1. Introduction
The questions to be addressed here belong to additive number theory. The scope of this field has grown in recent times. We shall consider the possibility of partitioning certain sets of integers into two or more subsets with equal sums. Although this is a very basic question, it appears not to have been previously discussed. A brief survey will show how it fits within the field.
In their classical introduction to number theory, Hardy and Wright [
1] devoted three chapters to additive number theory. The first of these chapters, entitled
Partitions, begins by describing what was then regarded as the general problem of additive number theory, the study of additive representations of positive integers. To paraphrase: Let
be a given subset of the positive integers
, such as
itself, or the squares
, or the primes
. Let
be the number of representations of an arbitrary positive integer
as a sum, each term of which is an element in
, subject to a variety of possible restrictions: the number of terms in the sum may be fixed or bounded or unbounded; the sum may be permitted to include equal terms, or this may be ruled out; the order of the terms in the sum may be considered relevant or not. The problem then is to determine
or at least to establish some of its properties.
For example, the study of
unrestricted partitions of positive integers considers
when the set
of possible summands is
the number of possible terms is unbounded, equal terms are permitted, and order is irrelevant. (Equivalently, in this case,
counts the number of multisets of positive integers with sum
) This view of additive number theory is endorsed by Nathanson in a more recent work focussing on representations as sums of
th powers (
or the primes [
2].
Various studies which do not focus on additive representations of integers, but nevertheless rightfully belong to additive number theory, have appeared in modern times. Many studies consider set partitions rather than integer partitions. Here, the general problem considers partitions of a given subset of into a fixed or bounded number of disjoint subsets, and seeks conditions in which at least one of those subsets must inevitably exhibit a certain property, or else conditions ensuring the existence of a partition in which none of the subsets has a certain property.
For instance, van der Waerden’s classical theorem [
3] effectively states that for given positive integers
and
if
is the set
comprising all positive integers up to
and if
is sufficiently large, then every partition of
into
subsets inevitably includes a subset containing an arithmetic progression of at least
terms. A 2004 major break-through theorem by Green and Tao [
4] implies that this result holds if
is the set
comprising all primes up to
In his survey of unsolved problems in number theory, Guy [
5] devotes a chapter to additive number theory, covering a wide range of problems, many of which do not readily fit the general types described above. They include studies seeking a maximal subset
of
with a specified property, such as all subsets of
having distinct sums, or all
–subsets having distinct sums, or no subset summing to a positive multiple of a prescribed integer
. Related studies consider subsets of
which are determined by the sums of their subsets of fixed size.
Against this background, let us now consider partitions of a finite set with the property that the participating subsets all have the same sum.
The notation and terminology are as follows. Given a finite set of positive integers
, of cardinality
let
be a partition of
into
nonempty subsets, called
blocks, with
Thus,
For brevity, call a –partition of and call the order of the partition. The partition is proper when , and trivial when or .
We consider the case when
has sum
which is a multiple of
say
. A
–partition
of
is
equisum, with
block sum , if each of its blocks has sum
:
When does have a proper equisum partition? Clearly, and are necessary conditions, and these conditions are sharp. In the following sections, constructive algorithms will be used to show:
If and or is any prime-power the initial interval of integers has an equisum –partition if and only if is a multiple of .
No product of two odd prime-powers has an equisum –partition of its positive divisors; however, for any prime and with odd, the set of all positive divisors of has an equisum –partition when . Even perfect numbers are the “boundary case” of this result.
If the set of aliquot divisors of has an equisum –partition then has at least two distinct prime factors. For any prime and with odd, the set of aliquot divisors of has an equisum –partition if . Again, even perfect numbers are the “boundary case” of this result.
If is odd, its set of aliquot divisors can have an equisum –partition only when is a perfect square. Further, if has exactly two distinct prime factors they must either be twin primes or 3 and 7. The aliquot divisors always have an equisum –partition when ; this probably also holds when . However, there may be only finitely many pairs such that the aliquot divisors of have such a partition.
Some suggestive results are also obtained for initial intervals of the primes. For , it is shown that the smallest feasible initial interval of primes with sum equal to a multiple of does have an equisum –partition. For every odd-sized initial interval of primes does have an equisum –partition, and it is conjectured that this holds for every odd-sized initial interval of primes.
2. Initial Intervals of
The most natural class of set
to consider for equisum partition is an initial interval of integers
If
is a
–partition of
, its range of block sizes
is of interest. The
defect of
is the smallest integer
such that
If has defect it is a uniform partition of , with block size It is natural to seek equisum partitions with minimum defect.
Two examples serve to give insight into equisum partitions of .
