On Intergenerational Commitment, Weak Sustainability, and Safety
Abstract
:1. Introduction
1.1. The Sustainability Commitment Is an Intergenerational Obligation
1.2. What Should We Aspire to Sustain?
1.2.1. Weak Sustainability—Sustaining Welfare by Bequeathing Non-Diminished Inclusive Wealth
1.2.2. Strong Sustainability—Sustaining Particular Resources
- Preserving nature for its amenity value to humans or for its own sake [37].
1.2.3. Exhaustible and Renewable Resources
1.2.4. WS-Plus
2. Materials and Methods
2.1. A Simple Model of a Stylized but Informative Case
- There is a decision maker (the agent) who seeks a reward on behalf of a group of resource-dependent people. The reward could come in welfare as economists define it or, in more isolated circumstances, perhaps food to store for the winter.
- The resource is at any time in one of two possible states, Prosperous or Degraded. The agent chooses a level of exploitation—High-pressure exploitation generates greater rewards, but is possible only in the P state.
- In any period under H, there is a chance that the resource collapses, i.e., tips to the D state where exploitation yields zero reward.
- Under Low-pressure exploitation in state P, the reward is smaller, but there is no chance of resource collapse.
- In state D, exploitation is impossible, but there is a chance that the resource will revert to the P state.
- System states, s: Prosperous or Degraded
- Policies,π, are risky (High-pressure exploitation if P; zero if D) and cautious (Low-pressure always).
- Key variables
rh | Time-stream of rewards from H action in P state (zero in D state). |
rl | Time-stream of rewards from L action in P state (zero in D state). |
rmin | The minimum acceptable time-stream of rewards. |
t | A time period in (0, …, T), such that rt, πt and st are r, π and s, respectively, in period t. |
d | Probability of collapse from H action in P state in a given period (i.e., a measure of system vulnerability). |
p | Probability of recovery in D state in a given period (i.e., a measure of system resilience). |
δ | Discount factor expressing the agent’s time preference, 0 ≤ δ ≤ 1; future rewards are discounted entirely at 0, while there is no discounting at 1. |
E(PV(r)) | Expected present value of the time-stream of rewards. |
- Optimality, O, in which the expected present value of the time-stream of rewards is maximized;
- Sustainability, S, in which the expected present value of the time-stream of rewards is maintained ≥ PV(rmin);
- Safety, Sa, which avoids all risk by maintaining the cautious L policy at all times, so that reward never falls below rl.
2.1.1. How Does This Model Relate to the Standard Sustainability Concepts?
2.1.2. How General Is This Model?
2.2. Thought Experiments to Elucidate the Implications, Bound the Scope, and Test the Generality of the Simple Model
3. Results
3.1. The Role of Safety in the BDLK Model
3.1.1. Risk Management
- Self-protection, i.e., expenditure of effort and resources to reduce the chance of harm by reducing d, and/or increasing p;
- Self-insurance, which may include savings to help maintain consumption ≥rtmin in all periods, even if rt falls below rtmin, and diversification to reduce dependence on a single vulnerable resource;
- Purchased insurance, i.e., a contract that promises compensation in the event of specified harms.
3.1.2. Scale: Within Limits, Increasing Scale Weakens the Case for Safety
3.2. The Intergenerational Commitment with Uncertain Welfare
3.2.1. The Illegitimacy of Generational Greed
3.2.2. Uncertain Welfare
3.3. What Can We Learn from the BDLK Model re Intergenerational Obligations?
3.3.1. Generations
3.3.2. Savings
3.4. Generalizing Beyond the BDLK Model
3.5. Intragenerational Burden-Sharing When Welfare Prospects Are Distributed Unevenly
3.5.1. On Heterogeneous Prospects
3.5.2. On Commonality of Interests
3.5.3. On the Intersection of These Concerns
- (1)
- The existence and prospects of present humans are valued.
- (2)
- The existence and prospects of future humans are valued.
- (3)
- Moral agents have intragenerational obligations to each other, such that commitments to provide opportunities for the future must be negotiated in the context of intragenerational obligations to each other, here and now.
