort of vermin or a crazed beast? I hope not. Dehumanizing one’s enemy is, of course, a long first step toward committing atrocities. (…) Terrorists are not in a class by themselves.[12] (p. 57)
The opt-out rule applies to procedures, not to the person on whom those procedures are performed. For as long as there is no moral objection to be had to treating burns, bullet wounds or whatever—and no one in their right mind would think that there is—then the identity of the person burned or shot is neither here nor there. There is no right not to perform permissible procedures on people of whom we disapprove.[13] (p. 60)
5. Illness and Blame
6. Are the Sick Really to Be Held Responsible?
If we attribute responsibility solely based on the health outcome, it is not possible to discriminate between these two categories of patients, or to make a distinction between the decision to take a health-related risk and the actual bad luck of seeing that risk materialized.[25] (p. 177)
Medical professionals choose a lifestyle that puts them at risk of catching infectious diseases, but few would deny them proper care on the grounds that they should be held responsible for thus becoming ill. We consider unhealthy work that benefits others such as masonry, pregnancy, or high risk sports (such as boxing or hockey playing) to be praiseworthy rather than a reason for liability or even worthy of punishment.[25] (p. 186)
7. Aristotle and the Concept of Epiékeia (Equity)
the sort of justice which goes beyond the written law. Its existence partly is and partly is not intended by legislators; not intended, where they have noticed no defect in the law; intended, where they find themselves unable to define things exactly, and are obliged to legislate universally where matters hold only for the most part; or where it is not easy to be complete owing to the endless possible cases presented.[30] (p. 2188 [1374a18–1374b23])
8. Conclusions
- Doctors are not judges: it is not their job to judge people, nor do they have the competencies to do so. Moreover, the judge’s role is hardly compatible with the tasks and duties that medical ethics assigns to doctors, starting from the duty to treat all patients who need help, regardless of their personal characteristics. If a doctor were to act as a judge, this would also jeopardise the relationship of trust between the doctor and his/her patients [34].
- 2.
- While it is unfair to punish patients by denying them medical care or postponing their treatment, it is possible to take certain measures to modify or discourage specific choices and lifestyles that can be hazardous to oneself and other people. In the case of vaccines, it is certainly possible—and indeed useful—to impose a range of limitations on the unvaccinated. This is a way to discourage a “lifestyle choice”, not to punish a “state of affairs”. It is certainly useful to provide in-depth and correct information to people who do not want to get vaccinated, so as to encourage a choice that is good for individuals and the people around them.
- 3.
- Finally, rules are important, and it is necessary to follow them. They also increase trust among the patients, who know they will be treated fairly through the general application of rules. Nevertheless, applying the rules in the real world, in situations one could not have foreseen, is not so easy. In the sixth book of Nicomachean Ethics [35], Aristotle introduces another important notion in this regard, namely that of phronesis (prudence or practical wisdom), which concerns particulars, as it has to do with how one must act in particular situations. But, as Aristotle observes, phronesis requires experience and training. Consequently, in order to ensure that the triage rules are applied well, it is necessary for all the persons involved, starting from the doctors, to be adequately trained to deal with these particular situations.
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | By “triage conducted on the basis of strictly clinical criteria” I mean that described by the World Health Organization as follows: “Patients must be split into groups based on the seriousness of their injuries and decisions must be made about the treatments they can be given according to the resources available and their chances of survival” [2] (p. 14) [3]. |
2 | Edward Luttwack has stated: “Strada is the man who was running the hospital in Afghanistan and was proud to be treating the Taliban, who would then leave the hospital to kill again. I do not have his moral standing: for him it’s all the same—the Islamic State is the same as the Swedish Red Cross. For him there are no terrorists. Under communism they used to call people like him useful idiots. Islam takes no notice of Gino Strada, but they would call him a useful idiot, a technical term. Useful to the terrorists”. My own translation. [4]. |
3 | For example, his injuries might be only slightly more severe (an almost imperceptible or almost insignificant difference, but one that is nevertheless real). |
4 | Among the many possible cases that one might mention, that of Nelson Mandela comes to mind. In a 1987 interview, Margaret Thatcher referred to the African National Congress (ANC) as “a typical terrorist organisation”. Up until 2008 Mandela and other ANC leaders were on the US’s terrorist watchlist. |
5 | I prefer to leave the Greek term epiékeia alongside the English “equity”, to distinguish the Aristotelian meaning of equity from the prevailing moral meaning of “equity”, which is quite different and influenced by John Rawls’ thought [28]. Rawls refers to equity as fairness and distinguishes it from equality: fairness, unlike equality, admits whatever degree of inequality might serve as a means to increase the welfare of society’s least advantaged members. In this sense, unlike equality (where each individual or group of people is given the same resources or opportunities), equity recognizes that each person finds themselves different circumstances and allocates the resources and opportunities needed to reach an equal outcome. |
6 | Here I am referring to so-called “reasonable people” in general. In this same special issue, however, there is an interesting article [33], to which I shall refer, in which the pros and cons of entrusting the decision to the treating physicians, to an ethics consultant, or to an ethics committee are examined in more detail. |
References
- Singer, P. Victims of the Unvaccinated; Project Syndicate: Prague, Czech, 2022; Available online: https://www.project-syndicate.org/commentary/health-care-priority-for-vaccinated-covid19-patients-by-peter-singer-2022-01 (accessed on 27 July 2022).
- World Health Organization. Emergency Situations Working Group—Transmissible diseases: Surveillance and action, WHO Americas Regional Office, WHO office in Haiti. In Évaluation des Risques Pour la Santé Publique et Interventions. Séisme: Haïti. 2010. Available online: https://apps.who.int/iris/handle/10665/70222 (accessed on 8 August 2022).