Example 1. Ifthen, so any proper equisum partition ofmust have order. Sinceis the only possible order that is a factor of 14, it is the only case where defectis possible. An equisum–
partition does exist in each case:
The first partition is uniform, the other two have defect.
Example 2. Ifthen, so any proper equisum partition ofhas order. An equisum–
partition exists in each case. For instance,
By taking unions of consecutive pairs of blocks, then repeating, equisum partitions of orders 4
and 2
are immediately produced. All three have defect . This is best possible, since each has even order but is odd.
Next, for the two possible orders which are divisors of 15
there are uniform equisum partitions: Finally, for order 6
we have an equisum partition with defect :
Notice that pairs of blocks of different sizes in this equisum 6–partition could be combined to give an alternative uniform equisum 3–partition.
We now introduce a construction which serves to generalise these examples. For any and define
Direct Sum Construction: Letandbe–partitions of the setsand,
respectively. The direct sumis a–partition of the set.
The direct sum construction has several useful special cases. If and are uniform, then is uniform. If and are equisum, and is uniform, then is equisum.
Let us call a consecsum –partition of if its block sums satisfy for . We now note two more special cases of the direct sum construction. If is consecsum and is uniform equisum, then is consecsum. Finally, if and are both consecsum, and is uniform, then is equisum when , the reverse of , is defined by .
Theorem 1. LetIfhas an equisum–partition with defect, then so does, for any, such that
Proof. Let be the trivial uniform –partition of with for Then is consecsum, so is a uniform equisum –partition of . Put and for all Then is a uniform equisum b–partition of . Let be an equisum –partition of with defect . Then, is an equisum –partition of with defect . □
When has a –partition of the specified type, the proof of Theorem 1 is, in effect, an unconditional algorithm for constructing from such a –partition for each suitable . The back and forth (boustrophedon) construction producing can be described as knitting.
With the convention that , we define to be a consecsum –partition of with defect , admitting one empty block. The knitting step produces an equisum –partition of with defect , so with ordinary knitting we have
Theorem 2. For any, andthe sethas an equisum–partition, with defect, for all
A parallel construction, proceeding from consecsum to equisum, now establishes.
Lemma 1. LetIfhas a consecsum–partition with defect, thenhas an equisum–partition with defectfor any, such that
Proof. As in the previous proof, is a uniform consecsum –partition of , and is a uniform equisum –partition of . For all let , Then, is a uniform consecsum –partition of . Suppose that is a consecsum –partition of with defect . Then, is an equisum –partition of with defect . □
When has a consecsum –partition with defect , the proof of Lemma 1 is, in effect, an unconditional algorithm for constructing from an equisum –partition with defect for each suitable . Knitting is the key.
Let , , for all . As is a consecsum partition of with defect , so is a consecsum –partition of with defect . Hence
Theorem 3. For any, andthe sethas a consecsum–partition, with defect, for all
The next construction proceeds from equisum to consecsum.
Lemma 2. For any oddifhas an equisum–partition with defect, thenandhave consecsum–partitions with defect.
Proof. For any
let
Let
be the
–partition of
with blocks
Clearly
runs through even members of
as
runs through
, and
runs through odd members of
as
runs through
. For each
, there is an
such that
has block sum
Thus there is a permutation
such that
so
is a uniform consecsum
–partition of
Let
be an equisum
–partition of
with defect
. Then,
and
are consecsum
–partitions of
and
, respectively, both with defect
. □
The construction in the proof of Lemma 2, together with a modified version in which is replaced by throughout, yields
Lemma 3. For any oddandthe sethas a consecsum–partition, with defectfor all.
Forming direct sums with now yields
Theorem 4. For any oddandthe sethas an equisum–partition, with defectfor allsuch that.
The interval can have an equisum –partition only if at most one block is a singleton, so Together, Theorems 2 and 4 establish
Theorem 5. For anyandthe sethas an equisum partition of order, with defect, ifor else if, andis odd.
Let be the set of primes. As and are coprime, we have
Corollary 1. For anywith, the sethas an equisum partition of order, with defect, if and only if.
For any proper divisor of or Theorem 5 settles when has an equisum partition of order . This leaves open the question of whether has an equisum partition of order when are coprime positive integers such that and
Example 3. Forthe following is a consecsum partition of order 10, with defect:
Its direct sum with the reversed trivial consecsum 10–partition ofyields an equisum 10–partition ofwith defect:
Here To generalise this example, it is notationally convenient to denote the set of triangular numbers by . Note that
Lemma 4. ForletThe sethas an equisum–partition with defect.
