2. Covering Properties
In this section, we mainly use q-open sets and u-open sets in BGTSs to introduce and study certain covering concepts in BGTSs. Related to the new covering concepts we will give characterizations, implications, and examples.
Definition 1 ([
16]).
Let be a BGTS. A subset A of X is said to be quasi-open (q-open) if for all there exists a μ-open set U, such that , or there exists a σ-open set V, such that . The family of all q-open sets in will be denoted by . A subset A of X is said to be quasi-closed (q-closed) if the complement of A is q-open. Theorem 1 ([
16]).
Let be a BGTS and . Subsequently, A is q-open of if and only if where and . Theorem 2 ([
16]).
Let be a BGTS. Then is a GT on X. Finite intersection of
q-open sets of a BGTS need not to be
q-open in general [
15]:
Example 1. In where and the sets and are q-open sets, but is not q-open.
Theorem 3 ([
16]).
Let be a BGTS and . Afterwards, B is q-closed of if and only if where is σ-closed and W is δ-closed. Definition 2. A subset B of a BGTS is called u-open if . The family of all u-open sets in will be denoted by .
Theorem 4. Let be a BGTS and . Then .
Proof. Let . Then or . Since and , then by Theorem 1, we have . ☐
Theorem 5. Let be a BGTS. Then is the smallest GT on X containing both μ and σ.
Proof. By Theorem 2, is a GT on X. Because and and by Theorem 4, , then containing both and . Let be a GT on X containing and , and let . By Theorem 1, , where and . Because and then and , and, hence, . Thus . ☐
Definition 3 ([
17]).
Let be a GTS.- (a)
A collection of subsets of X is said to be a σ-cover of X if the union of the elements of is equal to X.
- (b)
A σ-subcover of a σ-cover is a subcollection of which itself is a σ-cover.
- (c)
A σ-cover of X is said to be σ-open cover if the elements of are σ-open subsets of X.
- (d)
A σ-subcover of a σ-open cover is a subcollection of which itself is a σ-open cover.
Definition 4. Let be a BGTS.
- (a)
A collection of subsets of X is called a cover of X if the union of the elements of is equal to X.
- (b)
A sub-cover of a cover of X is a subcollection of , which itself is a cover of X.
- (c)
A cover of X is called q-open cover if .
- (d)
A cover of X is called u-open cover if .
- (e)
A u-open cover of X is called p-open cover if and .
Definition 5. A GTS is said to be σ-Lindelöf if each σ-open cover of X has a countable subcover.
Definition 6. Let be a BGTS. Subsequently,
- (a)
is called q-Lindelöf if every q-open cover of X has a countable sub-cover.
- (b)
is called u-Lindelöf if every -open cover of X has a countable sub-cover.
- (c)
is called p-Lindelöf if every p-open cover of X has a countable sub-cover.
- (d)
is called s-Lindelöf if is μ-Lindelöf and is σ-Lindelöf.
Theorem 6. A BGTS is q-Lindelöf if and only if it is u-Lindelöf.
Proof. Suppose is q-Lindelöf and let be a u-open cover of X. Subsequently, by Theorem 4, is a q-open cover of X. Since is a q-Lindelöf, has a countable subcover. Therefore, is u-Lindelöf.
Conversely, suppose that is u-Lindelöf and be a q-open cover of X. For every , by Theorem 1, there exists and such that . Set . Afterwards, is a u-open cover of X. By u-Lindelöfeness of , there exist countable sets where is a countable sub-cover of . It is not difficult to check that is a countable sub-cover of . Thus, is q-Lindelöf. ☐
Theorem 7. Every u-Lindelöf BGTS is s-Lindelöf.
Proof. Let be a u-Lindelöf BGTS.
is -Lindelöf: let be a -open cover of X. By u-Lindelöfeness of , there is countable subcover of . Hence, is -Lindelöf.
The proof that is -Lindelöf is similar to that used in the proof of is -Lindelöf. ☐
Theorem 8. Every u-Lindelöf BGTS is p-Lindelöf.
Proof. Let be a u-Lindelöf BGTS and let be a p-open cover of X. Then is a u-open cover of X. Since is a u-Lindelöf, has a countable subcover. Therefore, is p-Lindelöf. ☐
Theorem 9. Let be a BGTS. Then the following are equivalent:
- (a)
is σ-Lindelöf.
- (b)
is u-Lindelöf.
- (c)
is p-Lindelöf.
- (d)
is s-Lindelöf.
Proof. Straightforward. ☐
The following two examples will show that the concepts s-Lindelöf and p-Lindelöf are independent, and they will also show that the converse of each of Theorems 7 and 8 is not true in general:
Example 2. Consider the BGTS where and :
- (1)
is not p-Lindelöf and by Theorem 8, it is not u-Lindelöf: is a p-open cover of which has no countable sub-cover.
