From Postmodernism to Posthumanism: Theorizing Ethos in an Age of Pandemic
Abstract
:1. Introduction
I live at the tail end of bio-power, that is to say amidst the relentless necro-political consumption of all that lives. I am committed to starting from this, not from a nostalgic re-invention of an all-inclusive transcendental model, a romanticized margin or some holistic ideal. I want to think from here and now, … from missing seeds and dying species. But also, simultaneously and without contradiction, from the staggering, unexpected and relentlessly generative ways in which life, as bios and as zoe, keeps on fighting back.—Rosi Braidotti, The Posthuman (Braidotti 2013, pp. 194–95)
But should we in turn wish to “look into the future” and form an image of what it will be, there is one childish error we must avoid: to base the man of the future on what we are now, simply granting him a greater quantity of mechanical means and appliances.—Henri Lefebvre, Critique of Everyday Life (Lefebvre [1991] 2014, p. 246; emphasis added)
In “Positioning Ethos in/for the Twenty-First Century”—intended to introduce the Humanities special issue, Histories of Ethos—my co-author and I surveyed the “current state of theory” on ethos while seeking “to predict, and promote, discursive practices that will carry ethos into a hopeful future” (Baumlin and Meyer 2018, “Positioning,” p. 1). As we noted back then, we live in an age of ethos, wherein “issues of ‘trust,’ expertise, and ‘charismatic authority’ have largely supplanted Enlightenment logos or ‘good reasons’ as the ground of popular discourse” (Baumlin and Meyer 2018, “Positioning,” p. 3).1 A mere two years have passed, but much has changed socially, politically, economically, ecologically—and not just in the United States but globally, though the U.S. has become the world’s “leader” in COVID-19 infection-rates and death-rates, with little respite in sight. The “hopeful future” that we had called for has erupted into a full-blown crisis of ethos: that is, a crisis of (political) “trust” vs. (scientific) “expertise” in combatting pandemic. A deepening partisan divide, the intensifying “culture wars” (enflamed by nationalist “identity politics”), the obfuscation of “fake news,” a U.S. president’s discounting of science in policymaking and, most crucial at this time, an administration’s refusal to let its scientists speak has put the American people into a state of panic, paralysis, and confusion.It is not absurd to suppose that the extermination of man begins with the extermination of man’s germs. One has only to consider the human being himself, complete with his emotions, his passions, his laughter, his sex and his secretions, to conclude that man is nothing but a dirty little germ—an irrational virus marring a universe of transparency.—Jean Baudrillard, “Prophylaxis and Virulence” (Baudrillard [1994] 2000, p. 34)
2. From ἦθoς to ἤθεα: Character and/as “Dwelling”
We have not changed our minds. As described in the epigraph above, the binary between an existentialist ethos-as-revealed and a social-constructionist ethos-as performed still holds. Along with a speaker’s projected self-image and “cultural dress,” ethos identifies the ritualized modes of address “that confer authority upon those who would ‘speak on behalf’ of some group—some institution, organization, party, or class interest” (Baumlin and Meyer, “Positioning,” p. 7).4 Ours remains a transactional model, treating ethos as a dialectic engaging speakers and audiences conjointly.5 And we embrace the expansion of classical-Aristotelian ethos as outlined by Martin Heidegger (1889–1976) in his “Letter on Humanism” (1949)—the subject to which we now turn.We begin with a working definition provided by Jim W. Corder (1929–1998). Ethos, Corder writes, is “character as it emerges in language” (Corder 1978, “Varieties,” p. 2). By “character,” we assume both personhood and persona—that is, the self’s expressive self-identity as well as its social presentation or mask. There is a double movement, both inward and outward, in this term, which introjects how one “sees” oneself, as well as projects how one “is seen” by others. One hopes for sincerity, authenticity, and self-consistency in this doubled, inside/outside “showing-forth” of character. When inside and outside match, one can speak of ethos as self-revelation: “What you see is what you get.” But there can be a slippage or disjunction between the person and persona—again, between the inner and the outer versions of self. In that case, one can speak of ethos as performance. To this inside/outside dialectic, let us add considerations of culture. Character “emerges,” but does so within a distinctive “cultural dress,” one that presents itself—in effect, “clothes itself”—within markers of identity/difference (ethnicity, gender, social status, regional accent, etc.). Michel Foucault (1926–1984) gives the Athenian ethos as illustration: “Ethos was the deportment and the way to behave. It was the subject’s mode of being and a certain manner of acting visible to others. One’s ethos was seen by his dress, by his bearing, by his gait, by the poise with which he reacts to events, etc.” (Foucault 1988, “Ethic of Care,” p. 6; emphasis added). Ethos, in this sense, displays cultural “markers,” such that the speaker’s task is “to open a space” through language that allows the self to be heard and, saliently, to be seen.—James S. Baumlin and Craig A. Meyer, “Positioning Ethos”
Heidegger’s translation is “modern,” presumably, in that invokes human being “as an embodied existence in-the-world, and not as an abstraction belonging to metaphysics” (Baumlin and Meyer 2018, “Positioning,” p. 13). As Dasein or Being-in-the-world (Heideggerian terms for our humanness), we are called to bear witness to the Truth of Being and to dwell within that space wherein our humanness finds itself “thrown.” Into this unified lifeworld—the Heideggerian Geviert or “fourfold” of earth, sky, mortals, and divinities—“we are called by conscience to serve the world as witness, companion, and caretaker” (Baumlin and Meyer 2018, “Positioning,” p. 13). As we go on to note,The saying of Heraclitus (Fragment 119) goes: ἦθoς ἀνθρώπῳ δαίμων. This is usually translated, “A man’s character is his daimon.” This translation thinks in a modern way, not a Greek one. ἦθoς means abode, dwelling place. The word names the open region in which the human being dwells. The open region of his abode allows what pertains to the essence of the human being … to appear.
