Emotion and Knowledge in Decision Making under Uncertainty
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Review of the Literature
2.1. The Shape of the Weighting Function under Ambiguity
2.2. Emotions
2.3. Knowledge
3. Theoretical Background
- (i)
- Lower Subadditivity (LSA):
- (ii)
- Upper Subadditivity (USA):
4. Experimental Design and Methods
5. Results
5.1. Matching Tasks
5.2. Decision Making under Risk
5.3. Decision Making under Ambiguity
5.4. Emotion, Knowledge and Decision Making under Ambiguity
6. Discussion
Supplementary Materials
Author Contributions
Funding
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
Appendix A
Experiment | Election | Recruitment | Subjects | Date Exper. | Incentives |
---|---|---|---|---|---|
Milan 1 | 13 May 2001 Italian general political election. | Volunteers recruited through advertisement at the Faculty of Political Science of the University of Milan. | Subjects = n. 35 Females = n. 12 Males = n. 23 Median age = 25.37 s.d. age = 3.79 | 10 May 2001 | Show-up fee: 2000 Italian liras (about €1) instant lottery ticket. Incentive: Up to 240,000 Italian liras (about €120) if randomly selected. |
Alessandria | 12 and 13 June 2004 European parliamentary election. | Volunteers recruited through advertisement at the Faculty of Political Science of the University of Eastern Piedmont (IT). | Subjects = n. 31 Females = n. 14 Males = n. 17 Median age = 23.77 s.d. age = 3.68 | 9 June 2004 | Show up fee: €3 instant lottery ticket. Incentive: Up to €120 if randomly selected. |
Milan 2 | 23 and 24 February 2013 Italian general political election. | Volunteers attending an UG Public Economics course at the Faculty of Political, Economic and Social Sciences (SPES) of the University of Milan. | Subjects = n. 32 Females = n. 17 Males = n. 15 Median age = 24.84 s.d. age = 8.84 | 20 February 2013 | |
Milan 3 | 4 March 2018 Italian general political election | Volunteers attending an UG Public Economics course and a Graduate Macroeconomics course at the Faculty SPES of the University of Milan. | Subjects = n. 21 Females = n. 6 Males = n. 15 Non-Italian = n. 7 Median age = 23 s.d. age = 1.43 | 1 March 2018 (UG) 2nd March 2018 (Graduate) |
Emotion | Knowledge |
---|---|
Consider the case in which the Centre-Right coalition (Forza Italia-Berlusconi, Lega-Salvini premier, Fratelli d’Italia-Meloni, Noi con l’Italia-UDC) polls the relative majority of votes in the Italian general political elections. On a scale between 1 and 10 state your level of positive emotional involvement* for this result, 0 showing the lowest positive emotional involvement *, 10 the highest positive emotional involvement *: 0---1---2---3---4---5---6---7---8---9—10 | Do you rate yourself an expert in politics? On a scale between 1 and 10, report on the level of knowledge and expertise that you feel having as regards politics (0 not at all an expert, 10 very expert). 0---1---2---3---4---5---6---7---8---9--10 |
Tests | Space Partitions | Percentage of Subjects with Sum of Decision Weights Greater (Less) than Unity | Percentage of Subjects with Sum of Judgemental Probabilities Greater (Less) than Unity | ||||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
(a) | (b) | (c) | (d) | (d) | (e) | (f) | (g) | ||
Milan 1 N = 35 | Ales_Sandria N = 31 | Milan 2 N = 32 | Milan 3 N = 21 | Milan 1 N = 35 | Ales_Sandria N = 31 | Milan 2 N = 32 | Milan 3 N = 21 | ||
Tertiary additivity | A + B + C + D | 94 (3) | 96.7 (3.3) | 87.5 (12.5) | 95 (5) | 88.5 (3) | 93.5 (6.4) | 87.5 (3.1) | 100 (0) |