- (2)
is s-Lindelöf: let F be a μ-open cover of . Subsequently, and is a countable subcover of F. Therefore, is μ-Lindelof. Similarly, we can see that is σ-Lindelof.
Example 3. Consider the BGTS , where , and . Then is p-Lindelöf but not s-Lindelöf and by Theorem 7, it is not u-Lindelöf.
Proof. is p-Lindelöf: is p-compact: let be a p-open cover of . Because , or .
Case 1. . Subsequently, is a countable sub-cover of and we are done.
Case 2. and F. Choose , such that . Afterwards, and so is a countable sub-cover of .
is not s-Lindelof: is a -open cover of X, which has no countable subcover. This implies that is not -Lindelöf and, hence, is not s-Lindelöf. ☐
The converse of Theorem 7 is true for an s-Lindelöf BGTS, as in the following result:
Theorem 10. Let be a BGTS. Subsequently, the following are equivalent:
- (a)
is u-Lindelöf.
- (b)
is s-Lindelöf and p-Lindelöf.
Proof. (a) ⟹ (b) Theorems 7 and 8.
(b) ⟹ (a) Let be u-open cover of X. We have two cases:
Case 1. is a p-open cover of X. Subsequently, has a countable subcover of X because is p-Lindelöf.
Case 2. is not a p-open cover of X. Afterwards, is either a -open cover of X or a -open cover of X. Because is -Lindelöf and is -Lindelöf, in either of the two cases will have a countable subcover. ☐
Definition 7. A GTS is said to be σ-countably-compact if each countable σ-open cover of X has a finite subcover.
Definition 8. Let be a BGTS. Then
- (a)
is called q-countably-compact if every countable q-open cover of X has a finite subcover.
- (b)
is called u-countably-compact if every countable u-open cover of X has a finite subcover.
- (c)
is called p-countably-compact if every countable p-open cover of X has a finite subcover.
- (d)
is called s-countably-compact if is σ-countably-compact and is δ-countably-compact.
Theorem 11. A BGTS is q-countably-compact if and only if it is u-countably-compact.
Proof. Suppose that is q-countably-compact and let be a countable u-open cover of X. Afterwards, by Theorem 4, is a countable q-open cover of X. Since be a q-countably-compact, has a finite subcover. Therefore, is u-countably-compact.
Conversely, suppose that is u-countably-compact. Let be a countable q-open cover of X. By Theorem 1, for each , there is and , such that . Set . Afterwards, is a countable u-open cover of X. Since is u-countably-compact, there exist countable sets , such that is a finite sub-cover of . It is not difficult to check that is a finite subcover of . Thus, is q-countably-compact. ☐
Theorem 12. Every u-countably-compact BGTS is s-countably-compact.
Proof. Let be a u-countably-compact BGTS. To see that is -countably-compact, let be a countable -open cover of X. Subsequently, is a countable u-open cover of X. Because is u-countably-compact, has a finite sub-cover . Therefore, is a finite -sub-cover of . Hence, is -countably-compact.
The proof that is -countably-compact is similar to that used in the proof of is -countably-compact. ☐
Theorem 13. Every u-countably-compact BGTS is p-countably-compact.
Proof. Let be a u-countably-compact BGTS and let be a countable p-open cover of X. Subsequently, is a countable u-open cover of X. Because is u-countably-compact, has a finite sub-cover. Therefore, is p-countably-compact. ☐
Theorem 14. Let be a BGTS. Subsequently, the following are equivalent:
- (a)
is σ-countably-compact.
- (b)
is u-countably-compact.
- (c)
is p-countably-compact.
- (d)
If is s-countably-compact.
Proof. Straightforward. ☐
The following two examples will show that the concepts s-countably-compact and p-countably-compact are independent, and they will also show that the converse of each of Theorems 12 and 13 is not true in general:
Example 4. Let where E and O are the set of even natural numbers and the set of odd natural numbers, respectively. Consider the BGTS , where and . Subsequently,
- (1)
is not p-countably-compact and, by Theorem 13, it is not u-countably compact: is a countable p-open cover of X, which has no finite sub-cover.
- (2)
is s-countably compact: let be a countable σ-open cover X. Afterwards, and is a finite sub-cover of . Therefore, is σ-countably-compact. Similarly, we can see that is δ-countably-compact.
Example 5. Consider the BGTS , where X, as in Example 4, , and . Afterwards, is p-countably-compact, but not s-countably-compact and, by Theorem 13, it is not u-countably-compact.
Proof. is p-countably-compact: let be a countable p-open cover of X. Since , or .
Case 1.. Subsequently, is a finite sub-cover of and we are done.