Concomitantly, we note Heidegger’s failure to acknowledge cultural difference and the “positionality” or situatedeness inherent in rhetoric. Though his discussion continues to serve ethos theory, it does so through misprision: that is, through a critical misreading (unconscious in many cases) and misapplication of his work. For Heidegger, the ethos-as-dwelling is Being, as opposed to the “beings” that constitute nations, ethnicities, classes, and cultures. This theme repeats itself in our later discussions of ethos in ecology and technoscience: We begin with Heidegger but must reach beyond him to articulate models of ethos adequate to the 21st century.The Heideggerian model appeals to us for many reasons, not least of which is the ethical claims that it makes upon the speaker. One speaks not simply to declare one’s “dwelling place,” nor simply to share that dwelling, but also to care for it. Situated within a self/other dialectic, the act of self-expression becomes an invitation to dwell with others, “to open a space,” by means of language, where self and other “can dwell and feel at home” (Hyde 2004, “Introduction,” p. xxi). It is an invitation to hospitality.As an expansion upon Aristotelian eunoia, it’s the Heideggerian attitude of caring that leads us into a new “New Rhetoric,” one suited to the pluralist, post-Enlightenment, multiculturalist discourse of our age.6
3. From ἤθεα to Γαῖα: Planetary Ethos and/as “Dwelling-Together”
I take the passage above from the conclusion of our previous essay, to show that its endpoint marks the current essay’s starting point. As with our prior discussion of ethos-as-haunt, we begin with Heidegger, whose description of technology has deep implications for ecology. His essay, “The Question Concerning Technology” (1954), “defined the field for many years” (Kaplan 2009, Readings, p. 2), though the “field” Kaplan cites—the philosophy of science—continues to evolve in ways only partially anticipated by Heidegger.In this introduction to Histories of Ethos, we have made a series of claims that individual essays will put to the test. Some will explore the “cultural dress,” some the “modes of address,” by means of which individuals situate themselves within communities in place and time. Competing versions of ethos, both in theory and in praxis, will be applied. The role of narrative in identity-formation—both individually and culturally—will be a recurring motif. And, while individual essays might explore only a portion of the spacious field of ethos within any culture at any time, we assume that any claim regarding ethos can be turned, dialectically, into its “enabling other.” No premise or claim has been banished or disallowed from this collection. Hence, we affirm that ethos can be revealed or constructed; that it can pre-exist a speaker’s discourse or be produced within (or by means of) discourse; that it can ally itself with, or it can subvert, logos or pathos. If it can heal and liberate, surely it can be used to harm. Self necessarily posits an other; identity implies difference. Narratives can be “fixed” within a culture’s folk pathways and traditions; but these can also be revisited, reinterpreted, reshaped, retold. Ethos can be carried into new regions. With smart technologies, ethos enters the realm of the artificially-intelligent nonhuman—the cyborg. Even the “deep ecology” movement posits a “planetary ethos.”—James S. Baumlin and Craig A. Meyer, “Positioning Ethos”
But this “realm of revealing” is active upon and transformative of material nature:We are questioning concerning technology, and we have arrived now at alētheia, at revealing. What has the essence of technology to do with revealing? The answer: everything. For every bringing-forth is grounded in revealing…. Technology is therefore no mere means. Technology is a way of revealing. If we give heed to this, then another whole realm for the essence of technology will open itself up to us. It is the realm of revealing, that is, of truth.
The revealing that rules throughout modern technology has the character of a setting-upon, in the sense of a challenging-forth. That challenging happens in that the energy concealed in nature is unlocked, what is unlocked is transformed, what is transformed is stored up, what is stored up is, in turn, distributed, and what is distributed is switched about ever anew. Unlocking, transforming, storing, distributing, and switching about are ways of revealing. But the revealing never simply comes to an end.
Over-against Heideggerian Bestand is this stress upon schonen or “sparing,” with its implicit commitment to ecology. “The basic character of dwelling,” says Heidegger, “is to spare, to preserve. Mortals dwell in the way they preserve the fourfold in its essential being, its presencing…. Mortals dwell in that they save the earth…. To save the earth is more than to exploit it or even wear it out. Saving the earth does not master the earth and does not subjugate it” (Heidegger [1951] 1978, “Building,” p. 328).To free actually means to spare…. [Sparing] takes place when we leave something beforehand in its own essence, when we return it specifically to its essential being, when we “free” it in the proper sense of the word into a preserve of peace. To dwell, to be set at peace, means to remain at peace within the free, the preserve, the free sphere that safeguards each thing in its essence. The fundamental character of dwelling is this sparing.(Heidegger [1951] 1978, “Building,” pp. 326–27; emphasis in original)
While seeming to recapitulate the Heideggerian Bestand—that “standing-reserve” within nature, which falls to human management and use—Lovelock’s Gaia introduces a principle of planetary “health” into ecology:[W]e have assumed that the Gaian world evolves through Darwinian natural selection, its goal being the maintenance of conditions favourable for life in all circumstances, including variations in output from the sun and from the planet’s own interior. We have in addition made the assumption that from its origin the human species has been as much a part of Gaia as have all other species and that, like them, it has acted unconsciously in the process of planetary homoeostasis. However, in the past few hundred years our species, together with its dependent crops and livestock, has grown in numbers to occupy a substantial proportion of the total biomass. At the same time the proportion of energy, information, and raw materials which we use has grown at an even faster rate through the magnifying effect of technology. It therefore seems important in the context of Gaia to ask: “What has been the effect of all or any of these recent developments? Is technological man still a part of Gaia or are we in some or in many ways alienated from her?”
By analogy with biological life, planetary ecology can be studied as a delicately balanced (and, with global warming, increasingly threatened) homeostasis (Lovelock 2006).The larger the proportion of the Earth’s biomass occupied by mankind and the animals and crops required to nourish us, the more involved we become in the transfer of solar and other energy throughout the entire system. As the transfer of power to our species proceeds, our responsibility for maintaining planetary homoeostasis grows with it, whether we are conscious of the fact or not. Each time we significantly alter part of some natural process of regulation or introduce some new source of energy or information, we are increasing the probability that one of these changes will weaken the stability of the entire system, by cutting down the variety of response.
4. Urban Ethos and/as Postmodern Technoculture
Genetically recombined plants, animals and vegetables proliferate alongside computer and other viruses, while unmanned flying and ground armed vehicles confront us with new ways of dying. Humanity is re-created as a negative category, held together by shared vulnerability and the spectre of extinction, but also struck down by new and old epidemics, in endless “new” wars, detention camps and refugee exodus. The appeals for new forms of cosmopolitan relations or a global ethos are often answered by the homicidal acts of the likes of Pekka Eric Auvinen or Anders Behring Breivik.—Rosi Braidotti, The Posthuman (Braidotti 2013, p. 187)
Prophet of postmodernity, Marshall McLuhan (1911–1980) was among the first to proclaim the human-machine interface, the fact that “all technologies are extensions of our physical and nervous systems to increase power and speed” (McLuhan [1964] 2003, Understanding, 98). And, in this new age—which is already upon us, though its implications and applications continue to emerge—our human-social relations change, as well: For “electricity … decentralizes. It is like the difference between a railway system and an electric grid system: the one requires railheads and big urban centers. Electric power, equally available in the farmhouse and the Executive Suite, permits any place to be a center” (McLuhan [1964] 2003, Understanding, p. 39). Hence, the “center-margin structure” of 20th century geopolitical mapping is “experiencing an instantaneous reassembling of all its mechanized bits into an organic whole. This is the new world of the global village” (McLuhan [1964] 2003, Understanding, p. 101). Of course, the “global village” resides within a “global economy,” whose “techno-scientific structure” is built out of “different and previously differentiated branches of technology, notably the four horsemen of the posthuman apocalypse: nanotechnology, biotechnology, information technology and cognitive science” (Braidotti 2013, Posthuman, p. 59).During the mechanical ages we had extended our bodies in space. Today, after more than a century of electric technology, we have extended our central nervous system itself in a global embrace, abolishing both space and time as far as our planet is concerned. Rapidly, we approach the final phase of the extensions of man—the technological simulation of consciousness, when the creative process of knowing will be collectively and corporately extended to the whole of human society, much as we have already extended our senses and our nerves by the various media.—Marshall McLuhan, Understanding Media: The Extensions of Man (McLuhan [1964] 2003, pp. 3–4)
Being “post-traditional” (Giddens 1991, Modernity, p. 14), the contemporary urban ethos need no longer rest in cultural identifications and social-ritual practices; in some cases, these can themselves be seen as aspects of lifestyle and its choices.Each of us not only “has,” but lives a biography reflexively organized in terms of flows of social and psychological information about possible ways of life…. “How shall I live?” has to be answered in day-to-day decisions about how to behave, what to wear and what to eat—and many other things—as well as interpreted within the temporal unfolding of self-identity.
