The Paradox of Fictional Creatures
Abstract
:1. Creationism in the Philosophy of Fiction
Who created Frankenstein’s monster? One answer, from the internal perspective, is of course: Frankenstein. Only from the external point of view must the reply be: Mary Shelley.
- (1)
- Victor Frankenstein created Frankenstein’s monster. [True in the fiction]
- (2)
- Mary Shelley created Frankenstein’s monster. [True simpliciter]
- (3)
- Some characters in novels are closely modelled on actual people, while others are wholly products of the literary imagination, and it is usually impossible to tell which characters fall into which of these categories via textual analysis alone [26] (p. 302).
- (4)
- When authors create fictional characters, they present them with more or less physical detail, but in the 19th century, there were authors who presented some of the characters they created with a greater wealth of physical detail than characters in any 18th-century novel [14] (p. 207).
- (5)
- Austen might have made her character Emma less attractive by giving her a worse temper [24] (p. 195).
- (6)
- Sherlock Holmes is a fictional character created by Conan Doyle. He first appeared in print in 1887, in A Study in Scarlet [3] (p. 26).
2. The Paradox
2.1. Terminology
- (i)
- There are two cups on the table.
- (ii)
- If there are n Ks, then the number of Ks is n.
- (iii)
- The number of cups on the table is two.
- (iv)
- There is a number.
2.2. The Paradox of Fictional Creatures
- (7)
- Mary Shelley created FM.
- (8)
- FM is a (purely) fictional character.
- (9)
- FM does not (really) exist.
- (A)
- (7) ⇛ (8);
- (B)
- (8) ⇛ (9);
- (C)
- (7) ⇛ non-(9).
- Suppose (7) is true.
- Then, by (A) and (B), so is (9).
- Then, by (C), the negation of (9) is true.
- So, (9) is both true and false.
- Contradiction.
2.3. Truths about Fictional Characters
- (10)
- J.K. Rowling created FM.
- (11)
- Stacie Friend does not (really) exist.
2.4. Linking Principles
- Author X created Y.
- Therefore, Y is (purely) fictional.
“Jane Austen wrote a book pretending to use the name ‘Emma’ to refer to a woman and describe various things she did (where Austen was not referring back to any real person or prior character)” and “Emma is a fictional character in a book by Jane Austen” are redundant: any competent speaker who knows the truth of the first is, according to the standard rules of use for our noun term “fictional character”, entitled to infer the second; nothing more, no further investigation, is required.
- X is (purely) fictional.
- Therefore, X does not (really) exist.
I would have thought that, in so far as there were any conceptual truths associated with our concept of a fictional character, or linguistic truths associated with the expression “fictional character”, these would surely include the fact that fictional characters do not exist […]. After all, ordinary people seem quite happy to move from the claim that x is a fictional character to the claim that x doesn’t exist. We talk and think as-if being a fictional character precludes that thing’s existence and indeed explains or entails its nonexistence. We naturally say such things as “Emma doesn’t exist but is only a fictional character”, “Sadly, since Holmes is a fictional character he doesn’t exist”, “You are in love with Anna Karenina, so you are in love with a mere fictional character, something that doesn’t exist”, “Fictional characters exist in stories, not the real world”, and so on. We would certainly find it bizarre if someone, upon being told that Holmes is a fictional character, asserted that Holmes exists.
- -
- So seeing as he came up with a lot of crime scene techniques isn’t he a bit of a genius? Or did he research new techniques before writing the book?
- -
- Do you mean Arthur Conan Doyle? Because Sherlock Holmes wasn’t a real person and he certainly didn’t write his own books! […] Raccooneyes55 21:17, 2 August 2011 (UTC)
- -
- Raccooneyes55, with all respect, the assertion that Holmes was a fiction is debatable; There are many good arguments made both for Holmes as a real person poorly hidden, and for Holmes as a fiction. His existence as a fictional character ONLY is far from provable. […] 96.54.72.207 02:24, 14 August 2011 (UTC)
- (Author) X created Y.