A + B + H | 88.5 (5.7) | 87 (3.3) | 65.6 (18.8) | 80.9 (9.5) | 63 (34.3) | 87 (6.4) | 68.7 (15.6) | 95 (0) | |
A + E + D | 88.5 (8.5) | 87 (3.3) | 71.8 (18.8) | 85.7 (9.5) | 74.3 (8.5) | 83.8 (12.9) | 62.5 (28.1) | 90.4 (5) | |
C + D + I | 85.7 (8.5) | 87 (3.3) | 78.1 (18.8) | 90.4 (5) | 88.6 (3) | 80.6 (6.4) | 71.8 (15.6) | 95 (5) | |
Binary complementarity | A + G | 45.7 (28.5) | 64.5 (16.1) | 37.5 (43.7) | 43 (28) | 26 (51.4) | 35.4 (19.3) | 25 (31.2) | 57 (9.5) |
F + D | 45.7 (22.8) | 70.9 (12.9) | 37.5 (46.8) | 38 (38) | 60 (20) | 29 (22.5) | 40.6 (18.7) | 57 (14) | |
H + I | 54.3 (28.5) | 70.9 (12.9) | 34.3 (37.5) | 57 (19) | 57 (25.7) | 42 (35.4) | 34.3 (31) | 47.6 (28.5) |
Weighting Functions | Judgmental Probabilities |
---|---|
Tests for lower subadditivity: LSA (h = 7) | Tests for lower subadditivity: LSA (h = 7) |
WLSA1 = W(A)+W(B)-W(I) | JLSA1 = J(A)+J(B)-J(I) |
WLSA2 = W(B)+W(C)-W(E) | JLSA2 = J(B)+J(C)-J(E) |
WLSA3 = W(C)+W(D)-W(H) | JLSA3 = J(C)+J(D)-J(H) |
WLSA4 = W(I)+W(C)-W(F) | JLSA4 = J(I)+J(C)-J(F) |
WLSA5 = W(A)+W(E)-W(F) | JLSA5 = J(A)+J(E)-J(F) |
WLSA6 = W(E)+W(D)-W(G) | JLSA6 = J(E)+J(D)-J(G) |
WLSA7 = W(B)+W(H)-W(G) | JLSA7 = J(B)+J(H)-J(G) |
Tests for upper subadditivity: USA (h = 3) | Test for upper subadditivity: USA (h = 3) |
WUSA1 = 1-W(G)-W(I)+W(B) | JUSA1 = 1-J(G)-J(I)+J(B) |
WUSA2 = 1-W(G)-W(F)+W(E) | JUSA2 = 1-J(G)-J(F)+J(E) |
WUSA3 = 1-W(H)-W(F)+W(C) | JUSA3 = 1-J(H)-J(F)+J(C) |
Lower-Subadditivity wlsai > 0 | Upper-Subadditivity wusai > 0 | Global Sensitivity swi < 1 | Lower-Subadditivity jlsai > 0 | Upper-Subadditivity jusai > 0 | Global Sensitivity sji < 1 | |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Milan 1 (N = 35) | 100 | 86 | 97 | 91 | 74 | 86 |
Alessandria (N = 31) | 97 | 68 | 93 | 97 | 93 | 100 |
Milan 2 (N = 32) | 100 | 88 | 97 | 100 | 91 | 97 |
Milan 3 (N = 21) | 95 | 86 | 95 | 95 | 90 | 90 |
N. subj | Mean | Median | Min | Max | St. Dev. | ||
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Negative Emotions | Milan 1 | 35 | 5.52 | 5.5 | 0 | 10 | 3.54 |
Alessandria | 30 | 6.13 | 7 | 0 | 10 | 3.52 | |
Milan 2 | 31 | 6.87 | 7 | 0 | 10 | 3.17 | |
Milan 3 | 22 | 8.47 | 10 | 0 | 10 | 2.56 | |
Positive Emotions | Milan1 | 35 | 4.05 | 4 | 0 | 10 | 3.37 |
Alessandria | 31 | 3.16 | 3 | 0 | 10 | 3.09 | |
Milan 2 | 32 | 2.75 | 1.5 | 0 | 10 | 3.04 | |
Milan 3 | 22 | 0.9 | 0 | 0 | 5 | 1.7 | |
Net affect | Milan 1 | 35 | −1.47 | 0 | −10 | 10 | 6.57 |
Alessandria | 35 | −2.9 | 0 | −10 | 10 | 5.7 | |
Milan 2 | 31 | −4.22 | −5 | −10 | 10 | 5.57 | |
Milan 3 | 22 | −7.57 | −9 | −10 | 5 | 4.15 | |
Level of satisfaction | Milan 1 | 35 | 4.3 | 5 | 0 | 10 | 3.48 |
Alessandria | 30 | 3.1 | 2 | 0 | 10 | 3.1 | |
Milan 2 | 28 | 2.68 | 1.5 | 0 | 10 | 2.99 | |
Milan 3 | 22 | 0 | 1.43 | 0 | 10 | 2.52 | |
Knowledge | Milan 1 | 35 | 6 | 6 | 1 | 9 | 1.82 |
Alessandria | 31 | 4 | 5.25 | 0 | 7 | 1.98 | |
Milan 2 | 32 | 5.5 (5.25) | 6 (6) | 1 (0) | 8 (8) | 1.95 (2.3) | |
Milan 3 | 22 | 5 (5.9) | 5 (8) | 0 (0) | 10 (10) | 3.1 (4.03) |
References
- Knight, F.H. Risk, Uncertainty and Profit; Houghton Mifflin: Boston, MA, USA, 1921. [Google Scholar]
- Keynes, J.M. A Treatise on Probability; MacMillan and Co.: London, UK, 1921. [Google Scholar]
