1. Introduction
Consumers increasingly care about firms’ ethical conduct when making their consumption choices. Firm conduct particularly relevant to consumers includes firms’ environmental and labor practices (e.g., [
1,
2]). For example, the utilization of labor by many firms operating in the textile industry in Asia does not live up to Western ethical standards (though it may be in compliance with legal standards in the countries in question), possibly provoking consumer boycotts and the like.
1 As another example, the importance of
green consumers has led to a widespread use of eco-labeling in many countries. By handing out an eco-label, a third party certifies that the firm in question obeys the specific environmental standards that the third party stands for (e.g., [
3,
4]). The according literature deals with firms having selected
good technologies and seeking to credibly reveal their type to consumers, because this information can serve as a competitive advantage. In contrast, we are interested in firms possibly selecting
bad technologies and seeking to limit information about their choice, because it is better profit-wise for these firms to be pooled with other firm types.
Specifically, this note explores a setup in which a firm chooses between a
good and a
bad technology before deciding whether or not to conceal its choice from consumers. In reality, there are several avenues that firms may choose to make it difficult for consumers to infer their conduct. For instance, firms may choose to set-up or source from legal entities in foreign countries as their contractual input suppliers (thereby outsourcing morally questionable practices to a supplier network that is intransparent for the single consumer). According to an article by Mark Graham in
The Guardian published in 2010, [
5], the associated detachment of the material goods from the information about how they are produced allows firms to
conceal their production practices. It appears that Apple can serve as a case-in-point. It was argued, for example, that Apple sources from suppliers with very questionable practices and tries to hide detailed information about its supply chain.
2 Moreover, firms may attach greater importance to monitoring that employees keep information about production practices confidential. For example, factory campuses where Apple products are produced (i) are gated off and do not allow entry to the public, (ii) feature security guards to prevent trespassing, and (iii) require factory workers to sign confidentiality agreements and live in dormitories within the factory campuses (e.g., [
7]). Furthermore, firms may try to inconspicuously interfere with the work of NGOs trying to collect information about firm conduct.
3 1.1. Key Result
Consumers caring more about firm conduct can under certain circumstances induce a less desirable technology choice and a lower market transparency about production modes. Our key finding is the result of analyzing a very simple model in which a monopolistic firm chooses to adopt one of two technologies and whether or not to conceal its technology choice from morally conscious consumers. We derive the counterintuitive result subject to two key assumptions: First, some firms use the desirable technology even without being able to verify their technology to consumers, implying that the conduct of firms without certified production technologies is on average reasonably good. Second, the profit function of the firm must be strictly concave in the consumers’ consciousness, signifying diminishing returns to ethical conduct in terms of profits.
1.2. Related Literature
This note contributes to the literature by highlighting potentially adverse consequences (in terms of technologies adopted and information about modes of production available) resulting from consumers’ increased care about firm conduct. We allow for the option of concealing one’s technology choice from interested agents—an adverse act that was (to the best of our knowledge) not previously considered in the related literature.
The idea that consumers care about the environmental footprint of the firm’s production or product is well-established in environmental economics. Tietenberg ([
8]) considers the use of information as “the third wave” of pollution control (after legal regulation as the first wave and market-based instruments as the second wave). In this line of research, Eriksson ([
9]), for example, is interested in whether or not green consumerism can actually replace regulation. Similar to our approach, Doni and Ricchiuti ([
10]) point out that very high consumer consciousness need not serve welfare. However, in their setup, this results from the possibility of an overprovision of environmental quality. In much of this literature, the firms’ environmental quality is common knowledge (in contrast to our assumption about the possibility of concealment). Sengupta ([
11]) presents a paper in which consumers’ information about the actual production technology of firms is imperfect, thereby explicitly acknowledging the facts about global supply chains, for example, that we also rely upon for our motivation. The author is concerned with the desirability of mandatory disclosure when duopolists both know about the environmental consciousness of consumers and are subject to strict environmental liability. Our setup is much simpler and abstracts from competition or institutions such as liability. The interaction of competition and environmental consciousness has been considered in a number of papers, often using a vertical product differentiation setup (e.g., [
1,
12]).
4 Our research is also related to contributions in the law and economics literature about the comparison of mandatory and voluntary disclosure rules ([
13,
14]) and about the voluntary sharing of information prior to trial [
15]. In addition, in the management literature, corporate social responsibility has also received a great deal of attention (e.g., [
19]). Finally, whereas our paper is concerned with the concealment of information, there is of course literature addressing outright dishonesty in other domains (e.g., [
20] in the domain of advertising).
The rest of the paper is structured as follows.
Section 2 lays out the simple model, the brief analysis of which is presented in
Section 3.
Section 4 concludes.
2. The Model
Assume that a monopolistic firm can choose from two production technologies: a “good” one indexed by a responsibility parameter
and a “bad” one indexed by a responsibility parameter
, where
.
5 The bad technology is available at no cost. The firm’s fixed cost from adopting the good technology is a random variable
c, with
according to the cumulative distribution function
(as is assumed in, e.g., [
21]). There is a probability
that the firm will adopt the good technology out of its own moral concerns as long as the adoption costs are less than
(this is similar to, e.g., [
22]).
Consumers care about the firm’s production technology; the extent of caring is represented by a weight
. We assume that the firm chooses profit-maximizing behavior given the consumers’ beliefs about technology and their extent of caring, and represent parameterized maximal firm profits by
with
, assuming that
.