- Therefore, Y exists.
It is an undeniable conceptual, indeed (I dare say) analytic, truth that for any x, if x is created, x comes to existence. To create something is to bring it into existence13.
3. The Logical Space of Solutions
3.1. Structural Remarks
- α
- Deny (7): It is not the case that Mary Shelley created FM.
- β
- Deny (8): It is not the case that FM is a fictional character.
- γ
- Deny (9) and (B): FM really exists, and “being fictional” is not a way of “characterising nonexistence”.
- δ
- Deny (C): To create does not mean to bring into existence.
3.2. Inveterate Anti-Realism
We will engage in an extended pretense in which we pretend that our domain of discourse contains all those entities which occur within some fiction and that those entities are as they are characterized by that fiction. So if some fiction involves our pretending that there is some entity i or plurality of entities p, the extended pretense will also involve our pretending that there is the entity i or the plurality of entities p. And if some fiction characterizes x as being F then x will count as being F within this extended pretense. Within this extended pretense, those entities which genuinely exist will count as having the property of being real and those which do not will count as having the property of being fictional17 [47].
3.3. Neo-Meinongianism
I have said that, in a popular sense, an author creates characters, but this […] is hard to analyse. It does not mean, for example, that the author brings those characters into existence, for they do not exist. Nor does he or she makes them objects, for they were objects before they appeared in stories.
[W]hen Doyle coined the name “Holmes” he gave it to a non-existent object, picked out as an object which was a detective with acute powers of observation and inference, etc., in the worlds that realised the story he wished to tell. This was achieved with an act of mental pointing; and, realistically conceived, the object was available to be pointed at. But how does the pointing work? How does the act pick out one of the enormous number of non-existent objects? In many worlds there are objects—different objects—which are detectives with acute powers of observation and inference, etc. How does the act pick out one of these? […] I do not, myself, find a problem with a notion of mental pointing that can do this, any more than I find a problem with a notion of physical pointing that selects an object at random. (Close your eyes and point to someone in a crowd.)
3.4. Artefactualists and Anti-Creationists
It is surely possible, for example, for two composers independently and at different times to create exactly the same melody. If creating a melody entails bringing it into existence, we are hard pressed to explain how the composer composing at the later time could have created anything. The statement that X is caused to exist at t entails that, during some interval immediately prior to t, X does not exist. If t is the time at which the later composer creates the melody, we have no reason to suppose that such an interval exists.
4. Bringing a New Solution into Existence
4.1. An Analysis of Creation
- (12)
- [?] Leonardo da Vinci created the helicopter, i.e., the “aerial screw”, in the 1480s.
- (13)
- [?] Juan de la Cierva created the helicopter, i.e., the “autogyro”, in the 1920s.
4.2. Last Word with the Artefactualist
5. Conclusions: Solving the Paradox
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
1 | There are alternative terminologies corresponding to the same distinction. For instance, Gregory Currie distinguishes between “fictive” and “transfictive” statements [4]; Andrea Bonomi distinguishes between “textual” and “metatextual” statements [5]. This distinction between fictional and metafictional statements is not taken to be exhaustive, as all authors usually single out parafictional (or paratuxtual) statements, as well as many other mixed-perspective statements. I ignore these more fined-grained distinctions for they do not affect the rest of this paper. For a recent overview of the different problems surrounding the different uses of fictional names, see [6]. |
2 | However, as will be seen below, the problem I want to investigate helps to distinguish between competing theories on the existence and nature of individuals of paper, viz., neo-meinongianism and artefactualism on the realist side, and fictionalism and anti-creationsim on the anti-realist side. “Flesh-and-blood individuals” comes from [3]. “Individuals of paper” is a tribute to Salvador Plascencia’s 2005 metafiction entitled The People of Paper. |