5. Actants and Cyborgs: From Postmodernism to Posthumanism
A body corporate is what we and our artifacts have become. We are an object-institution. The point sounds trivial if applied asymmetrically. “Of course,” one might say, “a piece of technology must be seized and activated by a human subject, a purposeful agent.” But the point I am making is symmetrical: what is true of the “object” is still truer of the “subject.” There is no sense in which humans may be said to exist as humans without entering into commerce with what authorizes and enables them to exist (that is, to act).—Bruno Latour, “A Collective of Humans and NonHumans” (Latour [1999] 2009, p. 168)
[I]f the proper study of mankind used to be Man and the proper study of humanity was the human, it seems to follow that the proper study of the posthuman condition is the posthuman itself. This new knowing subject is a complex assemblage of human and non-human, planetary and cosmic, given and manufactured, which requires major re-adjustments in our ways of thinking.—Rosi Braidotti, The Posthuman (Braidotti 2013, p. 159)
In “A Collective of Humans and NonHumans,”19 Bruno Latour “seeks to overcome the dualistic paradigm” marking earlier Enlightenment philosophy: specifically, “the separation of subjectivity from objectivity, facts from values, and humans from technology” (Kaplan 2009, Readings, p. 7). As Kaplan observes, “there has never been such a thing as humanity without technology nor technology without humanity,” nor has society existed “apart from science and technology.” Rather, “nonhumans, (social) actors, and (objective) networks are ‘symmetrical.’ Neither is more important than the other; both are always bound up together. Humans and technology are active agents (or rather, actants)” (Kaplan 2009, Readings, p. 7). Such is the basis of actor-network theory (ANT), which sees the social and natural worlds as engaged in continuous, shifting interrelationships. Since “agents and technologies act jointly together,” ANT is ethotic in describing the roles human actants play in “human-technology relations.” For “each artifact has its script, its potential to take hold of passersby and force them to play roles in its story” (Latour [1999] 2009, “Collective,” p. 158). Kaplan illustrates: “I become a motorist when I drive a car; a gardener when I use a rake. As a result, it is more helpful to understand our lives as social-technical; our lives are composed of actants” (Kaplan 2009, Readings, p. 7). Latour’s own illustration makes for a savvy commentary on the American “gun-slinger” ethos:If bodies come into being without the usual procedure, would they be human? Or, if a body has several of its parts replaced by machines or organic parts from other species (xenotransplantation) or even made from genetic material from assorted species, would the body be human? Do clones have human rights? Are foreign parts within our bodies nativized, or do they stay alien and foreign?—Pramod K. Nayar, Posthumanism (Nayar 2014, p. 60)
“What does the gun add to the shooting?” Latour asks. He answers, “In the materialist account, everything: an innocent citizen becomes a criminal by virtue of the gun in her hand. The gun enables, of course, but also instructs, directs, even pulls the trigger—and who, with a knife in her hand, has not wanted at some time to stab someone or something?” (Latour [1999] 2009, “Collective,” pp. 157–8; emphasis in original).“Guns kill people” is a slogan of those who try to control the unrestricted sale of guns. To which the National Rifle Association (NRA) replies with another slogan, “Guns don’t kill people; people kill people.” The first slogan is materialist: the gun acts by virtue of material components irreducible to the social qualities of the gunman. On account of the gun the law-abiding citizen, a good guy, becomes dangerous. The NRA, meanwhile, offers (amusingly enough, given its political views) a sociological version more often associated with the Left: that the gun does nothing in itself or by virtue of its material components. The gun is a tool, a medium, a neutral carrier of human will.
Latour’s follow-up question takes us to the heart of actor-network theory: “Which of them, then, the gun or the citizen, is the actor in this situation? Someone else (a citizen-gun, a gun-citizen)” (Latour [1999] 2009, “Collective,” p. 159; emphasis added). We find Latour’s analysis compelling:If the agent is human, is angry, wants to take revenge, and if the accomplishment of the agent’s goal is interrupted for whatever reason (perhaps the agent is not strong enough), then the agent makes a detour: … Agent 1 falls back on Agent 2, here a gun. Agent 1 enlists the gun or is enlisted by it—it does not matter which—and a third agent emerges from a fusion of the other two.
Thus, the tool-using human agent—homo faber, in Enlightenment tradition—becomes “someone, something” else: Call him homo faber fabricatus. This “someone, something else,” this “hybrid actor” comprising gun and gunman, needs its own terminology, since “agents can be human or (like the gun) nonhuman, and each can have goals (or functions, as engineers prefer to say). Since the word ‘agent’ in the case of nonhumans is uncommon, a better term, as we have seen, is actant” (Latour [1999] 2009, “Collective,” p. 159).20You are a different person with the gun in your hand. Essence is existence and existence is action. If I define you by what you have (the gun), and by the series of associations that you enter into when you use what you have (when you fire the gun), then you are modified by the gun…. This translation is wholly symmetrical. You are different with a gun in your hand; the gun is different with you holding it. You are another subject because you hold the gun; the gun is another object because it has entered into a relationship with you.(Latour [1999] 2009, “Collective,” p. 159; emphasis added)
We cannot overstate Haraway’s influence upon theorists of the posthuman, for whom “the boundary between human and animal is thoroughly breached” (Haraway [1991] 2000, “Cyborg,” p. 72). Throughout the following discussion, two terms recur: “assemblage” and “becoming-”—the latter hyphenated, in that it rejects essentialist definitions while anticipating further evolution in bodies, lifeworlds, and lifestyles.It is not clear who makes and who is made in the relation between human and machine. It is not clear what is mind and what body in machines that resolve into coding practices. In so far as we know ourselves in both formal discourse (for example, biology) and in daily practice (for example, the homework economy in the integrated circuit), we find ourselves to be cyborgs, hybrids, mosaics, chimeras. Biological organisms have become biotic systems, communication devices like others. There is no fundamental, ontological separation in our formal knowledge of machine and organism, of technical and organic.