3.5.4. Some Tentative Steps toward Win-Win Solutions
3.5.5. Sustainable Development Goals, SDGs
4. Discussion
Funding
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
References
- World Commission on Environment and Development. Our Common Future; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 1987. [Google Scholar]
- Solow, R. Intergenerational equity and exhaustible resources. Rev. Econ. Stud. Symp. Econ. Exhaustible Resour. 1974, 41, 29–45. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Asheim, G.B. Intergenerational equity. Annu. Rev. Econ. 2010, 2, 197–222. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Neumayer, E. Weak Versus Strong Sustainability: Exploring the Limits of Two Opposing Paradigms, 4th ed.; Edward Elgar: Cheltenham, UK, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Turner, R.K. Speculations on Weak and Strong Sustainability; CSERGE Working Paper 92–26; Centre for Social and Economic Research on the Global Environment: London, UK, 1992. [Google Scholar]
- Ott, K. The case for strong sustainability. In Greifswald’s Environmental Ethics; Ott, K., Thapa, P.P., Eds.; Steinbecker Verlag Ulrich Rose: Greifswald, Germany, 2003; pp. 59–64. [Google Scholar]
- Mulgan, T. Ethics for a Broken World; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- Page, E. Intergenerational justice of what: Welfare, resources or capabilities? Environ. Politics 2007, 16, 453–469. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Stavins, R.N.; Wagner, A.F.; Wagner, G. Interpreting sustainability in economic terms: Dynamic efficiency plus intergenerational equity. Econ. Lett. 2003, 79, 339–343. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Randall, A. Environmental ethics for environmental economists. In Encyclopedia of Energy, Natural Resource, and Environmental Economics; Shogren, J., Shortle, J., Eds.; Elsevier: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 2013; Volume 3, pp. 25–32. [Google Scholar]
- Arrow, K.J.; Dasgupta, P.; Goulder, L.H.; Mumford, K.J.; Oleson, K. Sustainability and the measurement of wealth. Environ. Dev. Econ. 2012, 17, 317–353. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Dasgupta, P. The welfare economic theory of green national accounts. Environ. Resour. Econ. 2009, 42, 3–38. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hamilton, K.; Ruta, G. Wealth accounting, exhaustible resources and social welfare. Environ. Resour. Econ. 2009, 42, 53–64. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dasgupta, P.; Maler, K.G. Net national product, wealth, and social well-being. Environ. Dev. Econ. 2000, 5, 69–93. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pearce, D.; Atkinson, G. Capital theory and the measurement of sustainable development: An indicator of weak sustainability. Ecol. Econ. 1993, 8, 103–108. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Yamaguchi, R.; Islam, M.; Managi, S. Wealth in the twenty-first century: A summary and further discussion of Inclusive Wealth Report 2018. Lett. Spat. Resour. Sci. 2019, 12, 101–111. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Hamilton, K.; Hartwick, J.M. Investing exhaustible resource rents and the path of consumption. Can. J. Econ. 2005, 38, 615–621. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dasgupta, P.; Heal, G. Economic Theory and Exhaustible Resources; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1979. [Google Scholar]
- Hartwick, J. Intergenerational equity and the investing of rents from exhaustible resources. Am. Econ. Rev. 1977, 67, 972–974. [Google Scholar]
- Pezzey, J.C. One-sided sustainability tests with amenities, and changes in technology, trade and population. J. Environ. Econ. Manag. 2004, 48, 613–631. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Pezzey, J.C.; Toman, M. Progress and problems in the economics of sustainability. In International Yearbook of Environmental and Resource Economics 2002/2003; Tietenberg, T., Folmer, H., Eds.; Edward Elgar: Cheltenham, UK, 2002; pp. 165–232. [Google Scholar]
- Asheim, G. Hartwick’s rule. In Encyclopedia of Energy, Natural Resource, and Environmental Economics; Elsevier Science: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 2013; Volume 2, pp. 314–320. [Google Scholar]
- Figge, F. Capital substitutability and weak sustainability revisited: The conditions for capital substitution in the presence of risk. Environ. Values 2005, 14, 185–201. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Fenichel, E.P.; Zhao, J. Sustainability and substitutability. Bull. Math. Biol. 2015, 77, 348–367. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dasgupta, P. Time and Generations: Population Ethics for a Diminishing Planet; Columbia University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2019. [Google Scholar]