3 | See [9] for a very influential defence of creationism in general, later called “artefactualism”. See [10] for a useful distinction between “radical creationism” and “moderate creationism” (and an argument in favour of the latter): more on this below. See [11] for a recent book-length defence of creationism based on an institutional theory of fiction. The debate over fictional creationism has grown to be considerably large by now; some influential, fairly recent contributions include [12,13,14,15,16,17,18,19,20,21]. |
4 | |
5 | This re-framing of the creationism debate involves a focus on fictional names and avoids quantificational talk. Creationism is sometimes advertised using talk such as “There are fictional characters and these are created entities”. I think we can narrow down the problem on existence and reference, leaving quantification aside, without trouble, though. Additionally, the theory of quantification over nonexistents brings forth orthogonal technical questions. In the same vein, nothing I argue in this paper hinges on fine-grained distinctions about fictional terms, viz., between fictional names and fictional definite descriptions. I will thus also leave this distinction on the side. |
6 | |
7 | The arrow suggests itself for symbolising an entailment relation. I take this triple arrow so as to not prejudice any notion of entailment and go along with Thomasson on whatever suits best. In other words, nothing hinges on this notation. |
8 | For a seminal paper on this problem, see [40]. |
9 | “Really” should not be interpreted as “physically”, because realists typically hold that fictional characters really exist, i.e., exist in the real world, while being abstract. I am following the usage from the literature that “to exist” can be used for both concrete and abstract entities and means something like “being part of the real world” across the board. Thanks to Hannah Kim for pressing me on this point. |
10 | For the record, she is rephrasing and agreeing with Schiffer [41] here, who is another important creationist figure. |
11 | Note that this is not the only way of “characterising nonexistence”. Kroon considers many other cases, including the much commented upon example of an “imaginary friend”; saying of an entity that it is an imaginary friend is to contrast it with real friends by emphasising its nonexistence. The fact that “fictional” is a nonexistence entailing predicates (among others) has been explicitly held in many places. In [20] (p. 169), (B) is taken to be a “devastatingly simple” objection to creationism, and it is explicitly endorsed: “Unlike you and me, Mrs Gamp is a fictional individual. To say this entails that Mrs. Gamp does not exist. Fictionality of a thing entails its non-existence”. He then addresses the “two standard creationist replies” based on paraphrase. Artefactualists have since come up with other more elaborate replies; I argue against them in the last section. My position can thus be seen as an update on Yagisawa’s final argument. |
12 | The discussion is archived here: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Talk:Sherlock_Holmes/Archive_2#Genius accessed on 11 September 2023. |
13 | His emphasis. Later on, he writes the following: “We should be careful enough to distinguish creativity from creation. The creativity with which an author describes a fictional character need not consist in her bringing the character into existence. It may instead consists in an unusually imaginative manner in which she writes a story”. My defence of the naïve analysis of creation below can be seen as going in this suggested direction. |
14 | This is why I put (Author) in brackets, for (C) relies on intuitions about a general theory of creation. I am following usage here in not making a difference between authorial and non-authorial creation. As the opening quote shows (and other “creationist locutions”), literary authors are typically thought of as being full-fledged creators. My solution below will consist in challenging this, and downgrade authors to mere inventors, so to say. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for pushing me to clarify this. |
15 | These can obviously be combined, but that would be redundant. |
16 | |
17 | Along the same lines in [47] (p. 9), Brock argues that, despite appearances, (8)’s logical form is something like the following: “According to the realist’s hypothesis, FM is a fictional character.” |