- Ellsberg, D. Risk, ambiguity and the Savage axioms. Q. J. Econ. 1961, 75, 643–669. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Einhorn, H.J.; Hogarth, R.M. Ambiguity and uncertainty in probabilistic inference. Psychol. Rev. 1985, 92, 433–446. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Schmeidler, D. Subjective probability and expected utility without additivity. Econometrica 1989, 57, 571–587. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gilboa, I.; Schmeidler, D. Maxmin expected utility with non–unique prior. J. Math. Econ. 1989, 18, 141–153. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Camerer, C.F.; Weber, M. Recent developments in modeling preferences: Uncertainty and ambiguity. J. Risk Uncertain. 1992, 8, 167–196. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Brader, T.; Marcus, G.E. Emotion and political psychology. In The Oxford Handbook of Political Psychology, 2nd ed.; Huddy, L., Sears, D.O., Levy, J.S., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2013; Chapter 6; pp. 165–205. [Google Scholar]
- Tversky, A.; Kahneman, D. Advances in prospect theory: Cumulative representation of uncertainty. J. Risk Uncertain. 1992, 5, 297–323. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Heath, F.; Tversky, A. Preference and belief: Uncertainty and competence in choice under uncertainty. J. Risk Uncertain. 1991, 4, 4–28. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wu, G.; Gonzales, R. Curvature of the probability weighting function. Manag. Sci. 1996, 42, 1676–1690. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wu, G.; Gonzales, R. Nonlinear decision weights in choice under uncertainty. Manag. Sci. 1999, 45, 74–85. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Abdellaoui, M. Parameter–free elicitation of utility and probability weighting functions. Manag. Sci. 2000, 46, 1497–1512. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kilka, M.; Weber, M. What determines the shape of the probability weighting function under uncertainty? Manag. Sci. 2001, 47, 1712–1726. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Fox, C.R.; Weber, M. Ambiguity aversion, comparative ignorance, and decision context. Organ. Behav. Hum. Decis. Process. 2002, 88, 476–498. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- de Lara Resende, J.G.; Wu, G. Competence effects for choices involving gains and losses. J. Risk Uncertain. 2010, 40, 109–132. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Baillon, A.; Bleichrodt, H. Testing ambiguity models through the measurement of probabilities for gains and losses. Am. Econ. J. Microecon. 2015, 7, 77–100. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Abdellaoui, M.; Baillon, A.; Placido, L.; Wakker, P.P. The rich domain of uncertainty: Source functions and their experimental implementation. Am. Econ. Rev. 2011, 101, 695–723. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Loewenstein, G.F.; Hsee, C.K.; Weber, E.U.; Weich, N. Risk as feelings. Psychol. Bull. 2001, 127, 267–286. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Loomes, G.; Sugden, R.F. Regret theory: An alternative theory of rational choice under uncertainty. Econ. J. 1982, 92, 805–824. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Loomes, G.; Sugden, R.F. Disappointment and dynamic consistency in choice under uncertainty. Rev. Econ. Stud. 1986, 53, 271–282. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rick, S.; Loewenstein, G. The role of emotion in economic behaviour. In Handbook of Emotions, 3rd ed.; Lewis, M., Haviland–Jones, M., Barrett, L.F., Eds.; The Guilford Press: New York, NY, USA, 2008; Chapter 9; pp. 138–156. [Google Scholar]