- Ekins, P. Strong sustainability and critical natural capital. In Handbook of Sustainable Development, 2nd ed.; Atkinson, G., Dietz, S., Neumayer, E., Agarwala, M., Eds.; Edward Elgar: Cheltenham, UK, 2014; pp. 55–71. [Google Scholar]
- Farmer, M.C.; Randall, A. The rationality of a safe minimum standard. Land Econ. 1998, 74, 287–302. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ready, C.R.; Bishop, R.C. Endangered species and the safe minimum standard. Am. J. Agric. Econ. 1991, 73, 309–312. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bishop, R.C. Endangered species and uncertainty: The economics of a safe minimum standard. Am. J. Agric. Econ. 1978, 60, 10–18. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ciriacy-Wantrup, S.V. Resource Conservation: Economics and Policies, 3rd ed.; University of California, Division of Agricultural Science: Berkeley, CA, USA, 1968. [Google Scholar]
- Barbier, E.B.; Burgess, J.C. Natural resource economics, planetary boundaries, and strong sustainability. Sustainability 2017, 9, 1858. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Rockström, J.; Steffen, W.; Noone, K.; Persson, Å.; Chapin, F.S.; Lambin, E.F.; Lenton, T.M.; Scheffer, M.; Folke, C.; Schellnhuber, H.J.; et al. A safe operating space for humanity. Nature 2009, 461, 472–475. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Randall, A. Risk and Precaution; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Gollier, C.; Treich, N. Decision-making under scientific uncertainty: The economics of the precautionary principle. J. Risk Uncertain. 2003, 27, 77–103. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Chichilnisky, G. An axiomatic approach to choice under uncertainty with catastrophic risks. Resour. Energy Econ. 2000, 22, 221–231. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Raffensperger, C.; Tichner, J. Protecting Public Health and the Environment: Implementing the Precautionary Principle; Island Press: Washington, DC, USA, 1999. [Google Scholar]
- Armstrong, C. Natural Resources and Intergenerational Ethics. (18 August 2019). Available online: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3439068 (accessed on 1 July 2020).
- Barry, B. Sustainability and Intergenerational Justice. In Fairness and Futurity; Dobson, A., Ed.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 1999; pp. 93–117. [Google Scholar]
- Daly, H.E. On Wilfred Beckerman’s critique of sustainable development. Environ. Values 1995, 4, 49–55. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Brock, P.M.; Tan, D.K.Y. A second-take on the role of science: The case for applying public administration theory to natural resource management. Sustain. Earth 2020, 3, 1. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- El Serafy, S. The Proper Calculation of Income from Depletable Natural Resources. In Environmental Accounting for Sustainable Development; Ahmad, Y.J., el Serafy, S., Lutz, E., Eds.; The World Bank: Washington, DC, USA, 1989. [Google Scholar]
- Irwin, E.G.; Gopalakrishnan, S.; Randall, A. Wealth, welfare, and sustainability. Annu. Rev. Resour. Econ. 2016, 8, 77–98. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Randall, A. Weak sustainability, conservation, and precaution. In Handbook of Sustainable Development, 2nd ed.; Atkinson, G., Dietz, S., Neumayer, E., Agarwala, M., Eds.; Edward Elgar: Cheltenham, UK, 2014; pp. 160–172. [Google Scholar]
- Bolis, I.; Morioka, S.N.; Laerte, S.I. When sustainable development risks losing its meaning. Delimiting the concept with a comprehensive literature review and a conceptual model. J. Clean. Prod. 2014, 83, 7–20. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Barfuss, W.; Donges, J.F.; Lade, S.J.; Kurths, J. When optimization for governing human environment tipping elements is neither sustainable nor safe. Nat. Commun. 2018, 9, 2354. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Holling, C.S. Surprise for science, resilience for ecosystems, and incentives for people. Ecol. Appl. 1996, 6, 733–735. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Cai, Y.; Judd, K.L.; Lenton, T.M.; Lontzek, T.S.; Narita, D. Environmental tipping points significantly affect the cost-benefit assessment of climate policies. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 2015, 112, 4606–4611. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Raworth, K. A doughnut for the anthropocene: Humanity’s compass in the 21st century. Lancet Planet Health 2017, 1, e48–e49. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Asheim, G.B.; Mitra, T.; Tungodden, B. Sustainable recursive social welfare functions. Econ. Theory 2012, 49, 267–292. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Caney, S. Justice and posterity. In Climate Justice: Integrating Economics and Philosophy; Kanbur, R., Shue, H., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2018; pp. 157–174. [Google Scholar]