Case 2. and . Choose , such that . Afterwards, and so is a finite subcover of .
is not s-countably-compact: is a countable -open cover of X, which has no finite sub-cover. This implies that is not -countably-compact and, hence, is not s-countably-compact. ☐
The converse of Theorem 13 is true for s-countably-compact BGTS, as in the following result:
Theorem 15. Let be a BGTS. Afterwards, the following are equivalent:
- (a)
is u-countably-compact.
- (b)
is s-countably-compact and p-countably-compact.
Proof. (a) ⟹ (b) Theorems 12 and 13.
(b) ⟹ (a) Let be a countable u-open cover of X. We have two cases:
Case 1. is a countable p-open cover of X. Afterwards, it has a finite subcover of X, because is p-countably-compact.
Case 2. is not a p-open cover of X. Subsequently, is either a countable -open cover of X or a countable -open cover of X. Because is -countably-compact and is -countably-compact, in either of the two cases will have a finite subcover. ☐
3. Continuity
In this section, we define two new concepts of continuity between BGTSs. We will give several relationships regarding the two new continuity concepts and an old continuity concept. We focus on continuity images of covering properties that are defined in
Section 2.
Definition 9 ([
18]).
A function is called -continuous if for all , . Definition 10. A function ⟶ is called
- (a)
q-continuous [16] if for all , . - (b)
u-continuous if for all , .
- (c)
s-continuous if ⟶ is -continuous and ⟶ is -continuous.
Theorem 16. For any function ⟶ between the BGTSs and , the following are equivalent:
- (a)
g is q-continuous.
- (b)
⟶ is -continuous.
- (c)
For all , .
Proof. (a) ⟺ (b) Obvious.
(a) ⟹ (c) Follows from the definition and Theorem 4.
(c) ⟸ (a) Suppose for all and let . By Theorem 1, where and . By assumption and . Thus, by Theorem 2, . Therefore, g is q-continuous. ☐
Corollary 1. u-continuous functions between BGTSs are q-continuous.
Proof. Follows from Theorems 2 and 16. ☐
The converse of Corollary 1 is not true in general, as can be seen from the following example:
Example 6. Let and . Define ⟶ by . Then
- (1)
g is q-continuous: let . Then Therefore, .
- (2)
g is not u-continuous: Since while .
Theorem 17. A function ⟶ is s-continuous if and only if for all and for all .
Proof. Straightforward. ☐
Corollary 2. s-continuous functions between BGTSs are u-continuous.
The converse of Corollary 2 is not true in general, as it can be seen from the following example:
Example 7. Let and . Define ⟶ by . Then
- (1)
g is u-continuous: let . Subsequently, .
- (2)
g is not s-continuous: since while , then ⟶ is not -continuous. Therefore, g is not s-continuous.
Theorem 18. The q-continuous image of a q-Lindelöf BGTS is q-Lindelöf.
Proof. Let
⟶
be
q-continuous and surjective with
is
q-Lindelöf. Let
be a
q-open cover of
Z. By
q-continuity of
g,
for all
. Put
. Because
then
is a
q-open cover of
Y. Since
is
q-Lindelöf
has a countable subcover
. Choose a countable collection
with
. By surjectivity of
gTherefore, is a countable sub-cover of and, hence, is q-Lindelöf. ☐
Corollary 3. The u-continuous image of a u-Lindelöf BGTS is u-Lindelöf.
Proof. Theorems 6 and 18, and Corollary 1. ☐
Theorem 19. The s-continuous image of a p-Lindelöf BGTS is p-Lindelöf.
Proof. Let
⟶
be
s-continuous and surjective with
is
p-Lindelöf. Let
be a
p-open cover of
Z. By Corollary 2,
g is
u-continuous. Therefore,
for all
. Put
. Since
then
is a
u-open cover of
Y. Since
is
p-open cover, there exist
and
. By
s-continuity of
g,
and
. By surjectivity of
g,
and
. Therefore,
is a
p-open cover of
Y. Since
is
p-Lindelöf
has a countable subcover
. There exists a countable subfamily
such that
. By surjectivity of
g,
Therefore, is a countable sub-cover of and, hence, is p-Lindelöf. ☐
Theorem 20. The q-continuous image of a q-countably-compact BGTS is q-countably-compact.
Proof. Let
⟶
be
q-continuous and surjective with
is
q-countably-compact. Let
be a countable
q-open cover of
Z. By
q-continuity of
g,
for all
. Put
. Because
then
is a countable
q-open cover of
Y. Since
is
q-countably-compact
has a finite subcover
. Choose a finite collection
with
. By surjectivity of
gTherefore, is a finite sub-cover of and, hence, is q-countably-compact. ☐
Corollary 4. The u-continuous image of a u-countably-compact BGTS is u-countably-compact.