More than rewrite the scripts of our lifestyle choices, transhumanism reconstructs the human habitus in its near-entirety.22It is not our human shape or the details of our current human biology that define what is valuable about us, but rather our aspirations and ideals, our experiences, and the kinds of lives we lead. To a transhumanist, progress occurs when more people become more able to shape themselves, their lives, and the ways they relate to others, in accordance with their own deepest values. Transhumanists place a high value on autonomy: the ability and right of individuals to plan and choose their own lives.(Bostrom [2003] 2009, “Transhumanist,” pp. 345–6; emphasis added)
This “shared sense of vulnerability” carries us to brink of our own historical moment, when catastrophes are no longer “imminent” but upon us. We should have been better prepared, since “we live permanently in the shadow of the ‘imminent disaster,’” writes Brian Massumi (1993, “Everywhere,” p. 10):This new pan-humanity is paradoxical in two ways: firstly, because a great deal of its inter-connections are negative and based on a shared sense of vulnerability and fear of imminent catastrophes and, secondly, because this new global proximity does not always breed tolerance and peaceful co-existence; on the contrary, forms of xenophobic rejection of otherness and increasing armed violence are key features of our times[.]
The sirens and alarms are no longer outside of us; they pulse through our nervous systems and viscera, keeping us in “fight, flight, or fright mode,” adrenally exhausted.26 I mention this as the pathos-aspect of our response, which has tended to express itself in fear, anger, denial, or paralysis. Rationally, we’ve known that pandemic was inevitable: Scientists had been warning us for decades.What [postmodern] society looks toward is no longer a return to the promised land but a general disaster that is already upon us, woven into the fabric of day-to-day life. The content of the disaster is unimportant. Its particulars are annulled by its plurality of possible agents and times: here and to come. What registers is its magnitude. In its most compelling and characteristic incarnations, the now unspecified enemy is infinite. Infinitely small or infinitely large: viral or environmental.
What, then, shall we do with the information we are gathering on the virus, on its spread, and on the ways of its containment? Who shall speak on the subject? To whom shall we listen?[O]ur present culture is one not of essences and identities, but of overlaps and interfaces—of communication flow and systems management. She writes: “Integrity” and ‘‘sincerity’’ of the Western self gives way to decision procedures and expert systems…. No objects, spaces, or bodies are sacred in themselves; any component can be interfaced with any other if the proper standard, the proper code, can be constructed for processing signals in a common language” (Haraway [1991] 2000, p. 163). The body itself is now read as a machine. Genes are seen as codes, carrying messages. This is an image not of the individual body as a self-sustaining system, but as a set of shifting signifying surfaces turned not inwards towards a mysterious, untouchable and sublime essence, but outwards towards an ever-multiplying number of possible interconnections.(Mansfield 2000, Subjectivity, Kindle locations 2827–2832; emphasis added)
6. Responding to Pandemic: “The Scientist” Vs. “The Politician” Vs. “The Citizen”
The new ethos for computational systems, which I associate with cyborg discourse, focuses on the establishment of trust.—Carolyn Miller, “Expertise and Agency” (Miller 1994, p. 207)
In receiving a National Book Award for The Sea Around Us (Carson 1951), Rachel Carson (1907–1964) was honored for “bring[ing] attention to the public a hitherto unconsidered field of scientific inquiry” (Lear 2009, p. 218). Her acceptance speech was revolutionary in its time. Carson aimed to make science matter to the public, giving it voice and authority. In recent years, this challenge has increased. Starting with “climate skepticism,” the growing popular mistrust of science (and of academia more broadly) has brought us to a crisis not simply of fact and value, but also of messaging.We live in a scientific age; yet we assume that knowledge of science is the prerogative of only a small number of human beings, isolated and priest-like in their laboratories. This is not true. The materials of science are the materials of life itself. Science is part of the reality of living; it is the what, the how, the why of everything in our experience. It is impossible to understand man without understanding his environment and the forces that have molded him physically and mentally.—Rachel Carson, 1952 National Book Award Acceptance Speech(qtd. in Lear 2009, Witness, p. 218)
While “the citizen” may not have answers, she does “have the same capacity to question things as experts. The key is to know what kinds of questions to ask…. We have to question technology. It is our responsibility” (Kaplan 2009, Readings, p. xv; emphasis added). We agree with Kaplan, in that science is itself a mode of discourse whose truth claims are built on consensus. There is, further, a social-constructionist underside to its workings: “The much-praised ‘objectivity of science’… rests on active inter-subjectivity and social interaction” (Braidotti 2013, Posthuman, pp. 175–6). A key to “democratizing science” is to transform its rhetorical praxis by an expansion of audience: Unless practiced as a mode of ethical-ethotic public discourse, science fails to inform policy.[M]ore Internet-backed interactivity will allow citizens to participate in all forms of planning, managing and assessing their urban environment. The key words are: open source, open governance, open data and open science, granting free access by the public to all scientific and administrative data.
It’s in contemporary media that Bourdieu locates the material-technological-cultural symbols of skeptron authority:In Homer, the skeptron “is the attribute of the king, of heralds, messengers, judges, and all persons who, whether of their own nature or because of a particular occasion, are invested with authority” (Bourdieu 1991, Language, p. 193). But, as Bourdieu states elsewhere, this “authority comes to language from outside, a fact concretely exemplified by the skeptron that, in Homer, is passed to the orator who is about to speak. Language at most represents this authority, manifests and symbolizes it” (Language 109; emphasis added). A speaker’s assumption of authority, thus, is not a consequence of ethos (as per Aristotle); rather, it is a precondition—a “given,” and accessed by means of the skeptron.