18 | Granted that fictional characters not only enjoy a special relationship with their authors (the creative relationship), but also with the consumers of the fiction who imagine them, it has to be acknowledged that the interactions between authors and their reading community is very complex. The author does not enjoy unbound authority; there is an uptake mechanism at play for fictional characters, contrary to mere (im)possibilia. The disanalogy thus re-appears on the consumer’s side; fan-fictions are always possible, whereas there is no fan-(im)possibilia. Though perhaps the literature on neo-meinongianism could be seen as a philosophical fan-fiction based on the Gegenstandstheorie! (For a similar joke, see [50]—which contains mostly serious contributions apart from the title.) |
19 | |
20 | There are alternative terminologies: “to invent” can be thought of as synonymous with “to plan”, “to thought up”, “to make up” and “to imagine”, while “to realise” can be thought of as synonymous with “to make it the case that”, “to bring into existence” and “to produce”. |
21 | Arguably, the Australian aboriginal notion of “Dreamtime”, according to which, roughly, the world we live in is that of a God’s dream, is a myth of the origin based on mere invention, and not full-fledged creation. Interestingly, there is a debate in anthropology about the correct translation of the original term “alcheringa”, which is due to the interpretation of the distinction between linear and cyclic time that is crucial to the aboriginal culture, and which has consequences for what creation amounts to. Swain [55] thus proposes the word “uncreated” as a candidate: ‘Dreamtime’ or ‘Dreaming’, as T.G.H. Strehlow has noted, emerged with a mistranslation of the altjira root, which has the meaning of ‘eternal, uncreated, springing out of itself’. Altjira rama, literally ‘to see the eternal’, is the evocative description for human sleep-dreams, but the so-called ‘Dreaming’ is derived from Altjiringa ngambakala: ‘that which derives from altjira’. Strehlow grasps at ‘having originated out of its own eternity’ as the closest possible English equivalent. |
22 | So, I predict that the opening example is really a piece of (great) rhetoric, and not decisive linguistic data. Moreover, Lamarque and Olsen’s zeugma, which is based on the proximity of the English words “to create” and “to invent”, does not translate so well. Italian, French and German speakers concur in saying that it sounds odd to use a literal translation of “to create” to describe the special relationship that is held between an author and a fictional character, though it is completely idiomatic in English. |
23 | The analogy between God and the author is a commonplace in the literature from the 19th century. See, in particular, Flaubert’s famous letter to Louise Colet, where he wrote the following in 1852: “in his work, the artist must be like God in the universe: everywhere present but nowhere to be seen.” |
24 | Remember, what Mary Shelley is supposed to have created is distinct and different from the human-like monster that Victor Frankenstein has created. She is supposed to have created an abstract artefact (or a type, for the type theorist), which has a place in the history of the literature, and is indeed akin to Leonardo’s invention. A proper analysis of the difference between Leonardo’s and Shelley’s creative processes would require a full-fledged analysis of fiction making, which greatly exceeds the scope of this paper. For the record, and in line with the anti-realist line of my argument, I think the promising starting point is an analysis of make-believe as presented in [25] and developed as Everett’s [24] “pretence semantics”. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for pressing me to make this more explicit. |
25 | I concur with Voltolini’s [10] (p. 292) terminological remark that “artefact” is not a good word for this new version of creationism championed by Abell, Terrone and Voltolini, because the analogy with manufactured goods is utterly misleading. I stick to the label for historical reasons, and for lack of a better term, provided this present caveat. For a misleading analogy between inventing a fictional character and carpentry, see [56]. |
26 | I think the same point is put forward in [57] (p. 364), when disagreeing with Thomasson’s defence of principle (C) as expressing an analytic truth. I am unsure whether Connolly would go for (B) over (C); he explicitly asserts that his account is anti-realist (denying the existence of fictional characters), while at the same time, in several places, talks about the existence of “characterisations”. Depending on whether he identifies “characterisations” with types, my argument would apply against his view. |
27 | Especially if we focus on (repeatable) works of art like novels, plays, pieces of music, etc. See [59] for an apt and influential defence of this view. |
