Tragedy, Tragic Irony, and War: A Dialectical Approach
Abstract
:1. The Idea of Tragedy and Its Ironies
1.1. Tragedies
“War is both father and king of all; some she has shown forth as gods and others as men, some he has made slaves and others free.”(Wheelwright 1999, p. 29, Heraclitus fragment 25)
“The stupidity which characterizes history’s peaks has no equivalent but the ineptitude of those who are its agents.”(Cioran 2010, p. 94; also Leskanich 2021)
1.2. Ironies and Rorty
The ironist’s preferred form of argument is dialectical in the sense that she takes the unit of persuasion to be a vocabulary rather than a proposition. Her method is redescription rather than inference. … I have defined (dialectic) as they attempt to play off vocabularies against one another. … Literary criticism does for ironists what the search for universal moral principles is supposed to do for metaphysicians.
1.3. The Idea of Tragic Irony
In Shakespeare’s King Lear, there is a scene that involves a very powerful use of dramatic irony. Gloucester, who has recently been cruelly blinded, wants to die. He asks Edgar to take him to the “very brim” of the cliffs of Dover, to “a cliff whose high and pending head. /Looks fearfully in the confined deep” (Act IV Scene i). Edgar misleads him into thinking that he has done just that. […] The audience knows that what Gloucester does not know: that, contrary to what he thinks, he is not on the edge of the cliffs of Dover, and thus not able with one step to cast himself over the edge to his certain death.(Goldie 2014, p. 27; also, Goldie 2007)
1.4. Hegel on Irony and the Cunning of Reason
(FR) Call it a disaster tragedy, and you are talking about tragic irony—because tragedy is ironic per definitionem. (Because tragedy is a disaster plus irony.)
(HTI) A Historic subject fails disastrously, which leads to unforeseen greater things where a higher value is revealed.
(CHR) An agent promotes her goals and, therefore, contributes to realizing higher, ideal goals.
Human beings least of all, sustain the bare external relation of mere means to the great ideal aim. Not only do they, in the very act of realizing it, make it the occasion of satisfying personal desires, whose purport is diverse from that aim—but they share in that ideal aim itself; and are, for that very reason, objects of their existence; not formally merely, as the world of living beings generally is—whose individual life is essentially subordinate to that of man, and is properly used up as an instrument. Men, on the contrary, are objects of existence to themselves, as regards the intrinsic import of the aim in question.(see also Forbes 1975, esp. pp. xv, xxviii)
2. Tragic Ironies of War
- Proposition one: If White had lost the war, they would have suffered less than they did as winners.
- Proposition two: Even if Red had won the war they started, they would not have benefited from it.
- Proposition three: Even if Red had won the war, which they started believing they could not win, they would not have benefited.
- Proposition four: Nothing good would have followed from victory, but total defeat was a blessing regardless of the degree of the disaster.
3. Controversy and Existential Beliefs
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
1 | |
2 | |
3 | |
4 | |
5 | On tragedy and tragical, see Szondi (1961). This fundamental work emphasizes that Aristotle defined (scripted) tragedy but Hegel, Schelling, etc. treated what is (non-scripted) tragic the first time. I cannot go deeper into this tradition emphasizing contradiction, dialectic, and the presentation of alterity that transcends rationality (Schelling, Hölderlin, Nietzsche, etc.). Many of my examples of war and peace implicitly return to these themes. See also, Eagleton (2020); de Beistegui and Sparks (2000). (Here I am grateful to an anonymous referee.) |
6 | The connection between Rortyan irony as dialectical redescription and metaphor is interesting, but I cannot go into details here. Obviously, much of the redescription will be metaphoric. This places metaphor into the core of irony. See, for instance, Snaevar (2010). This impressive and comprehensive book misses Rortyan irony, which is a major defect. But perhaps Rorty himself misses the role of metaphor in dialectics. |
7 | |