Proof. For any
let
be the
–partition of
with blocks
Since
for
, it follows that
, so
is consecsum with defect
. Let
, so
is a defect
equisum
–partition of
. Let
and
for all
. Then
is a uniform
–partition of
. Hence
has the defect
equisum 𝑏–partition
, for any
. □
Lemma 4 describes a family of sets with an equisum partition of order such that and . In particular, leads to an order equisum partition of with defect , starting with the order 6 partition of given in Example 2. Similarly, leads to an order equisum partition of with defect , starting with the order 10 partition of in Example 3.
Example 4. Here is an order 6 consecsum partition for, with defect:
and an order 10
consecsum partition for , with defect :
Each of these partitions yields a defect equisum –partition when we form its direct sum with the reversed trivial consecsum –partition of . With Lemma 1
it now follows for all that has an equisum –partition, and has an equisum –partition, with defect in all instances. As 12 is not a triangular number, we cannot use Lemma 4 for the case but the method used in Example 4 can be applied.
Example 5. Here are defectorder 12
consecsum partitions for the intervals and :
Equisum –partitions with defect result by forming direct sums with the reversed trivial consecsum –partition of . For all Lemma 1
now shows that and have equisum –partitions with defect .
For , these results demonstrate the existence of order equisum partitions of for all four residue classes of such that
Theorem 6. Forandthe sethas an equisum partition of order, with defect, if and only if
It appears likely that for all , if and then has an equisum partition of order , with defect However, a proof with this level of generality seems to be elusive.
3. Initial Intervals of
An apparently unlikely class of set
to consider for equisum partition is an initial interval of the primes
,
Because appears to have an irregular fine structure, regularity in partitions of its initial intervals is unexpected. However, has a regular large scale structure, such as the asymptotic equidistribution of primes into the reside classes coprime with for any Hence, for any we might hope that there are infinitely many primes such that has an equisum –partition with a relatively small defect. Closer study gives support to this hope.
If has an equisum –partition with then for some Perhaps, for each , there might be a prime such that has an equisum –partition if and only if and The next example is consistent with this possibility.
Example 6. Forthe earliest instances ofsuch thatare the following, noted for eachas pairswithfor
Forthe instances are much less frequent:is the first. Evidently,anddo not have equisum partitions of orderbecauseis not large enough. For each order, the following are the earliest possible equisum–partitions, with the corresponding possible. Considerations of parity show that the block containing 2
must be the only block of its size, so each partition has a positive defect:
For an equisum partition of order 6
for iswhere the final block is the subset of 21
remaining primes from This solution was produced using a greedy algorithm approach. It is easy to see that order 6
equisum partitions with smaller defect do exist: for example, the subset could be exchanged for Guy’s prime from the first block to reduce the defect of the above partition. Let us examine the case
more closely. Let
with
for all
Since
is the only even prime,
if and only if
is odd. Suppose, for some particular
, that
has an equisum 2–partition
Say that
has the
extension property if there are subsets
such that
where
(This is somewhat related to the classical Goldbach conjecture.) Then,
is an equisum 2–partition
of
. (To suit the notation, at times it might be necessary to interchange the two blocks of
) If
the construction always works with
If
and 2, 3 are in separate blocks of
then
works and 2, 3 are in separate blocks of
Beginning with
the sequence
leads to equisum 2–partitions with
and subsequently:
Thus, has an equisum 2–partition for , since the first 14 cases have the extension property, and apart from adjoining the two new primes, at each step, except and , it suffices to move 2, or move 3, or interchange 2 and 3; when we interchange 3 and 7, and when we move 7. This covers all primes to Even the famously large gap is accommodated. The construction is heuristic rather than algorithmic, as the extension property has not been proved to continue to hold, though it is highly plausible that it will do so.
Conjecture: has an equisum 2–partition for all
Similar, but more complicated, heuristic constructions can be given for higher order partitions, but we leave the details for the reader.
4. Divisor Sets
For any
the divisor set of
is
and
where
is the set of maximal prime-power divisors of
We call
the
rank of
it is simply the number of distinct prime factors of
For any
a necessary condition for
to have an equisum
–partition is
and
since
Thus, we need
so the “boundary case”
requires
to be
perfect [
6]; in all other cases,
so
is
abundant. No prime-power is perfect or abundant, since
always holds: for
to have an equisum
–partition with
, the rank of
must be at least 2. Indeed, order
requires a rank of at least 3, order
requires rank at least 6, and so on. If
is odd and has rank 2 then
, so an equisum
–partition of
for
of rank 2 is only possible if
. If
for some
then
so
can have an equisum
–partition only if
Lemma 5. LetFor everythe divisor sethas an equisum–partition.