28 | Note that, in line with Kroon [42] as noted above, there are other ways of being nonexistent for a language (and other types). Note that languages can fail to exist for non-fictional reasons. For instance, take a language in which the rules for negation are linear (e.g., to negate a sentence, place the negation word in the second position of the linear order). It is an empirical fact that there is no such language. Moreover, syntacticians have argued for the stronger claim that on the basis of the hierarchical structure of all languages, such a language could not exist. Such a language was “invented” by linguists, or rather stipulated in the course of a reductio argument, which is another typical way of “characterising nonexistence”. |
References
- Lamarque, P.; Stein, H.O. Truth, Fiction, and Literature: A Philosophical Perspective; Clarendon Library of Logic and Philosophy; Clarendon Press: Oxford, UK, 1994. [Google Scholar]
- Friend, S. The real foundation of fictional worlds. Australas. J. Philos. 2017, 95, 29–42. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Recanati, F. II—Fictional, Metafictional, Parafictional. In Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2018; Volume 118, pp. 25–54. [Google Scholar]
- Currie, G. The Nature of Fiction; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1990. [Google Scholar]
- Bonomi, A. Fictional context. In Perspectives on Context; CSLI Publications: Stanford, CA, USA, 2008; pp. 213–248. [Google Scholar]
- García-Carpintero, M. ‘Truth in Fiction’ Reprised. Br. J. Aesthet. 2022, 62, 307–324. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Deutsch, H. The creation problem. Topoi 1991, 10, 209–225. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lihoreau, F. (Ed.) Truth in Fiction; De Gruyter: Berlin, Germany, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Thomasson, A.L. Fiction and Metaphysics; Cambridge Studies in Philosophy; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1999. [Google Scholar]
- Voltolini, A. How to Vindicate (Fictional) Creationism. In Abstract Objects: For and Against; Springer: Cham, Switzerland, 2020; pp. 277–294. [Google Scholar]
- Abell, C. Fiction: A Philosophical Analysis; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2020. [Google Scholar]
- Brock, S. A Recalcitrant Problem for Abstract Creationism. J. Aesthet. Art Crit. 2018, 76, 93–98. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Goodman, J. Creatures of fiction, objects of myth. Analysis 2014, 74, 35–40. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kroon, F. The fiction of creationism. In Truth in Fiction; Franck, L., Ed.; De Gruyter: Berlin, Germany, 2010; pp. 203–222. [Google Scholar]
- Kroon, F. The social character of fictional entities. In From Fictionalism to Realism; Carola, B., Maurizio, F., Alberto, V., Eds.; Cambridge Scholars Publishing: Newcastle upon Tyne, UK, 2013; pp. 87–110. [Google Scholar]
- Kroon, F. Creationism and the problem of indiscernible fictional objects. In Fictional Objects; Stuart, B., Anthony, E., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Voltolini, A. The Seven Consequences of Creationism. Metaphysica 2009, 10, 27–48. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Voltolini, A. How Creationism Supports for Kripke’s Vichianism on Fiction. In Truth in Fiction; Franck, L., Ed.; De Gruyter: Berlin, Germany, 2010; pp. 38–93. [Google Scholar]
- Voltolini, A. A Suitable Metaphysics for Fictional Entities. In Fictional Objects; Stuart, B., Anthony, E., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2015; pp. 129–146. [Google Scholar]
- Yagisawa, T. Against Creationism in Fiction. Noûs 2001, 35, 153–172. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Zvolenszky, Z. An Argument for Authorial Creation. Organon F 2015, 22, 461–487. [Google Scholar]
- Parsons, T. Nonexistent Objects; Yale University Press: New Haven, CT, USA, 1980. [Google Scholar]
- Priest, G. Creating non-existents. In Truth in Fiction; De Gruyter: Berlin, Germany, 2010; pp. 107–118. [Google Scholar]
- Everett, A. The Nonexistent; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Walton, K. Mimesis as Make-Believe: On the Foundations of the Representational Arts; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1990. [Google Scholar]
- Van Inwagen, P. Creatures of fiction. Am. Philos. Q. 1977, 14, 299–308. [Google Scholar]