- Rottenstreich, Y.; Hsee, C.K. Money, kisses, and electric shocks: On the affective psychology of risk. Psychol. Sci. 2001, 12, 185–190. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Ditto, P.H.; Pizarro, D.A.; Epstein, E.B.; Jacobson, J.A.; MacDonald, T.K. Visceral influences on risk–taking behavior. J. Behav. Decis. Mak. 2006, 19, 99–113. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Loewenstein, G.F.; O’Donoghue, T.; Bhatia, S. Modeling the interplay between affect and deliberation. Decision 2015, 2, 55–81. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Damasio, H.; Grabowski, T.; Frank, R.; Galaburda, A.M.; Damasio, A.R. The return of Phineas Gage: Clues about the brain from the skull of a famous patient. Science 1994, 264, 1102–1105. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Bechara, A. The role of emotion in decision–making: Evidence from neurological patients with orbifrontal damage. Brian Cogn. 2004, 55, 33–40. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Slovic, P.; Finucane, M.L.; Peters, E.; MacGregor, D.G. Risk as analysis and risk as feelings: Some thoughts about affect, reason, risk, and rationality. Risk Anal. 2004, 24, 311–322. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Schwarz, N. Feelings–as–information theory. In Handbook of Theories of Social Psychology; Van Lange, P., Kruglanski, A., Higgings, E.T., Eds.; Sage Publications: London, UK, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Baillon, A.; Koellinger, P.D.; Treffers, T. Sadder but wiser: The effects of emotional states on ambiguity attitudes. J. Econ. Psychol. 2016, 53, 67–82. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Schlösser, T.; Dunning, D.; Fetchenhauer, D. What a feeling: The role of immediate and anticipated emotions in risky decisions. J. Behav. Decis. Mak. 2013, 26, 13–30. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Li, Z.; Müller, J.; Wakker, P.P.; Wang, T.V. The rich domain of ambiguity explored. Manag. Sci. 2018, 64, 3227–3240. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Fox, C.R.; Tversky, A. Ambiguity aversion and comparative ignorance. Q. J. Econ. 1995, 110, 585–603. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tversky, A.; Fox, C.R. Weighing risk and uncertainty. Psychol. Rev. 1995, 102, 269–283. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Keppe, H.; Weber, M. Judged knowledge and uncertainty aversion. Theory Decis. 1995, 39, 51–77. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Fox, C.R.; Tversky, A. A belief–based account of decision under uncertainty. Manag. Sci. 1998, 44, 879–895. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Di Mauro, C.; Maffioletti, A. The valuation of insurance under uncertainty: Does information about probability matter? Geneva Pap. Risk Insur. Theory 2001, 26, 195–224. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Chew, S.H.; Li, K.K.; Chark, R.; Zhong, S. Source preference and ambiguity aversion: Models and evidence from behavioral and neuroimaging experiments. In Neuroeconomics: Advances in Health Economics and Health Services Research; Houser, D., McCabe, K., Eds.; Emerald Group Publishing Limited: Bingley, UK, 2008; Volume 20, pp. 179–201. [Google Scholar]