8 | Huson (1998, p. 123). Huson says the definition of tragic irony applies to scripted drama and its peripeteia and catharsis; alas, I cannot understand what he says about the state in this context. It sounds evident that “with the state, irony takes another form than it does in the drama” (p. 123): his definition of tragic irony mentions only individuals. As I see it, they can be dramatic heroes or world-historical individuals—but what about states? Why discuss states in this context? My strategy here is to discuss world-historical individuals, which allows me to apply Huson’s interesting definition to the real world of states and politics. |
9 | See Moynahan (1997, p. 360). Rasputin’s political goals were much the same as Lenin’s. On the World Historical Individual, see Hegel ([1840] 1956, p. 29)—some of them fail (Napoleon), some win (Stalin), or it is hard to tell (De Gaulle, Churchill). |
10 | E. M. Cioran writes, “If Jesus had ended his career upon the Cross, if he had not been committed to resuscitation—what a splendid tragic hero.” This is an example of a spoiled nexus. A true tragic hero “succumbs under the weight of his own actions” alone, without hope, consolation, or redemption. Eternal happiness ruins the drama (Cioran 2010, Conditions of Tragedy, p. 87). The death of Jesus may have been disastrous but not tragic. |
11 | See Hegel ([1840] 1956, p. 17): “The essence of Spirit is Freedom,” and “the perfect embodiment of Spirit assumes—the State.” See also (Hegel [1830] 1975, p. 104), and (Hegel ([1821] 1969), for example § 258, Addition. The goal of the State is substantive freedom. Notice that the State is a historical entity: only the State has proper history (Hegel [1840] 1956, p. 41). Therefore, freedom is realized in history. On Hegel’s philosophy of history, see, for instance, Malabou (2000); Thanassas (2016); Baumann (2021); Zuckert and Kreines (2017). |
12 | See Roese and Olson (1995)—Richard J. Evans in The Guardian calls it intellectual atavism and a waste of time, but we cannot avoid what-if history in the relevant narrative contexts. Scientific historians must avoid it, but the future of nations depends on it. For instance, Nazism’s early political successes were based on the following: If we had continued fighting in the Great War, we would have had a chance to prove ourselves—but our politicians deceived us. Therefore, this paper concerns counterfactual historical narratology in the conversational sense. See, Evans (2014). |
13 | Hotta (2014, Ch. 9: An Unwinnable, Inevitable War). Also, Wintrobe (2023, pp. 273–286). Japan’s reasons may have been defencive, though. |
14 | On the Finnish Civil War, see “Hourly History” (2022). This war has many names for political and partisan reasons: the War of Independence, Red Mutiny, Civil War, Crofter Mutiny, and War between Brothers. Finland gained its independence from Russia before the war started. On the Winter War and the Operation Barbarossa, see Nenye et al. (2015, 2018). |
15 | |
16 | |
17 | See Dower (1999). See the cartoon on p. 70. The nation may accuse the political power brokers, big business, and militarism of the defeat and destruction and turn to victors to alleviate their pain. This happened in Finland, too. The internalized conflict vanished; the enemy was no longer the hated Other but a redeemer and even a liberator. (Rapaport 1974, pp. 197–98) |
18 |
References
- Airaksinen, Timo. 2020. Irony and Sarcasm in Ethical Perspective. Open Philosophy 3: 358–68. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Airaksinen, Timo. 2021. Metaphysics, Universal Irony, and Richard Rorty’s “We Ironists”. Humanities 10: 106. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Airaksinen, Timo. 2023. Three Types of Dramatic Irony. In Power and Responsibility: Interdisciplinary Perspectives for the 21st Century in Honour of Manfred J. Holler. Edited by Martin Lerouch and Florian Rupp. Cham: Springer, pp. 15–30. [Google Scholar]
- Bacon, Michael. 2005. A Defend of Liberal Ironism. Res Publica 11: 403–23. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Barry, McLoughlin. 1999. Documenting the Death Toll. Available online: https://www.historians.org/research-and-publications/perspectives-on-history/may-1999/documenting-the-death-toll-research-into-the-mass-murder-of-foreigners-in-moscow-1937-38 (accessed on 19 March 2023).