Our analysis continued: “While the camera records a speaker’s visual presence, it’s the microphone that stands in for the skeptron today. As women and people of color have learned too well, the difficulty in achieving social justice—in being seen and heard, whether individually or as a group—lies not in refutation within public debate, but in practices of silencing: that is, of being denied the skeptron” (Baumlin and Meyer 2018, “Positioning,” p. 8). We can describe these as actants: (speaker + skeptron = authority) vs. (speaker − skeptron = silence). While this present essay seeks “to give voice” to science, our previous essay focused on the skeptron as an instrument of social justice.The abundance of microphones, cameras, journalists and photographers, is, like the Homeric skeptron … the visible manifestation of the hearing granted to the orator, of his credit, of the social importance of his acts and his words. Photography—which, by recording, eternizes—has the effect … of solemnizing the exemplary acts of the political ritual.(Bourdieu 1991, Language, p. 193; emphasis in original)
I am a medicine man whose vocation and mission, as passed down through generations of the Ahkehkt clan, is to heal the individual, family, community, society, and planet. Though the indigenous technologies of healing are traditional, they are continuously adaptive to conditions at hand, relying always on the gifts of the Earth: water, soil, stones, plants, animals, air, heat, cold—all gifts, but one gift. The Sehaptin cosmos is a unity, wherein the strength of one element sustains the rest, while weakness in one diminishes the rest. A Eurocentric worldview tends to dissect and analyze and compartmentalize, whereas the indigenous worldview seeks unity and synergy and synthesis. Science and religion are one: both gifts, but one gift.I have been asked how I view the present state of things. The medicine man’s technology rests in knowledge, discernment, and decision making. Without these, tools are useless. People come to me with their illnesses, but the illnesses are not theirs alone: They’re signs of exhaustion and toxicity in the water, soil, plants, animals, air. We humans are a microcosm of the planet: Having wasted its resources and destroyed its health, we find ourselves wasting away. We live longer than generations before us, but do we live better? The Eurocentric habit is to exploit nature, depleting its resources. In using up the land, we are using up the future. Look at the soil. Once a region of native forests and prairies, southwest Missouri was transformed into farms, orchards, and ranches. One hundred years ago, Missouri fed itself. Now, almost all our food is shipped in. If we relied on the land in its current depleted state, we’d starve.We have a way forward, which the land itself teaches if we’re willing to look, listen, and learn. The cosmos is a unified, living creation. Left alone, the soil will regenerate; but one hundred years of human exploitation might take one thousand years to restore at nature’s pace. The soil needs our help in regenerating; and we best serve the soil, not by behaving as chemists, but by learning to behave like the millennial forests and prairies that built layer upon layer of topsoil. The technology of proper stewardship consists of a shovel, a rake, and a wheelbarrow. My current homestead was soil-poor when I first took possession of it, showing a quarter inch of tilth depth over most of the acreage. After four years, the soil depth is sixteen inches in places and rising. Yes, I grow my own herbs and vegetables, organically. My family takes care of the soil, and the soil gifts us in return.I have been asked about the planet’s future. The language of the Sehaptin people speaks the unity of the cosmos; and, with every loss of a species of plant or insect or animal, we have to relearn our language. Every loss of species diminishes the whole of life and the language of life. Creation is a song. But ours is a diminished song, with fewer words and fewer notes. Today, the indigenous people sing a song of mourning. With proper stewardship, we can bring some measure of healing to the land. We can add notes to the song and sing it in a more hopeful key. As we do so, we shall restore to the planet its original, recuperative powers. And we’ll be restoring our own health, as well.
Funding
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
References
- Aristotle. 1991. Aristotle on Rhetoric: A Theory of Civic Discourse. Translated by George A. Kennedy. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Baudrillard, Jean. 2000. Prophylaxis and Virulence. In Readers in Cultural Criticism: Posthumanism. Edited by Neil Badmington. London: MacMillan, pp. 33–41. First published 1994. [Google Scholar]
- Baumlin, James S. 2019a. On the Confluence of Technology, Regional Economy, and Culture. In TechnOzarks: Essays in Technology, Regional Economy, and Culture. Edited by Thomas A. Peters and Paul L. Durham. Springfield: Ozarks Studies Institute, pp. xx–xxvi. [Google Scholar]
- Baumlin, James S. 2019b. In Transit to Postmodernity. In TechnOzarks: Essays in Technology, Regional Economy, and Culture. Edited by Thomas A. Peters and Paul L. Durham. Springfield: Ozarks Studies Institute, pp. xxvii–l. [Google Scholar]
- Baumlin, James S., and William B. Edgar. 2018. The Ozarks: Sharing the Ecological Message, 1818–2018. In Living Ozarks: The Ecology and Culture of a Natural Place. Edited by William B. Edgar, Rachel M. Besara and James S. Baumlin. Springfield: Ozarks Studies Institute, pp. 20–50. [Google Scholar]
- Baumlin, James S., and Craig A. Meyer. 2018. Positioning Ethos in/for the Twenty-First Century: An Introduction to Histories of Ethos. Humanities 7: 78. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Borgmann, Albert. 2009. Focal Things and Practices. In Readings in the Philosophy of Technology, 2nd ed. Edited by David M. Kaplan. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield, pp. 56–75. First published 1984. [Google Scholar]
- Bostrom, Nick. 2009. The Transhumanist FAQ. In Readings in the Philosophy of Technology, 2nd ed. Edited by David M. Kaplan. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield, pp. 345–60. First published 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Bourdieu, Pierre. 1991. Language and Symbolic Power. Edited by John B. Thompson. Translated by Gino Raymond, and Matthew Adamson. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Braidotti, Rosi. 2013. The Posthuman. Cambridge: Polity. [Google Scholar]
- Carson, Rachel. 1951. The Sea around Us. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Corder, Jim W. 1978. Varieties of Ethical Argument, with Some Account of the Significance of Ethos in the Teaching of Composition. Freshman English News 6: 1–23. [Google Scholar]
- Foucault, Michel. 1988. The Ethic of Care for the Self as a Practice of Freedom. An Interview with Michel Foucault on January 20, 1984, conducted by Raúl Fornet-Betancourt, Helmut Becker, and Alfredo Gomez-Müller, Translated by J. D. Gauthier, S.J. In The Final Foucault. Edited by James Bernauer and David Rasmussen. Boston: MIT, pp. 1–20. [Google Scholar]
- Giddens, Anthony. 1991. Modernity and Self-Identity: Self and Society in the Late Modern Age. Cambridge: Polity. [Google Scholar]
- Gould, Stephen Jay. 1991. Bully for Brontosaurus: Reflections in Natural History. New York: W. W. Norton. [Google Scholar]
