A Note on Health Insurance under Ex Post Moral Hazard
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Optimal Coinsurance Under Ex Post Moral Hazard
3. A Computable Example
4. Conclusions
Conflicts of Interest
References
- J. Mossin. “Aspects of rational insurance purchasing.” J. Polit. Econ. 76 (1968): 533–568. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- K.J. Arrow. “Uncertainty and the welfare economics of medical care.” Am. Econ. Rev. 53 (1963): 941–973. [Google Scholar]
- M. Pauly. “The economics of moral hazard: Comment.” Am. Econ. Rev. 58 (1968): 531–537. [Google Scholar]
- R. Zeckhauser. “Medical insurance: A case study of the tradeoff between risk spreading and appropriate incentives.” J. Econ. Theory 2 (1970): 10–26. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- M. Feldstein. “The welfare loss of excess health insurance.” J. Polit. Econ. 81 (1973): 251–280. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- K.J. Arrow. “Welfare analysis of changes in health co-insurance rates.” In The Role of Health Insurance in the Health Services Sector. Edited by R. Rosett. New York, NY, USA: NBER, 1976, pp. 3–23. [Google Scholar]
- R. Feldman, and B. Dowd. “A new estimate of the welfare loss of excess health insurance.” Am. Econ. Rev. 81 (1991): 297–301. [Google Scholar] [PubMed]
- R.L. Keeney. “Utility functions for multiattributed consequences.” Manag. Sci. 18 (1972): 276–287. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- S.F. Richard. “Multivariate risk aversion, utility dependence and seprable utility functions.” Manag. Sci. 22 (1975): 12–21. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- S. Andersen, G.W. Harrison, M.I. Lau, and E.E. Rutström. Multiattribute Utility Theory, Intertemporal Utility and Correlation Aversion. Working Paper 2011–04; Atlanta, GA, USA: Center for the Economic Analysis of Risk, Georgia State University, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- W.K. Viscusi, and W.N. Evans. “Utility functions that depend on health status: Estimates and economic implications.” Am. Econ. Rev. 80 (1990): 353–374. [Google Scholar]
- W.N. Evans, and W.K. Viscusi. “Estimation of state dependent utility functions using survey data.” Rev. Econ. Stat. 73 (1991): 94–104. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- A. Finkelstein, E.F.P. Luttmer, and M.J. Notowidigdo. “What good is wealth without health? The effect of health on the marginal utility of consumption.” J. Eur. Econ. Assoc. 11 (2013): 221–258. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- M. Abdellaoui, C. Barrios, and P. Wakker. “Reconciling introspective utility with revealed preference: Experimental arguments based on prospect theory.” J. Econom. 138 (2007): 356–378. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- H. Bleichrodt, and J.L. Pinto. “A parameter-free elicitation of the probability weighting function in medical decision analysis.” Manag. Sci. 46 (2000): 1485–1496. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- J.F. Outreville. “Risk aversion, risk behavior, and demand for insurance: A survey.” J. Insur. Issues 37 (2014): 158–186. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- 1In our health insurance setting, the decision maker is considered multivariate risk-averse if for any and any , she prefers lottery , which gives an even chance for or to lottery , which gives an even chance for or , or, equivalently, if
- 2See Bommier (2007) and [10] on the link between risk aversion w.r.t. wealth, correlation aversion, and the intertemporal elasticity of substitution. Many macroeconomic models postulate an additive intertemporal utility function, which corresponds to correlation neutrality. In such a case, the atemporal risk aversion—often measured by the index of relative risk aversion—simultaneously determines preferences among gambles in a given period, and the propensity of the representative consumer to substitute wealth across time.
- 3Moreover, there is no consensus among health economists about the sign of the cross derivative , and thus about whether individuals are bivariate risk-averse or risk-seeking when they face gambles related to wealth and health; see Viscusi and Evans [11], Evans and Viscusi [12], and Finkelstein et al. [13].
- 4Hence, any change in the utility function —for instance, a change in a parameter that would make the individual more risk-averse—may affect the marginal willingness to pay. However, parameter provides one degree of freedom in the value of this marginal willingness to pay. A non-expected utility setting—such as prospect theory—would provide more flexibility in order to characterize the attitude toward financial risk, independent of the marginal willingness to pay for a health improvement. See Abdellaoui et al. [14] for an experimental approach, and Bleichrodt et al. [15] for an application to medical decision analysis.
- 5In the insurers’ terminology, the coinsurance rate is sometimes used for , which is the share of health expenses retained by the policyholder.
- 6Outreville [16] surveys the empirical analysis of socio-demographic variables associated with risk aversion.
- 7Equation (11) is obtained first by substituting in and then by observing that, for all x, the derivative of U with respect to m vanishes when because of Equation (1). The pointwise derivative of U with respect to is thus written as . The optimal coinsurance rate cancels the expected value of this pointwise derivative, which gives (11).
- 8Note that because is increasing w.r.t. x.
- 9The conclusions of Section 2 have been reached for a given value of parameter , and the optimal coinsurance rate may depend on as well as on function . Since , we may consider an exogenously-given wealth level as a reference point, and define as the reference of the individual. With this definition, an individual is fully characterized by function , which represents her preferences among financial gambles, by , which measures her willingness to pay for a better health and by her initial wealth w. Our conclusion about the invariance of the optimal coinsurance rate w.r.t. initial wealth holds for unchanged and .
- 11Everything else given, (24) does not hold when is small enough. In that case, is equal to 0 or 1 in a sub-interval of . Thus, strictly speaking, the independence of from has been established among values of that are large enough for such corner solutions not to be optimal.
- 12Note that the two terms in Equation (12) may be rewritten as and . Hence, in the CARA case, both terms are proportional to the index of absolute risk tolerance , so that does not affect the optimal coinsurance rate. In addition, both terms are independent of (which may not be the case in the more general framework considered in Section 2) and, consequently, the optimal coinsurance rate does not depend on .
© 2016 by the author; licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC-BY) license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Picard, P. A Note on Health Insurance under Ex Post Moral Hazard. Risks 2016, 4, 38. https://doi.org/10.3390/risks4040038
Picard P. A Note on Health Insurance under Ex Post Moral Hazard. Risks. 2016; 4(4):38. https://doi.org/10.3390/risks4040038
Chicago/Turabian StylePicard, Pierre. 2016. "A Note on Health Insurance under Ex Post Moral Hazard" Risks 4, no. 4: 38. https://doi.org/10.3390/risks4040038
APA StylePicard, P. (2016). A Note on Health Insurance under Ex Post Moral Hazard. Risks, 4(4), 38. https://doi.org/10.3390/risks4040038