- Baumann, Charlotte. 2021. Was Hegel an Authoritarian Thinker? Reading Hegel’s Philosophy of History on the Basis of his Metaphysics. Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 103: 120–47. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bernstein, Richard J. 2016. Ironic Life. London: Polity Press. [Google Scholar]
- Boggs, Carl, ed. 2003. Masters of War: Militarism and Blowback in the Era of American Empire. New York and London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Booth, Wayne C. A. 2004. Rhetoric of Irony. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. [Google Scholar]
- Camp, Elisabeth. 2012. Sarcasm, Pretense, and the Semantic/pragmatics Distinction. Nous 46: 587–634. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Casall, Sergio. 1995. Tragic Irony in Ovid, Heroides 9 and 11. Classical Quarterly 45: 505–11. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Cioran, Emil M. 2010. A Short History of Decay. Translated by Richard Howard. London: Penguin. [Google Scholar]
- CliffsNotes. 2023. Critical Essay Aristotle on Tragedy. Available online: https://www.cliffsnotes.com/literature/a/agamemnon-the-choephori-and-the-eumenides/critical-essay/aristotle-on-tragedy (accessed on 16 June 2020).
- Connaughton, Richard M. 2020. Rising Sun and Tumbling Bear: Russia’s War with Japan. London: Weidenfeld & Nicholson. [Google Scholar]
- Cuddon, John A. 1999. Penguin Dictionary of Literary Terms, 4th ed. London: Penguin. [Google Scholar]
- Currie, Gregory. 2006. Why Irony is Pretense. In The Architecture of the Imagination. Edited by Shaun Nichols. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- de Beistegui, Miguel, and Simon Sparks. 2000. Philosophy and Tragedy. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Dower, John W. 1999. Embracing Defeat: Japan in the Wake of World War II. New York: Norton. [Google Scholar]
- Eagleton, Terry. 2020. Tragedy. New Haven: Yale University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Evans, Richard J. 2014. ‘What If’ Is a Waste of Time. Available online: https://www.theguardian.com/books/2014/mar/13/counterfactual-history-what-if-waste-of-time (accessed on 28 March 2023).
- Forbes, Duncan. 1975. Introduction. In Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, Lectures on the Philosophy of World History, Introduction. Translated by H. B. Nisbet. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Friedrich, Otto. 1982. The End of the World: A History. New York: Coward, McCann & Geoghegan. [Google Scholar]
- Garmendia, Joana. 2010. Irony is Critical. Pragmatics and Cognition 8: 397–421. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gaskill, Nicholas M. 2008. Experience and Signs: Towards a Pragmatist Literary Criticism. New Literary History 39: 165–83. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Goldie, Peter. 2007. Dramatic Irony, Narrative, and the External Perspective. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 60: 69–84. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Goldie, Peter. 2014. The Mess Inside: Narrative, Emotion, and the Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Green, Mitchell. 2017. Irony as Expression (of a Sense of the Absurd). The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication 12: 1–24. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. 1969. Philosophy of Right. Translated by T. M. Knox. Oxford: Oxford University Press, First publish 1821. [Google Scholar]
- Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. 1975. Lectures on the Philosophy of World History: Introduction. Translated by H. B. Nisbet. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, First publish 1830. [Google Scholar]
- Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. 1956. The Philosophy of History. Translated by J. Sibree. New York: Dover, First publish 1840. [Google Scholar]
- Hotta, Eri. 2014. Japan 1941: Countdown to Infamy. New York: Vintage Books. [Google Scholar]
- “Hourly History”. 2022. Finnish Civil War: A History from Beginning to End. Hourly History. Traverse City: Independent Publisher. [Google Scholar]
- Huson, Timothy C. 1998. Hegel and the Concept of ‘Tragic Irony’. Southwest Philosophy Review 14: 123–30. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Inkpin, Andrew. 2013. Taking Rorty’s Irony Seriously. Humanities 2: 292–312, Special Issue The Legacy of Richard Rorty. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Jähner, Harald. 2022. Aftermath: Life in the Fallout of the Third Reich, 1945–1955. New York: Knopf. [Google Scholar]
- Lambert, Laura. 2023. Available online: https://www.britannica.com/science/Stockholm-syndrome (accessed on 27 March 2023).
- Leskanich, Alexandre. 2021. Cosmic Invalidity: E. M. Cioran and the Contagion of Nothingness. The Philosopher 109: 92–98. [Google Scholar]
- Leypoldt, Günther. 2008. Uses of Metaphor: Richard Rorty’s Literary Criticism and the Poetics of World-Making. New Literary History 39: 145–63. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Malabou, Catherine. 2000. The Future of Hegel: Plasticity, Temporality, Dialectic. Hypatia 15: 196–220. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Małecki, Wojciech, ed. 2011. Pragmatism and Literature. Pragmatism TodayI, 2/2. pragmatism today.