6 How marginal profits change with the level of
R will depend on the specifics of the setup considered. Assume, for instance, that a monopolist with marginal production costs set equal to zero faces a demand
, where the consumers’ beliefs about the firm’s conduct influences the prohibitive price
a. The monopolist sets profit-maximizing prices
, yielding maximal profits
. We find that
follows from
. Thus, firm profits may be either concave or convex in the level of
R.
Although consumers care about the firm’s mode of production, they may not be able to observe it. In this case, they make a rational (Bayesian) inference about it. We assume that the firm cannot credibly establish its mode of production with probability
, and that it can choose to conceal it in the state that occurs with probability
(i.e., when it could establish it in principle).
7 All firm types whose technology cannot be observed by consumers form the set denoted
N. The expected value of responsibility for any firm from this set will be denoted by
. As a result, any firm in the set
N will earn profits
.
The timing of the model is such that nature first draws the firm’s level of adoption cost, the firm’s type with respect to whether the firm will adopt the good technology out of moral concerns, and whether or not it can credibly inform consumers about its mode of production. Next, the firm chooses between adopting the good technology and adopting the bad one, and whether or not to conceal its choice from consumers. Consumers next make their consumption choices. When consumers cannot observe the firm’s technology, they use their beliefs about the firm’s conduct.
8 3. The Analysis
There are three different profit levels in our framework. A firm who cannot or does not want to make its type known earns . A firm whose technology is observed earns either (when the firm adopts the good technology) or (when the firm adopts the bad technology). Since , all firms who ultimately choose the bad technology will conceal this fact. For firms whose type can principally be observed, the choice is thus between (i) adopting the good technology and (ii) adopting the bad technology while concealing this fact from consumers.
A firm whose technology cannot be credibly revealed to consumers for exogenous reasons may be a firm who adopted the good technology out of its own moral concerns or a firm who picked the bad technology. The probability that a firm adopted the good technology out of its own moral concerns amounts to
. As a result, a firm whose type cannot be observed for exogenous reasons has an expected type of
A firm that can principally establish the technology in use may nevertheless choose to conceal it. We assume that there is a level of the fixed adoption cost
that leads to
that is, that induces indifference on the part of the firm with this level of adoption cost between the option of adopting the good technology and the alternative of adopting the bad technology and concealing this fact. A firm with adoption costs
will conceal its type such that consumers’ inference about the firm’s technology leads to the consumers’ belief
with the intuitive association regarding how the belief changes with the level of the fixed adoption costs of the indifferent firm
The higher the critical level of adoption costs
, the more likely it is that a firm in set
N did not actively choose to conceal its technology, and therefore a higher weight is attached to the expected technology
instead of
. Equations (
2) and (
3) together establish the equilibrium values of
and
.
We now turn to our central interest—that is, the impact of an increase in consumers’ caring for firm conduct (as represented by an increase in the level of
). Our key research question is whether greater environmental consciousness of consumers may induce the firm to adopt the bad technology and conceal this fact instead of adopting the good technology. In order to investigate this issue, we return to condition (
2).
To sharpen our intuition before we consider the details, note that a marginal increase in means a greater influence of consumers’ caring on firm profits. For the marginal firm with , adopting and concealing the technology means relatively lower consumers’ beliefs when compared to adopting the good technology (since ), but also the saving of fixed adoption cost. The difference in consumers’ beliefs () is more pronounced in terms of its influence on the level of R at a higher level of . However, for the firm’s choice between whether or not to adopt the good technology, it is key whether the influence of R on the firm’s profits becomes more or less important (i.e., whether marginal profits from a higher level of r—namely, —are increasing or decreasing with R). This results from the fact that the firm has to compare the change in profits from implementing instead of at higher levels of R due to the increase in .
To be precise, taking account of (
3), the total differential of (
2) is
Since
, we thus obtain
when
or, stated alternatively as
Consumers’ greater consciousness induces a greater utilization of the bad technology when
. It is clear from (
6) that
is a necessary condition for this possibility to arise. In other words, consumers must think that silent firms are on average responsible firms (such that the profit of firms in set
N is increasing in
). In our setup, it is not necessarily true that
holds, because the use of the bad technology is associated with
. In addition,
is bounded from above by
. Assumptions about both the probability of the occurrence of moral concerns in firms (i.e., the level of
) and the extent to which they are important (i.e., the level of
m), and about the probability that a firm cannot credibly transmit information about the technology (i.e., the level of
k) are key influences on the level of
. When both
and
k are sufficiently high, the condition
will be obtained.
9 Moreover, an additional necessary condition for the counterintuitve result of greater consumer caring inducing a lower threshold
is that firm profits must be concave in the level of
R. This effects that
applies. In (
7), strict concavity ensures that the right-hand side is less than one. Finally, condition (
7) makes it clear that the concavity of
must be strong enough to outweigh the fact that
. In contrast, strict convexity of the profit function suffices to unambiguously deliver the opposite prediction; that is, the intuitive prediction saying that greater consciousness leads to better technology choices and more transparency.
We summarize our key result as follows:
Result:
(i) If condition (7) holds (which necessitates and ), then a marginal increase in consumers’ caring about firm conduct induces less desirable technology choices and lower market transparency (by lowering the level of ); (ii) If either applies or and/or k are relatively low (implying ), then condition (7) cannot hold and a marginal increase in consumers’ caring about firm conduct induces a more desirable technology choice and higher market transparency (by increasing the level of ). Let us briefly consider a very simple example only to illustrate the mentioned possibility of . Assume that the firm faces one consumer who buys at most one unit of the product and whose willingness to pay amounts to , where . Maximal profits are equal to the consumer’s willingness to pay minus production costs. The quadratic specification of the consumer’s willingness to pay implies a strictly concave profit function. In this case, assuming , , , and , we find that indeed for , whereas for .