- Kripke, S. Reference and Existence: The John Locke Lectures; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Van Inwagen, P. Existence, ontological commitment, and fictional entities. In The Oxford Handbook of Metaphysics; Michael, J.L., Dean, W.Z., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Thomasson, A.L. Fictional characters and literary practices. Br. J. Aesthet. 2003, 43, 138–157. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rouillé, L. Anti-Realism about Fictional Names at Work: A New Theory for Metafictional Sentences. Organon F 2021, 28, 223–252. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Recanati, F. Fictional reference as simulation. In Language of Fiction; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2021; pp. 17–36. [Google Scholar]
- Yablo, S. Carnap’s Paradox and Easy Ontology. J. Philos. 2014, 111, 470–501. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Thomasson, A.L. Fictional Discourse and Fictionalisms. In Fictional Objects; Stuart, B., Anthony, E., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2015; pp. 255–274. [Google Scholar]
- Thomasson, A.L. Ontology Made Easy; OUP: New York, NY, USA, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- Quine, W.V.O. On What There Is. In The Pragmatism Reader: From Peirce Through the Present; Robert, B.T., Scott, F.A., Eds.; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1948; pp. 221–233. [Google Scholar]
- Carnap, R. Empiricism, Semantics and Ontology. Rev. Int. Philos. 1950, 4, 20–40. [Google Scholar]
- Thomasson, A.L. Norms and Necessity; OUP: New York, NY, USA, 2020. [Google Scholar]
- Rayo, A. Ontological commitment. Philos. Compass 2007, 2, 428–444. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Peacock, H. Two kinds of ontological commitment. Philos. Q. 2011, 61, 79–104. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Friend, S. Real People in Unreal Contexts: Or Is There a Spy Among Us? In Empty Names, Fiction and the Puzzles of Non-Existence; Anthony, E., Thomas, H., Eds.; CSLI Publications: Stanford, CA, USA, 2000; pp. 183–203. [Google Scholar]
- Schiffer, S. Language-created language-independent entities. Philos. Top. 1996, 24, 149–167. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kroon, F. Characterizing Non-existents. Grazer Philos. Stud. 1996, 51, 163–193. [Google Scholar]
- Berto, F. Impossible worlds and the logic of imagination. Erkenntnis 2017, 82, 1277–1297. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Priest, G. Sylvan’s Box: A Short Story and Ten Morals. Notre Dame J. Form. Log. 1997, 38, 573–582. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Priest, G. In Contradiction, 2nd ed.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2006. [Google Scholar]
- Evans, G. The Varieties of Reference; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 1982. [Google Scholar]
- Brock, S. Fictionalism about fictional characters. Noûs 2002, 36, 1–21. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Zalta, E.N. Abstract Objects: An Introduction to Axiomatic Metaphysics; D. Reidel: Dordrecht, The Netherland, 1983. [Google Scholar]
- Sainsbury, R.M. Fiction and Fictionalism; Routledge: London, UK, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Kroon, F.W. Was meinong only pretending? Philos. Phenomenol. Res. 1992, 52, 499–527. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Searle, J.R. The Logical Status of Fictional Discourse. New Lit. Hist. 1975, 6, 319–332. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Salmon, N. Nonexistence. Noûs 1998, 32, 277–319. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Terrone, E. On Fictional Characters as Types. Br. J. Aesthet. 2017, 57, 161–176. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Walters, L. Fictional Objects. Br. J. Aesthet. 2017, 57, 103–106. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Swain, T. A Place for Strangers: Towards a History of Australian Aboriginal Being; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1993. [Google Scholar]
- Fine, K. The problem of non-existents. Topoi 1982, 1, 97–140. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Connolly, N. Fictional Characters and Characterisations. Pacific Philos. Q. 2022, 104, 348–367. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lamarque, P. Works and Objects: Explorations in the Metaphysics of Art; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Walters, L. Repeatable Artworks as Created Types. Br. J. Aesthet. 2012, 53, 461–477. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2023 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Rouillé, L. The Paradox of Fictional Creatures. Philosophies 2023, 8, 92. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies8050092
Rouillé L. The Paradox of Fictional Creatures. Philosophies. 2023; 8(5):92. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies8050092
Chicago/Turabian StyleRouillé, Louis. 2023. "The Paradox of Fictional Creatures" Philosophies 8, no. 5: 92. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies8050092