Proof. Theorems 11 and 20, and Corollary 1. ☐
Theorem 21. The s-continuous image of a p-countably-compact BGTS is p-countably-compact.
Proof. Let
⟶
be
s-continuous and surjective with
is
p-countably-compact. Let
be a countable
p-open cover of
Z. By Corollary 2,
g is
u-continuous. Therefore,
for all
. Put
. Because
then
is a countable
u-open cover of
Y. Since
is
p-open cover, there exist
and
. By
s-continuity of
g,
and
. By the surjectivity of
g,
and
. Therefore,
is a countable
p-open cover of
Y. Because
is
p-countably-compact
has a finite subcover
. There exists a finite subfamily
such that
. By surjectivity of
g,
Therefore, is a finite subcover of and, hence, is p-countably-compact. ☐
4. Minimality
In this section, we define types of minimality in BGTSs, we give several relationships regarding them, and we focus on continuity images of each of them.
Definition 11 ([
18]).
A nonempty σ-open subset B of a GTS is said to be a minimal μ-open set if the only nonempty σ-open set, which is contained in B is B. Definition 12. Let be a BGTS and B a nonempty subset of Y. Subsequently, B is called a
- (a)
minimal q-open set if B is q-open and the only nonempty q-open set which is contained in B is B.
- (b)
minimal u-open set if B is u-open and the only nonempty u-open set that is contained in B is B.
- (c)
minimal s-open set if B is a minimal σ-open in and B is a minimal δ-open in .
Theorem 22. A subset B of a BGTS is a minimal q-open set if and only if it is a minimal -open set in .
Proof. Straightforward. ☐
Lemma 1. IfB is a minimal q-open set in a bi-generalized topological space , then .
Proof. By Theorem 1, where and . By Theorem 4, . Since and B is a minimal q-open set in , then or . Similarly, we can conclude that or . Since , or . Therefore, or . In both cases, . ☐
Theorem 23. Let be a BGTS and . Subsequently, B is a minimal q-open set if and only if B is a minimal u-open set.
Proof. Necessity. Suppose that B is a minimal q-open set. By Lemma 1, B is a nonempty u-open set. Let with . By Theorem 4, . Since B is minimal q-open, then . It follows that B is a minimal u-open set.
Sufficiency. Suppose that B is a minimal u-open set. Subsequently, by Theorem 4, B is a non-empty u-open set. Let with . Because C is q-open then, by Theorem 1, where and . Since , and B is a minimal u-open set, then or . Similarly, we can conclude that or . Because , or . Thus, or and, hence, . It follows that B is a minimal q-open set. ☐
Theorem 24. Let be a BGTS and . If B is a minimal s-open set, then B is a minimal u-open set.
Proof. Suppose that B is a minimal s-open set. Subsequently, B is nonempty and . Let with . Afterwards, or . If , then, as B is a minimal -open set, . If , then as B is a minimal -open set, . Therefore, B is a minimal u-open set. ☐
Remark 1. The converse of Theorem 24 is not true in general; indeed, in Example 3 is a minimal u-open set that is not a minimal s-open set.
Theorem 25. Let be a BGTS and B a minimal u-open set in . Then
- (a)
If , then B is a minimal σ-open set.
- (b)
If then B is a minimal δ-open set.
- (c)
If , then B is a minimal s-open set.
Proof. - (a)
Suppose that B is a minimal u-open set and . Let with . Since B is minimal u-open and with , then . Thus, B is a minimal -open set.
- (b)
Similar to the proof of (a).
- (c)
Follows from (a) and (b).
☐
Corollary 5. Let be a BGTS and . Subsequently, the following are equivalent:
- (a)
B is a minimal s-open set.
- (b)
B is a minimal u-open set.
Proof. (a) ⟹ (b) Theorem 24.
(b) ⟹ (a) Theorem 25 (c). ☐
Theorem 26. Let be injective and -continuous function. If B is a minimal σ-open set, such that , then is a minimal δ-open set.
Proof. Since , then . Suppose with . Then . Since g is injective, . Because g is -continuous and , then . As , . Because B is a minimal -open set, then . Thus, . Hence, . ☐
Corollary 6. Let ⟶ be injective and s-continuous function. If B is a minimal s-open set in with , then is a minimal s-open set in .
Theorem 27. Let ⟶ be injective and q-continuous function. If B is a minimal q-open set in with , then is a minimal q-open set in .
Proof. Since , then . Suppose with . Afterwards, . Because g is injective, . As g is q-continuous and , then . Because , . Since B is a minimal q-open set then . Thus, . Hence, . ☐
Corollary 7. Let ⟶ be injective and u-continuous function. If B is a minimal u-open set in with , then is a minimal u-open set in .
Proof. Corollary 1, Theorem 23 and Theorem 27. ☐