- Ehrlich, I.; Becker, G. Market insurance, self-insurance, and self-protection. J. Political Econ. 1972, 80, 624–648. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Traeger, C.P. Why uncertainty matters: Discounting under intertemporal risk aversion and ambiguity. Econ. Theory 2014, 56, 627–664. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Millner, A.; Dietz, S.; Heal, G. Scientific ambiguity and climate policy. Environ. Resour. Econ. 2013, 55, 21–46. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tallis, H.M.; Hawthorne, P.L.; Polasky, S.; Reid, J.; Beck, M.W.; Brauman, K.; Bielicki, J.M.; Binder, S.; Burgess, M.G.; Cassidy Clark, E.A.; et al. An attainable global vision for conservation and human well-being. Front. Ecol. Environ. 2018, 16, 563–570. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Ingram, J. A food systems approach to researching food security and its interactions with global environmental change. Food Secur. 2011, 3, 417–431. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Parfit, D. Reasons and Persons; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 1984. [Google Scholar]
- Rawls, J. A Theory of Justice; Belknap Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1971. [Google Scholar]
- Otsuka, M. Libertarianism Without Inequality; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Bewley, T.F. General Equilibrium, Overlapping Generations Models, and Optimal Growth Theory; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2007. [Google Scholar]
- Mulgan, T. Future People; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2006. [Google Scholar]
- World Wildlife Fund. Living Planet Report 2018; World Wildlife Fund: Gland, Switzerland, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Wilson, E.O. Half-Earth: Our Planet’s Fight for Life; Liveright: London, UK, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Szabo, M. A common heritage fund for future generations. In Institutions for Future Generations; Gonzalez-Ricoy, I., Gosseries, A., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2017; pp. 197–213. [Google Scholar]
- Buscher, B.; Fletcher, R.; Brockington, D.; Sandbrook, C. Half earth or whole earth? Radical ideas for conservation, and their implications. Oryx 2016, 51, 407–410. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Armstrong, C. Sharing conservation burdens fairly. Conserv. Biol. 2019, 33, 554–560. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Salzman, J.; Bennett, G.; Carroll, N.; Goldstein, A.; Jenkins, M. The global status and trends of payments for ecosystem services. Nat. Sustain. 2018, 1, 136–144. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Duchelle, A.E.; Simonet, G.; Sunderlin, W.D.; Wunder, S. What is REDD+ achieving on the ground? Curr. Opin. Environ. Sustain. 2018, 32, 134–140. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- United Nations. Sustainable Development Goals. 2020. Available online: https://www.un.org/sustainabledevelopment/sustainable-development-goals/ (accessed on 1 July 2020).
- Kuhlman, T.; Farrington, J. What is sustainability? Sustainability 2010, 2, 3436–3448. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Serageldin, I. Making development sustainable. In Making Development Sustainable—From Concepts to Action; Environmentally Sustainable Development Occasional Paper Series No. 2; Serageldin, I., Steer, A., Eds.; World Bank: Washington, DC, USA, 1994; pp. 1–3. [Google Scholar]
- Holland, T.; Peterson, G.D.; Gonzalez, A. A cross-national analysis of how economic inequality predicts biodiversity loss. Conserv. Biol. 2009, 23, 1304–1313. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Mikkelson, G.; Gonzalez, A.; Peterson, G.D. Economic inequality predicts biodiversity loss. PLoS ONE 2007, 2, 1–5. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
© 2020 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Randall, A. On Intergenerational Commitment, Weak Sustainability, and Safety. Sustainability 2020, 12, 5381. https://doi.org/10.3390/su12135381
Randall A. On Intergenerational Commitment, Weak Sustainability, and Safety. Sustainability. 2020; 12(13):5381. https://doi.org/10.3390/su12135381
Chicago/Turabian StyleRandall, Alan. 2020. "On Intergenerational Commitment, Weak Sustainability, and Safety" Sustainability 12, no. 13: 5381. https://doi.org/10.3390/su12135381
APA StyleRandall, A. (2020). On Intergenerational Commitment, Weak Sustainability, and Safety. Sustainability, 12(13), 5381. https://doi.org/10.3390/su12135381