- Haraway, Donna J. 2000. A Cyborg Manifesto: Science, Technology, and Socialist-Feminism in the Late Twentieth Century. In Readers in Cultural Criticism: Posthumanism. Edited by Neil Badmington. London: MacMillan, pp. 68–84. First published 1991. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, Martin. 1998. Letter on Humanism. In Martin Heidegger: Pathmarks. Edited by William McNeil. Translated by Frank A. Capuzzi. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 239–76. First published 1949. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, Martin. 1978. Building Dwelling Thinking. In Heidegger: Basic Writings. Edited by David Farrell Krell. Translated by A. Hofstadter. New York: Harper, pp. 319–39. First published 1951. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, Martin. 2009. The Question Concerning Technology. In Readings in the Philosophy of Technology, 2nd ed. Edited by David M. Kaplan. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield, pp. 9–24. First published 1954. [Google Scholar]
- Ihde, Don. 1993. Philosophy of Technology: An Introduction. New York: Paragon. [Google Scholar]
- Jacobs, Jane. 1961. The Death and Life of Great American Cities. New York: Knopf Doubleday. [Google Scholar]
- James, Paul. 2015. Urban Sustainability in Theory and Practice: Circles of Sustainability. New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Jarratt, Susan C., and Nedra Reynolds. 1994. The Splitting Image: Contemporary Feminisms and the Ethics of Ethos. In Ethos: New Essays in Rhetorical and Critical Theory. Edited by James S. Baumlin and Tita French Baumlin. Dallas: Southern Methodist University Press, pp. 37–64. [Google Scholar]
- Kaplan, David M., ed. 2009. Readings in the Philosophy of Technology, 2nd ed. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield, pp. xiii–xviii. [Google Scholar]
- Keller, David. 1997. Gleaning Lessons from Deep Ecology. Ethics and the Environment 2: 139–48. [Google Scholar]
- Kennedy, Pagan. 2016. Inventology: How We Dream up Things That Change the World. Boston: Houghton Mifflin. [Google Scholar]
- Kroker, Arthur, Marilouise Kroker, and David Cook. 1989. Panic Encyclopaedia: The Definitive Guide to the Postmodern Scene. Basingstoke: Macmillan. [Google Scholar]
- Landis, Phillip Cloudpiler. 2018. Land and Stewardship. In Living Ozarks: The Ecology and Culture of a Natural Place. Edited by William B. Edgar, Rachel M. Besara and James S. Baumlin. Springfield: Ozarks Studies Institute, pp. 215–16. [Google Scholar]
- Latour, Bruno. 2009. A Collective of Humans and Nonhumans: Following Daedalus’s Labyrinth. In Readings in the Philosophy of Technology, 2nd ed. Edited by David M. Kaplan. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield, pp. 156–67. First published 1999. [Google Scholar]
- Lear, Linda. J. 2009. Rachel Carson: Witness for Nature. Boston: Mariner Books. [Google Scholar]
- Lefebvre, Henri. 2014. Critique of Everyday Life. London: Verso. First published 1991. [Google Scholar]
- LeFevre, Karen Burke. 1987. Invention as a Social Act. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Lovelock, James. 2000. Gaia: A New Look at Life on Earth. Oxford: Oxford University Press. First published 1979. [Google Scholar]
- Lovelock, James. 2006. The Revenge of Gaia: Why the Earth Is Fighting Back—And How We Can Still Save Humanity. Santa Barbara: Allen Lane. [Google Scholar]
- Mansfield, Nick. 2000. Subjectivity: Theories of the Self from Freud to Haraway. St. Leonards: Allen and Unwin. [Google Scholar]
- Marcuse, Herbert. 1991. One-Dimensional Man: Studies in the Ideology of Advanced Industrial Society, 2nd ed. Introduction by Douglas Kellner. London: Routledge. First published 1964. [Google Scholar]
- Massumi, Brian. 1993. Everywhere You Want to Be: Introduction to Fear. In The Politics of Everyday Fear. Edited by Brian Massumi. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 3–57. [Google Scholar]
- Maton, Karl. 2014. Habitus. In Pierre Bourdieu: Key Concepts, 2nd ed. Edited by Michael Grenfell. London: Routledge, pp. 48–64. [Google Scholar]
- McLuhan, Marshall. 2003. Understanding Media: The Extensions of Man. Berkeley: Gingko. First published 1964. [Google Scholar]
- Miller, Carolyn R. 1994. Expertise and Agency: Transformation of Ethos in Human-Computer Interactions. In The Ethos of Rhetoric. Columbia: South Carolina Press, pp. 197–218. [Google Scholar]
- Naess, Arne. 1973. The Shallow and the Deep, Long-Range Ecology Movement: A Summary. Inquiry 16: 95–100. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Nayar, Pramod K. 2014. Posthumanism. Cambridge: Polity. [Google Scholar]
1 | Though I’ll occasionally write in first-person singular, this essay continues my intellectual collaboration with Craig A. Meyer. I write on his behalf: hence the “we” of this essay. |
2 | As Pramod K. Nayar notes, the posthuman “is discussed as a process of becoming through new connections and mergers between species, bodies, functions and technologies” (Nayar 2014, Posthumanism, pp. 30–31). Along with our interspecies co-evolution, posthumanist theory sees the human as “symbiotic with” other species. As Nayar writes, “We are companion species with numerous other species, most of which we are unaware of. Posthumanism argues a case for companion species, for multispecies citizenship” (Nayar 2014, Posthumanism, p. 126). |
3 | As Pierre Bourdieu deploys the term, habitus describes “a socialized subjectivity” and “the social embodied” (Maton 2014, “Habitus,” pp. 52–53):
Considerations of biology and ecology must surely complicate this dialectic. As Rosi Braidotti writes, “Becoming-posthuman consequently is a process of redefining one’s sense of attachment and connection to a shared world, a territorial space: urban, social, psychic, ecological, planetary as it may be” (Braidotti 2013, Posthuman, p. 193). |
4 | For “groups need representation,” notes Karl Maton, “since they cannot speak as a group. They therefore invest their moral authority in … individuals who, thus consecrated, are the voice ‘of the people’—a claim to which they give tacit assent” (Maton 2014, “Habitus,” p. 56; emphasis added). |
5 | Ethos, as Karen Burke LeFevre writes, “appears in that socially created space, in the ‘between,’ the point of intersection between speaker or writer and listener or reader” (LeFevre 1987, Invention, p. 46). Susan C. Jarratt and Nedra Reynolds elaborate:
|
6 | A quick primer may be in order. In his Rhetoric, Aristotle outlines three pisteis or modes of “artistic proof” (1.2.2.), these being logos (an offering of “good reasons”), pathos (an appeal to an audience’s emotions), and ethos (an appeal for an audience’s trust). Ethos itself consists of three components, as Aristotle observes: these are “practical wisdom [phronesis] and virtue [arete] and goodwill [eunoia]; for speakers make mistakes in what they say or advise through [failure to exhibit] either all or one of these…. Therefore, a person seeming to have all these qualities is necessarily persuasive to the hearers” (Aristotle 1991, Rhetoric 2.5.7; 1378a). Following the transactional model outlined in “Positioning Ethos,” we note the intersection of these terms:
|
7 | As we shall see, this revealing (or “bringing into presence”) is the aim and central activity of Heideggerian phenomenology: It is an alētheia or “unconcealment” of Being within the space of language. |