Proof. Let
Choose any
and let
Then
is a
–partition of
, with block sums
To begin, suppose
and
. (This is the case in which
is perfect.) Then the block sums of
are
so the transfer
produces a new
–partition
of
which is equisum, since its block sums are
Note that
,
and
. Now suppose
and
, or
and
. (In this case
is abundant.) Recall that the block sums of
satisfy
Let
Then
because either
or
. Since
contains
, there is some set
such that
matches the binary representation of
Now the exchange
defines a
–partition
of
which is equisum, since
This construction explicitly satisfies the claim. □
When , the divisor set contains exactly odd factors of so the block sums of any –partition of have the same parity if and only if is odd. Hence, an equisum –partition of is only possible when is odd.
Suppose
is odd and
Continue with the construction used to prove Lemma 5, now adjusted by taking
As
is odd, so
is even. Let
and
so
There is a subset
such that
and the exchange
produces an equisum 2–partition of
If
then
. Hence, we have
Theorem 7. LetThen the divisor sethas an equisum–partition.
It is worth noting that the equisum –partition explicitly constructed to prove Theorem 7 is not necessarily unique. For instance, when , the constructed equisum –partition of has as the block containing while an alternative has as the block containing (This alternative essentially results from the identity
We shall forego discussion of equisum –partitions of divisor sets for cases when has rank greater than 2. However, there is a nice question to note. Presumably for each there are divisor sets which have an equisum –partition; if so, what is the smallest such ?
5. Aliquot Sets
For any , the aliquot set is the set of divisors less than often called its aliquot parts. Its sum is Unlike , the function is not multiplicative, so it is less straightforward to use the structure of to predict when will be a multiple of any given However, for the simplest case evidently if and only if and have the same parity: this occurs precisely when is an odd square, or is even and is neither a square nor twice a square.
The construction used for Lemma 5 and Theorem 7 easily adapts to the aliquot case, and shows in particular that the aliquot set of an even perfect number has an equisum 2–partition.
Theorem 8. LetThen, the aliquot sethas an equisum–partition.
Proof. Let
be the equisum 2–partition of the divisor set
used to establish Theorem 7. Then
and
. Let
Evidently,
is an equisum 2–partition of
. □
For any
, suppose the divisor set
has an equisum 2–partition
such that
Then, the construction used for Theorem 8 modifies to yield an equisum 2–partition
for the aliquot set
, thus:
Note that if is an equisum 2–partition of the blocks of do not necessarily separate and . For instance, has an equisum 2–partition into and its complement. On the other hand, the equisum 2–partition into and its complement does separate 300 and 600, so easily modifies to give an equisum 2–partition of
For any , we have , so any –partition of has one block sum in the residue class and all others in ; hence, the block sums cannot be equal. Thus, if has an equisum –partition, must have a rank of at least 2.
For brevity, we shall confine the remaining discussion to equisum –partitions of for odd of rank 2.
Theorem 9. Lethave just two distinct prime factorsIf the aliquot sethas anequisum–partition thenare twin primes or
Proof. Let
for some
Clearly,
has no equisum
–partition if its largest aliquot divisor
is greater than the sum of all other aliquot divisors. The sum of those other divisors is
Hence,
certainly holds if
For
, this holds when
For
, it holds when
since
is prime, the only case not then excluded is
□
Theorem 10. For everythe aliquot sethas an equisum 2–partition.
Proof. When
, the aliquot set
has the equisum
–partition
Fix
and suppose
is an equisum
–partition of
with
Since
then
has
–partition
such that
Moreover,
is equisum because
Now fix
and suppose
is an equisum
–partition of
with
Then
has
–partition
such that
where
. Furthermore,
is equisum because
Induction on
and
completes the argument. □
As before, the proof of Theorem 10, and that which follows for Theorem 11, do essentially provide unconditional algorithms for constructing an equisum partition in any concrete instance.
Theorem 11. Forand everythe aliquot sethas an equisum 2–partition.
Proof. When
, the aliquot set
has the equisum
–partition
Fix
and suppose
is an equisum
–partition of
with
Then
has
–partition
such that
Moreover
is equisum because
When
, the aliquot set
has an equisum
–partition comprising
and its complement. When
, the aliquot set
has an equisum
–partition comprising
and its complement. Fix
and assume
is an equisum
–partition of
with
Then
has the
–partition
such that
with complement
Furthermore,
so
is equisum. The claim now follows by induction on
. □
Probably the aliquot set has an equisum 2–partition for every although a general construction seems to be elusive. However, perhaps there is only a finite number of prime pairs such that has an equisum –partition for any
As with divisor sets, we forego discussion of aliquot sets when has rank greater than except to report that has both an equisum –partition and an equisum –partition, so we can ask the following general question. Presumably for each there are aliquot sets which have an equisum –partition; if so, what is the smallest such ?