- Machina, M.J.; Schmeidler, D. A more robust definition of subjective probability. Econometrica 1992, 60, 745–780. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Fox, C.R.; Rogers, B.A.; Tversky, A. Option traders exhibit subadditive decision weights. J. Risk Uncertain. 1996, 13, 5–17. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wakker, P.P. On the composition of risk preference and belief. Psychol. Bull. 2004, 111, 236–241. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Becker, G.M.; DeGroot, M.H.; Marschak, J. Stochastic models of choice behavior. Behav. Sci. 1963, 8, 41–55. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wakker, P.P.; Deneffe, D. Eliciting von Neumann–Morgenstern utilities when probabilities are distorted or unknown. Manag. Sci. 1996, 42, 1131–1150. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Abdellaoui, M.; Vossmann, F.; Weber, M. Choice–based elicitation and decomposition of decision weights for gains and losses under uncertainty. Manag. Sci. 2005, 51, 1384–1399. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Booji, A.S.; van Praag, B.M.; van de Kuilen, G. A parametric analysis of Prospect Theory’s functionals for the general popolation. Theory Decis. 2010, 68, 115–148. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Fox, C.R.; Rottenstreich, Y. Partition priming in judgement under uncertainty. Psychol. Sci. 2003, 14, 195–200. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- See, K.E.; Fox, C.R.; Rottenstreich, Y.S. Between ignorance and truth: Partition dependence and learning in judgment under uncertainty. J. Exp. Psychol. Learn. Mem. Cogn. 2006, 32, 1385–1402. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Newell, J.L.; Bull, M.J. Italian politics after the 2001 general election: Plus Ça Chang, Plus C'est La Même Chose? Parliam. Aff. 2002, 55, 626–642. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hix, S.; Marsh, M. Punishment or protest? Understanding European parliamentary elections. J. Politics 2007, 69, 495–510. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Newell, J.L. Italy. Political Insight 2013, 4, 26–29. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Chiaramonte, A.; Emanuele, V.; Maggini, N.; Paparo, A. Populist success in a hung parliament: The 2018 general election in Italy. South Eur. Soc. Politics 2018, 23, 479–501. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dimmock, S.G.; Kouwenberg, R.; Wakker, P.P. Ambiguity attitudes in a large representative sample. Manag. Sci. 2016, 62, 1363–1380. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
1 | |
2 | |
3 | At the individual level, the proportion of subjects showing linearity of the value function (i.e., reporting the expected value for at least one of the two matching lotteries), ranged from 66% (14 subjects in Milan 3) to 31% (10 subjects in Milan 2). |
4 | Wilcoxon signed-rank tests for pairs of dependent samples rejected the null hypothesis that reaction to ambiguity was independent of the number of events into which the state space was divided. This result can be taken as evidence of a “partition dependency” effect, a well-documented effect in the literature. (Fox and Rottenstreich, 2003 [46]; See et al. 2006 [47]) In fact, in our experiments preference for ambiguity decreased when the number of state partitions decreased. |
5 | Table A4 in Appendix A describes in detail the seven tests of LSA and the three tests of USA. |
6 | Table A5 in Appendix A shows that no less than 68% of the subjects satisfied BA at median values in each experiment. |
7 | Finding that LSA had more impact than USA was consistent with our previous result that the median sum of decision weights for complementary events was greater than unity in Alessandria, Milan 1 and Milan 3. For Milan 2, this effect was weaker, and Table 3 validates this finding. |