8 | As Kaplan notes, “Heidegger calls this way of revealing the world ‘enframing’ (Gestell) … a way of ordering people to see the world (and each other) as a mere stockpile of resources to be manipulated. Enframing happens both in us and in the world; it is the revelation of being (human beings and nature) as standing-reserve” (Kaplan 2009, Readings, p. 2). |
9 | |
10 | Note the expansiveness of these paired terms, where “earth” represents the planet and its geology, while ‘sky’ represents the material universe above; similarly, “divinities” invokes all that belongs to deathless spirit, while “mortals” invokes all of biological life, human and otherwise, whose destiny is death. |
11 | For posthumanist philosophy, the “presencing” that Heidegger describes becomes a “co-presence, that is to say the simultaneity of being in the world together,” which defines the ethics of “interaction with both human and non-human others” (Braidotti 2013, Posthuman, p. 163). |
12 | As Arne Naess describes it, “deep ecology” rejects “shallow environmentalism” for being “simply an extension of the anthropocentric Western paradigm” of land use (Naess 1973, “Shallow,” p. 96), wherein “the reasons for preserving wilderness or biodiversity are inevitably couched in terms of human welfare” (Keller 1997, “Gleaning,” p. 140). David Keller elaborates: “Shallow environmentalism falls short of valuing nonhumans apart from their use-value. Deep Ecology, in contrast, asserts that all organisms have intrinsic value. In this way Deep Ecology is fundamentally nonanthropocentric” (Keller 1997, “Gleaning,” p. 140). |
13 | The “as if” in the sentence above marks the divide between popular vs. scientistic responses to Lovelock: for scientists like Stephen Jay Gould, Gaia is “a metaphor, not a mechanism” (Gould 1991, Bully, p. 339)—and certainly not a super-organism with its own homeostatic-metabolic processes, as proponents of hylozoism (or material vitalism) would claim. We’re content to name the planet our habitus, though we respect the cultural traditions that name our planet, animistically, “Mother Earth.” |
14 | This and several paragraphs following draw materials from three essays: “On the Confluence of Technology, Regional Economy, and Culture” (Baumlin 2019a), “In Transit to Postmodernity” (Baumlin 2019b), and “The Ozarks: Sharing the Ecological Message” (Baumlin and Edgar 2018). What I had applied regionally to the Ozarks (where I live and teach) is in this present essay applied nationally and, indeed, globally. |
15 | “It is silly,” writes Jane Jacobs, “to try to deny the fact that we Americans are a city people, living in a city economy” (Jacobs 1961, Death, p. 200). Though published in 1961, Jacobs’s Death and Life of Great American Cities remains an influential textbook in urban planning. |
16 | “Lifestyle,” writes Anthony Giddens, “is not a term which has much applicability to traditional cultures, because it implies choice within plurality of possible options, and is ‘adopted’ rather than ‘handed down’” (Giddens 1991, Modernity, p. 81). He continues:
|
17 | We should note that, in its affluence, the urban habitus (as described herein) belongs to the Global North primarily; even in American cities, inequality restricts access. Postmodernism is in fact purchased. “Progress,” thus, comes with price tags. And advantages come with trade-offs: “No longer defined by locality, or even nationality, the subject is open to, even dispersed amongst, an endlessly proliferating number of information streams. We gain information instantly at the cost of becoming information ourselves, outside of any consideration of personal choice, as liberal political theory understood it” (Mansfield 2000, Subjectivity, Kindle locations 2747–2752). Our desires become structured by the available technologies, such that “new possibilities open up to us, but only as they become technologically efficient, manageable and therefore standardized.” In this way, “the horizons of the subject are simultaneously expanded and reduced” (Mansfield 2000, Subjectivity, Kindle locations 2747–2752). |
18 | “As late as the 1870s,” Pagan Kennedy notes, “families settling on the American prairie would mend their own coffeepots, nail together hog-slaughtering stands, and repair wagon axles” (Kennedy 2016, Inventology, p. 168). She continues:
Such pioneer self-reliance belongs to the past: Unless we’ve expertise in the items following, our SUVs and HVAC systems and iPhones—and even, for goodness’ sake, our own coffee pots—lie beyond our mending. |
19 | Excerpted from Pandora’s Hope: Essays on the Reality of Science Studies (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), pp. 174–93. |
20 | I am, myself, living illustration of Latour’s actant: The eyeglasses that I have worn since age seven have become exoskeletal, and the iPhone and laptop are now so thoroughly part of my lifestyle that they accompany me to bed. Indeed, teaching online (the university classroom being closed to pandemic) and pursuing a habit of dawn-to-dusk reading and writing have bound me to my laptop (well named, that); during those times when I’m not connected to the web, I’m likely connected to the steering wheel of my SUV or cooking at my electric stove. Even during those “focal activities” of daily domesticity, the cable news might likely be on. My habitus is defined, not by its urban setting alone, but by its black-boxed technologies. My home has two wood-burning stoves, but I’ve never used them for cooking or for heat. If the power grid failed and my HVAC shut down, I’d alternatively freeze or swelter; if my freezer defrosted, I’d likely go hungry. Such is my reliance on postmodern technoculture and its standing-reserve of energy. |
21 | As Nayar writes, “In vitro fertilization, cloning, artificial ventilators and organ transplants in clinical medicine have changed the ways in which we perceive life” (Nayar 2014, Posthumanism, p. 107) He continues:
|
22 | As I reread the paragraphs above, I find the ANT version of myself (Baumlin + eyeglasses + laptop + iPhone + “sheltering” in viral prophylaxis) inching toward Bostrom’s transhumanism, that “intermediary form between the human and the posthuman” (Kaplan 2009, Readings, p. 347). I’m open to that expanded self-identity, despite my existentialist commitments. |
23 | As Braidotti deploys it, a postmodern subjectivity “defies our separation into distinct selves,” at the same time that it “encourages us to imagine that, or simply helps us to understand why, our interior lives inevitably seem to involve other people, either as objects of need, desire and interest or as necessary sharers of common experience” (Mansfield 2000, Subjectivity, Kindle locations 122–125; emphasis added). In this way, Mansfield notes, the posthuman subject “is always linked to something outside of it—an idea or principle or the society of other subjects” (Mansfield 2000, Subjectivity, Kindle locations 122–125). It is a subjectivity built upon empathy (Braidotti 2013, Posthuman, p. 26): More precisely, it is a “complex and relational subject framed by embodiment, sexuality, affectivity, empathy and desire as core qualities” (Braidotti 2013, Posthuman, p. 26). |
24 | As Braidotti writes, “a sustainable ethics” for pan-humanity “rests on an enlarged sense of interconnection between self and others, including the non-human or ‘earth’ others, by removing the obstacle of self-centred individualism” (Braidotti 2013, Posthuman, p. 190). Hence, becoming-posthuman “does not mean to be indifferent to the humans, or to be de-humanized.” Rather, “it implies a new way of combining ethical values with the well-being of an enlarged sense of community, which includes one’s territorial or environmental interconnections” (Braidotti 2013, Posthuman, p. 190). |