- Pan American Health Organization. Pan American Sanitary Bureau, Regional Office of the World Health Organization. In Establishing a Mass Casualty Management System; Pan American Health Organization: Washington, DC, USA, 1995; Available online: https://www.eird.org/isdr-biblio/PDF/Establishing%20a%20mass%20casualty.pdf (accessed on 8 August 2022).
- Attentati Bruxelles: Luttwak, Bombardiamo Molenbeek, Risparmiamo Denaro. Gino Strada Utile Idiota. Il Fatto Quotidiano 25 March 2016. Available online: https://www.ilfattoquotidiano.it/2016/03/25/attentati-bruxelles-luttwak-bombardiamo-molenbeek-risparmiamo-denaro-gino-strada-utile-idiota/499402/ (accessed on 27 July 2022).
- Strada, G. Pappagalli Verdi. Cronache di un Chirurgo di Guerra; Feltrinelli: Milan, Italy, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Semplici, S. Ethics in Emergency Times: The Case of COVID-19. Philosophies 2022, 7, 70. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dworkin, R. What is equality? Part 2: Equality of resources. Philos. Public Aff. 1981, 10, 283–345. [Google Scholar]
- Cohen, G.A. Luck and equality. A reply to Hurley. Philos. Phenomenol. Res. 2006, 72, 439–446. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ashcroft, R. The Psychology of Repugnance and the Duty to Trust. Am. J. Bioeth. 2009, 9, 51–52. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Agamben, G. State of Exception; University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 2005. [Google Scholar]
- Schmitt, C. Political Theology: Four Chapters on the Concept of Sovereignty; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1986. [Google Scholar]
- Davis, M. Terrorists are Just Patients. Am. J. Bioeth. 2009, 9, 56–57. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Brassington, I. Separating the “Rights Of” and “Justice For” Bombers. Am. J. Bioeth. 2009, 9, 59–61. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Beecher, H.K. Scarce Resources and Medical Advancement. Daedalus 1969, 98, 275–313. [Google Scholar] [PubMed]
- Underwood, M.J.; Bailey, J.S. Coronary bypass surgery should not be offered to smokers. Br. Med. J. 1993, 306, 1047–1049. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Moss, A.H.; Siegler, M. Should alcoholics compete equally for liver transplantation? JAMA 1991, 265, 1295–1298. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Sharkey, K.; Gillam, L. Should patients with self-inflicted illness receive lower priority in access to healthcare resources? Mapping out the debate. J. Med. Ethics 2010, 36, 661–665. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Delumeau, J. La Peur en Occident; Fayard: Paris, France, 1978. [Google Scholar]
- Delumeau, J. Le Péché Et La Peur. La Culpabilisation En Occident; Fayard: Paris, France, 1983. [Google Scholar]
- Sontag, S. Illness as Metaphor; Farrar, Straus & Giroux: New York, NY, USA, 1978. [Google Scholar]
- Kanner, L. Autistic disturbances of affective contact. Nerv. Child 1943, 2, 217–250. [Google Scholar]
- Kanner, L. Problems of nosology and psychodynamics of early infantile autism. Am. J. Orthopsychiatr. 1949, 19, 416–426. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Spinsanti, S. Malato? Colpevole! Janus 2006, 22, 5. [Google Scholar]
- Butler, S. Erewhon, or, Over the Range; Trübner & Co.: London, UK, 1872. [Google Scholar]
- Clavien, C.; Hurst, S. The Undeserving Sick? An Evaluation of Patients’ Responsibility for Their Health Condition. Camb. Q. Healthc. Ethics 2020, 29, 175–191. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Hosseinpoor, A.R.; Stewart Williams, J.A.; Itani, L.; Chatterji, S. Socioeconomic inequality in domains of health: Results from the World Health Surveys. BMC Public Health 2012, 12, 198. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Mulder, L.B.; Rupp, D.E.; Dijkstra, A. Making snacking less sinful: (counter-) moralising obesity in the public discourse differentially affects food choices of individuals with high and low perceived body mass. Psychol. Health 2015, 30, 233–251. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Rawls, J. A Theory of Justice; Belknap: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1999. [Google Scholar]
- Turoldo, F. On Moral Nose. In Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethic; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, in press.
- Aristotle. Rhetoric. In Aristotle, The Complete Works; Barnes, J., Ed.; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1984. [Google Scholar]
- Harris, J. The Value of Life; Routledge: London, UK, 1985. [Google Scholar]
- Ricoeur, P. The Just; The University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 2000. [Google Scholar]
- Battisti, D.; Picozzi, M. Deciding the Criteria Is Not Enough: Moral Issues to Consider for a Fair Allocation of Scarce ICU Resources. Philosophies 2002, 7, 92. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hansson, S.O. The ethics of making patients responsible. Camb. Q. Healthc. Ethics 2018, 27, 87–92. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Aristotle. Nicomachean Ethics; Hackett: Indianapolis, IN, USA, 2019. [Google Scholar]
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2022 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Turoldo, F. The Triage of “Blameworthy” Patients. Philosophies 2022, 7, 99. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7050099
Turoldo F. The Triage of “Blameworthy” Patients. Philosophies. 2022; 7(5):99. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7050099
Chicago/Turabian StyleTuroldo, Fabrizio. 2022. "The Triage of “Blameworthy” Patients" Philosophies 7, no. 5: 99. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7050099
APA StyleTuroldo, F. (2022). The Triage of “Blameworthy” Patients. Philosophies, 7(5), 99. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies7050099