8 | The descriptive statistics for emotion and knowledge in the four experiments are reported in Table A6 in Appendix A. |
9 | Individual controls included the subject’s Age and the following dummy variables (when applicable): Male (Male = 1 and Female = 0); Graduate (equal to 1 for a graduate student, and equal to zero otherwise); and Italian (equal to 1 if the subject is Italian and equal to zero otherwise). |
10 | We used the value of 1 for individual observations associated with a given state partition and the value of zero otherwise. |
11 | Due to the presence of multiple observations for each individual, Table 4 uses robust standard errors that account for both clustering and potential heterogeneity by subjects. |
12 | Similar results, not reported in Table 4, hold when using net affect or the level of satisfaction. |
13 | Seven tests for LSA, and three tests for USA, see Table A4 in Appendix A for definitions. |
14 | For decision weights in Milan 1 and Alessandria, the space partition dummies were as follows. For the LSA tests, Test1 = 1 if the individual observation refers to partition A+B-I (no better than the highest vote share predicted by polls) and zero otherwise; Test2 = 1 for B+C-E, I+C-F, A+E-F (in the range of vote share predicted by polls) and zero otherwise; Test3 = 1 for C+D-H (better vote share than predicted by polls) and zero otherwise; Test 4 = 1 for E+D-G, B+H-G (vote share higher than the worse result predicted by polls). The dummies for Milan 2 were as follows: Test 1 = 1 for A+B-I (no better than the highest vote share predicted by polls) and zero otherwise; Test 2 = 1 for B+C-E, I+C-F, A+E-F (in the range of vote share predicted by polls) and zero otherwise; Test 3 = 1 for C+D-H and zero otherwise; Test 4 = 1 E+D-G, B+H-G (almost sure vote share). The dummies for Milan 3 were as follows: Test 1 = 1 for A+B-I and zero otherwise (no better than the highest vote share predicted by polls); Test 2 = 1 for B+C-E, C+D-H, I+C-F and A+E-F and zero otherwise (in the range of vote share predicted by polls); Test 3 = 1 for E+D-G and zero otherwise (better vote share than predicted by polls); Test 4 = 1 for B+H-G and zero otherwise (almost sure share of votes). For USA tests, the dummies were Part 1 = 1 for 1-G-I+B and zero otherwise; Part 2 = 1 for 1-G-F+E and zero otherwise; Part 3 = 1 for 1-H-F+G and zero otherwise. |
15 | Results for JPUSA are not shown. |
16 |
Pricing Question | Judgment of Probability Question |
---|---|
On Sunday the 4 March 2018, the Italian general elections will be held. You own a ticket of the following lottery: You win €60 if the Centre-Right coalition (Forza Italia-Berlusconi, Lega-Salvini premier, Fratelli d’Italia-Meloni, Noi con l’Italia-UDC) wins X% of the votes at the national level for the Chamber of Deputies, otherwise you win nothing. What is the minimum selling price at which you are willing to sell your lottery ticket? Price= | On Sunday the 4 March 2018, the Italian general elections will be held. The Centre-Right coalition (Forza Italia-Berlusconi, Lega-Salvini premier, Fratelli d’Italia-Meloni, Noi con l’Italia-UDC) wins X% of the votes at the national level for the Chamber of Deputies. Probability estimate= |
The target events X% were as follows: A = less than 35% [or between 0% (included) and 35% (excluded)]; B = between 35% (included) and 38% (excluded); C = between 38% (included) and 40% (excluded); D = at least 40% [or between 40% and 100% (both included)]; E = between 35% (included) and 40% (excluded); F = less than 40% [or between 0% (included) and 40% (excluded)]; G = at least 35% [or between 35% and 100% (both included)]; H = at least 38% [or between 38% and 100% (both included)]; I = less than 38% [or between 0% and 38% (excluded)] |