- Marchetti, Sarin. 2019. Irony and Redescription. Iride: Filosofia e Discussione Pubblica 88: 631–43. [Google Scholar]
- Marshall Plan. 2022. Available online: https://www.history.com/topics/world-war-ii/marshall-plan-1 (accessed on 19 March 2023).
- McMeekin, Sean. 2021. Stalin’s War: A New History of World War II. New York: Basic Books. [Google Scholar]
- Menke, Christoph. 2009. Tragic Play: Irony and Theater From Sophocles to Beckett. New York: Columbia University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Moynahan, Brian. 1997. Rasputin, The Saint who Sinned. New York: Random House. [Google Scholar]
- Nenye, Vesa, Peter Munter, and Toni Wirtanen. 2015. Finland at War: The Winter War 1939–1940. Oxford: Osprey. [Google Scholar]
- Nenye, Vesa, Peter Munter, and Toni Wirtanen. 2018. Finland at War: The Continuation and Lapland Wars 1941–1945. Oxford: Osprey. [Google Scholar]
- Pajunen, Jussi, and Mikko Karjalainen. 2019. Finnish Volunteer Battalion of the Waffen SS in 1941–1943, and Related Finnish Studies. In Finnish-German Yearbook of Political Economy. vol. 2, Edited by Timo Airaksinen, Manfred Holler and Hannu Nurmi. München: Accedo Verlag, pp. 5–40. [Google Scholar]
- Ramberg, Björn. 2014. Irony’s Commitment: Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity. The European Legacy 2: 144–62. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rapaport, Anatol. 1974. Conflict in Man-Made Environment. Harmondsworth: Penguin. [Google Scholar]
- Roese, Neal J., and James M. Olson. 1995. What Might Have Been: The Social Psychology of Counterfactual Thinking. New Jersey: Erlbaum. [Google Scholar]
- Roland, Paul. 2019. Life After the Third Reich: The Struggle to Rise from the Nazi Ruins. London: Arcturus. [Google Scholar]
- Rorty, Richard. 1989. Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Schulenberg, Ulf. 2015. Romanticism and Pragmatism: Richard Rorty and the Idea of a Poeticized Culture. New York: Palgrave-Macmillan. [Google Scholar]
- Snaevar, Stefán. 2010. Metaphors, Narratives, and Emotions: Their Interplay and Impact. Amsterdam: Rodopi. [Google Scholar]
- Szondi, Peter. 1961. Versuch über das Tragische. Frankfurt a. M.: Insel Verlag. [Google Scholar]
- Thanassas, Panagiotis. 2016. Hegel ohne Ballast Geschichtsphilosophie in neuen Lektüren. Philosophische Rundschau 63: 207–23. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tucker, Rober C. 2009. The Cunning of Reason in Hegel and Marx. Available online: https://www.cambridge.org/core/journals/review-of-politics/article/abs/cunning-of-reason-in-hegel-and-marx/ (accessed on 19 March 2023).
- Väyrynen, Pekka. 2014. Essential Contestability and Evaluation. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 92: 471–88. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Walicki, Andrzej. 1982. Philosophy and Romantic Nationalism: The Case of Poland. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Wheelwright, Philip. 1999. Heraclitus. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Wintrobe, Ronald. 2023. Why did Japan Attack Pearl Harbor? In Power and Responsibility. Edited by Martin Leroch and Florian Rupp. Cham: Springer, pp. 273–86. [Google Scholar]
- Zuckert, Rachel, and James Kreines, eds. 2017. Hegel on Philosophy in History. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2023 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Airaksinen, T. Tragedy, Tragic Irony, and War: A Dialectical Approach. Humanities 2023, 12, 54. https://doi.org/10.3390/h12040054
Airaksinen T. Tragedy, Tragic Irony, and War: A Dialectical Approach. Humanities. 2023; 12(4):54. https://doi.org/10.3390/h12040054
Chicago/Turabian StyleAiraksinen, Timo. 2023. "Tragedy, Tragic Irony, and War: A Dialectical Approach" Humanities 12, no. 4: 54. https://doi.org/10.3390/h12040054
APA StyleAiraksinen, T. (2023). Tragedy, Tragic Irony, and War: A Dialectical Approach. Humanities, 12(4), 54. https://doi.org/10.3390/h12040054