Additivity Tests | Space Partitions | Median Sum of Decision Weights | Median Sum of Judgmental Probabilities | ||||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
(a) | (b) | (c) | (d) | (e) | (f) | (g) | (h) | ||
Milan 1 N = 35 | Alessandria N = 31 | Milan 2 N = 32 | Milan 3 N = 21 | Milan 1 N = 35 | Alessandria N = 31 | Milan 2 N = 32 | Milan 3 N = 21 | ||
Tertiary additivity | A + B + C + D | 1.83 | 2 | 1.63 | 1.7 | 1.7 | 1.75 | 1.5 | 1.7 |
A + B + H | 1.42 | 1.67 | 1.33 | 1.39 | 1.2 | 1.4 | 1.3 | 1.45 | |
A + E + D | 1.5 | 1.67 | 1.33 | 1.42 | 1.2 | 1.38 | 1.3 | 1.4 | |
C + D + I | 1.54 | 1.58 | 1.33 | 1.5 | 1.7 | 1.35 | 1.33 | 1.29 | |
Binary Complementarity | A + G | 1.08 | 1.17 | 1.03 | 1.08 | 0.9 | 1 | 1 | 1.15 |
F + D | 1.08 | 1.17 | 1 | 1 | 1.15 | 1 | 1 | 1.1 | |
H + I | 1.17 | 1.33 | 1 | 1.08 | 1.15 | 1 | 1 | 1.1 |
Milan 1 | Alessandria | Milan 2 | Milan 3 | |
---|---|---|---|---|
Decision weights | wlsa = 0.42 wusa = 0.25 sw = 0.33 | wlsa = 0.33 wusa = 0.17 sw = 0.42 | wlsa = 0.17 wusa = 0.28 sw = 0.33 | wlsa = 0.33 wusa = 0.25 sw = 0.42 |
Judgmental probabilities | jlsa = 0.3 jusa = 0.2 sj = 0.45 | jlsa = 0.3 jusa = 0.25 sj = 0.35 | jlsa = 0.24 jusa = 0.2 sj = 0.5 | jlsa = 0.3 jusa = 0.2 sj = 0.57 |
Milan 1 (a) DW-JP | Milan 1 (b) DW-JP | Alessandria (c) DW-JP | Alessandria (d) DW-JP | Milan 2 (e) DW-JP | Milan2 (f) DW-JP | Milan3 (g) DW-JP | Milan3 (h) DW-JP | |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Positive emotions | 0.0252 [0.0251] | -------- | 0.0254 [0.0304] | ---------- | −0.0127 [0.0442] | ----------- | −0.095 [0.0578] | ---------- |
Negative emotions | ---------- | −0.0266 [0.0252] | ----------- | −0.0073 [0.0281] | ----------- | 0.0727 * [0.0440] | --------- | 0.05389 [0.0459] |
Knowledge | 0.0667 * [0.0351] | 0.0788 ** [0.0387] | 0.0439 [0.0419] | 0.0327 [0.0452] | 0.0878 ** [0.0383] | 0.0925 ** [0.0460] | −0.074 ** [0.0348] | −0.0709 * [0.0379] |
Age | −0.0159 [0.0152] | −0.0203 [0.0147] | −0.0387 ** [0.0170] | −0.0449 ** [0.0202] | −0.0140 [0.0120] | −0.0216 ** [0.0096] | 0.076 [0.0786] | 0.0544 [0.0913] |
Male | −0.2830 * [0.1660] | −0.2907 * [0.1695] | 0.2198 [0.1897] | 0.2901 [0.2100] | −0.3797 * [0.2255] | −0.4618 ** [0.2159] | 0.0187 [0.1904] | −0.0422 [0.2259] |
Graduate | ---------- | ---------- | ---------- | ---------- | ---------- | ---------- | 0.3916 [0.3488] | 0.4805 [0.4429] |
Italian | ---------- | ---------- | ---------- | ---------- | ---------- | ---------- | 0.3125 * [0.1803] | 0.2961 * [0.1678] |
Constant | 0.0691 [0.4920] | 0.3645 [0.3654] | 0.7862 ** [0.4441] | 1.0523 * [0.4853] | 0.2212 [0.3293] | −0.1032 [1.3923] | −1.7559 [1.7497] | −1.8442 [1.8403] |
Space partition | YES | YES | YES | YES | YES | YES | YES | YES |
N subj | 35 | 35 | 31 | 30 | 32 | 31 | 21 | 21 |
N obs | 245 | 245 | 217 | 210 | 224 | 217 | 147 | 147 |
R-squared | 0.1955 | 0.1976 | 0.13 | 0.1336 | 0.1847 | 0.2775 | 0.262 | 0.225 |
Wald Chi2 (10) | 44.83 | 46.05 | 35.95 | 34.13 | 25.35 | 21.68 | 48.39 | 43.59 |
Milan 1 (a) WLSA | Milan 1 (b) WLSA | Milan 1 (c) WUSA | Milan 1 (d) JPLSA | Aless. (e) WLSA | Aless. (f) WLSA | Aless. (g) WUSA | Aless. (h) JPLSA | |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Positive emots | 0.021 ** [0.008] | -------- | 0.004 [0.017] | −0.001 [0.012] | 0.022 ** [0.011] | ----- | −0.001 [0.017] | 0.012 [0.011] |
Negative emots | --------- | −0.016 * [0.009] | ---------- | ---------- | ---------- | −0.004 [0.011] | ----------- | ------------ |
Knowled. | 0.028 ** [0.012] | 0.032 ** [0.013] | −0.005 [0.033] | −0.021 [0.021] | 0.037 *** [0.014] | 0.029 [0.020] | 0.039 [0.027] | −0.006 [0.015] |
Age | 0.004 [0.005] | −0.000 [0.007] | 0.006 [0.008] | 0.006 [0.008] | −0.025 *** [0.008] | −0.032 *** [0.008] | −0.005 [0.009] | −0.006 [0.006] |
Male | −0.099 * [0.056] | −0.1098 * [0.057] | 0.092 [0.134] | −0.012 [0.069] | 0.034 [0.067] | 0.082 [0.069] | −0.090 [0.106] | −0.126 * [0.076] |
Constant | 0.078 [0.193] | 0.327 * [0.196] | 0.083 [0.280] | 0.050 [0.266] | 0.758 *** [0.178] | 0.995 *** [0.213] | 0.103 [0.237] | 0.585 *** [0.169] |
Test Dummies | YES | YES | YES | YES | YES | YES | YES | YES |
N Subj | 35 | 35 | 35 | 35 | 31 | 30 | 31 | 31 |
N obs | 245 | 245 | 105 | 245 | 217 | 210 | 93 | 217 |
R-squared | 0.107 | 0.086 | 0.025 | 0.09 | 0.165 | 0.149 | 0.55 | 0.081 |
Wald Chi2 | 21.41 [7] | 15.59 [7] | 2.71 [6] | 39.54 [7] | 40.35 [7] | 28.32 [7] | 5.83 [6] | 8.97 [7] |
Milan 2 (a) WLSA | Milan 2 (b) WLSA | Milan 2 (c) WUSA | Milan 2 (d) JPLSA | Milan 3 (e) WLSA | Milan 3 (f) WUSA | Milan 3 (g) WUSA | Milan 3 (h) JPLSA | |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Positive emots | −0.004 [0.012] | -------- | 0.044 [0.046] | −0.011 [0.013] | −0.048 * [0.0276] | 0.072 *** [0.016] | ----------- | −0.017 [0.018] |
Negative emots | --------- | 0.014 [0.013] | ---------- | ---------- | ---------- | --------- | −0.055 *** [0.0168] | ------------ |
Knowled. | 0.046 *** [0.013] | 0.050 *** [0.015] | 0.044 [0.046] | 0.026 ** [0.013] | 0.001 [0.014] | 0.055 *** [0.017] | 0.060 *** [0.0164] | 0.0278 ** [0.012] |
Age | −0.01 *** [0.003] | −0.011 *** [0.003] | 0.011 [0.014] | −0.007 * [0.004] | 0.025 [0.026] | −0.048 [0.043] | −0.016 [0.039] | −0.022 [0.029] |
Male | −0.263 *** [0.071] | −0.273 *** [0.074] | 0.125 [0.290] | −0.158 * [0.089] | −0.045 [0.082] | −0.039 [0.113] | 0.061 [0.127] | −0.158 ** [0.066] |
Grads | ------- | ------ | -------- | ---------- | 0.005 [0.144] | −0.118 [0.159] | −0.292 [0.193] | −0.067 [0.131] |
Italian | -------- | ----------- | ---------- | ----------- | −0.057 [0.060] | −0.183 [0.140] | −0.195 [0.125] | −0.163 ** [0.072] |
Constant | 0.550 *** [0.128] | 0.453 *** [0.124] | 0.148 [0.512] | 0.410 *** [0.122] | −0.130 [0.610] | 1.206 [0.927] | 1.066 [0.880] | 1.034 [0.631] |
Test Dumm | YES | YES | YES | YES | YES | YES | YES | YES |
N subj | 32 | 31 | 31 | 32 | 21 | 21 | 21 | 21 |
N obs | 224 | 217 | 93 | 224 | 145 | 62 | 62 | 147 |
R-squared | 0.205 | 0.223 | 0.11 | 0.086 | 0.119 | 0.248 | 0.226 | 0.246 |
Wald Chi2 | 29.43 [7] | 28.7 [7] | 10.09 [6] | 13.98 [7] | 18.89 [9] | 80.32 [8] | 28.02 [8] | 51.99 [9] |
© 2019 by the authors. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Maffioletti, A.; Santoni, M. Emotion and Knowledge in Decision Making under Uncertainty. Games 2019, 10, 36. https://doi.org/10.3390/g10040036
Maffioletti A, Santoni M. Emotion and Knowledge in Decision Making under Uncertainty. Games. 2019; 10(4):36. https://doi.org/10.3390/g10040036
Chicago/Turabian StyleMaffioletti, Anna, and Michele Santoni. 2019. "Emotion and Knowledge in Decision Making under Uncertainty" Games 10, no. 4: 36. https://doi.org/10.3390/g10040036
APA StyleMaffioletti, A., & Santoni, M. (2019). Emotion and Knowledge in Decision Making under Uncertainty. Games, 10(4), 36. https://doi.org/10.3390/g10040036