25 | The coronavirus, by the way, is clearly one of “the variety of shared diseases that tie humans and animals” together (Braidotti 2013, Posthuman, p. 162). Coining the term zoonosis, German physician-biologist Rudolf Virchow (1821–1902) sought to break down dividing lines between animal and human medicine, given “the isomorphism of structures between humans and animals in immunology, bacteriology, and vaccine developments. This means that humans are both exposed and vulnerable to new diseases, like bird flu and other epidemics, which they share with animal species” (Braidotti 2013, Posthuman, p. 161). Such is the etiology of the coronavirus, which can infect our pets, as well. |
26 | For many, it’s fright especially: If W. H. Auden’s poem, “Age of Anxiety” (1947), defined the postwar condition, then ours is an age of outright panic. “Panic is the key psychological mood of postmodern culture,” write Arthur Kroker, Marilouise Kroker, and David Cook: “Panic culture” comes to serve “as a floating reality, with the actual as a dream world, where we live on the edge of ecstasy and dread” (Kroker et al. 1989, Panic, pp. 13–14). |
27 | Baudrillard’s version is more ominous: “Virulence takes hold of a body, a network or other system when that system rejects all its negative components and resolves itself into a combinatorial system of simple elements. It is because a circuit or a network has thus become a virtual being, a non-body, that viruses can run riot within it; hence too the much greater vulnerability of ‘immaterial’ machines as compared with traditional mechanical devices” (Baudrillard [1994] 2000, “Prophylaxis,” pp. 33–34). “Virtual and viral,” he continues, “go hand in hand. It is because the body itself has become a non-body, a virtual machine, that viruses are taking it over” (Baudrillard [1994] 2000, “Prophylaxis,” p. 34). |
28 | The current administration has threatened China, for example, with some sort of reprisal (most likely economic) over the outbreak’s origin in Wuhan, without acknowledging that U.S. laboratories need chemical reagents supplied by China to produce and process test kits for viral exposure. Similarly, the pandemic offers brutal demonstration, not simply of the insufficiency of current biomedical technology, but of the fragility of global supply chains that can bring down entire industries through the lack of one ingredient, component, or resource. At the time of writing, communities throughout the U.S. cobbled together a supply of lab test kits that are effectively useless without application swabs—a mere swirl of cotton tipping a lengthy cardboard rod. An entire system can be brought to its knees by something so simple as a cotton swab. |
29 | In our human-social lifeworlds, Borgmann distinguishes between “mere devices” that recede into the white-noise background (HVAC systems, for example) and focal objects that contribute to “the reflective care of the good life” (Borgmann [1984] 2009, “Focal,” p. 62). Kaplan summarizes Borgmann’s argument:
COVID-19, I must confess, has affected many of my own lifestyle habits, including such nontechnological, “focal activities” as cooking, housecleaning, and gardening—which I’ve done a lot more of while sheltering at home. (I’ve expressed pride in my mother’s Polish heritage and have cooked Polish foods occasionally; otherwise, the “traditional” cultural components of my habitus are purely nostalgic.) I should add that, with the school gym closed, I bike. And while I play internet chess daily (I’d call that a fairly harmless addiction), I’ve also begun to play board games with my spouse—something we haven’t done in decades. |
30 | “In a hyperprotected space the body loses all its defences,” writes Baudrillard: “So sterile are operating rooms that no germ or bacterium can survive there. Yet this is the very place where mysterious, anomalous viral diseases make their appearance. The fact is that viruses proliferate as soon as they find a free space. A world purged of the old forms of infection, a world ‘ideal’ from the clinical point of view, offers a perfect field of operations for the impalpable and implacable pathology which arises from the sterilisation itself” (Baudrillard [1994] 2000, “Prophylaxis,” p. 34). |
31 | Writing as a critic of postmodern technoscience, Baudrillard declares that biotechnological actants have in fact weakened the body and its defenses:
Baudrillard is like right, though the postmodernist train has left the station and I’m on it and there’s no turning back. In this respect, I’m currently an assemblage of (Baumlin + hand sanitizers + azithromycin)—but not of penicillin, which would throw me into anaphylactic shock: in this respect, I have “become eminently vulnerable to medicine.” |
32 | In describing the interrelation between classical-Aristotelian logos and ethos, Carolyn Miller notes that, “in Aristotelian rhetoric, ethos stands in for expertise, because rhetoric occurs where either complete knowledge is not available or the audience is not adequately knowledgeable or competent: pathos and ethos, arete and eunoia make up for lack of knowledge” (Miller 1994, “Expertise,” p. 204). Yet the rhetoric of science remains committed to “a rhetorical style of impersonality, in which facts “speak for themselves”” (Miller 1994, “Expertise,” p. 203). This universalizing of thought—seemingly an Enlightenment legacy—might help us escape the current partisan strategies of ad hominem attack: that is, of rejecting the speech (in this case, the recommendations of science) because of the speaker. This style of depersonalization, notes Carolyn Miller, creates the paradox of “an ethos that denies the importance of ethos. The technical ethos must be informed but impartial, authoritative but self-effacing. One of the major strategies for achieving this delicate balance is the transformation of ethos into logos” (Miller 1994, “Expertise,” p. 203). |
33 | Though agribusinesses build their processing plants in smaller communities outside of urban centers, the traditional human assembly line of shoulder-to-shoulder labor has been turned, through viral infection, into a humanimal abattoir. |
34 | As Giddens notes, “A person’s identity is not to be found in behaviour, nor—important though this is—in the reactions of others, but in the capacity to keep a particular narrative going. The individual’s biography, … must continually integrate events which occur in the external world, and sort them into the ongoing ‘story’ about the self” (Giddens 1991, Modernity, p. 54). Giddens’s narrative model turns ethos into an individual’s storytelling: Such was a theme of our prior essay (Baumlin and Meyer 2018, “Positioning,” pp. 15–22). Ours, clearly, has become the story of pandemic and its impact upon our lifeworlds. |
© 2020 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Baumlin, J.S. From Postmodernism to Posthumanism: Theorizing Ethos in an Age of Pandemic. Humanities 2020, 9, 46. https://doi.org/10.3390/h9020046
Baumlin JS. From Postmodernism to Posthumanism: Theorizing Ethos in an Age of Pandemic. Humanities. 2020; 9(2):46. https://doi.org/10.3390/h9020046
Chicago/Turabian StyleBaumlin, James S. 2020. "From Postmodernism to Posthumanism: Theorizing Ethos in an Age of Pandemic" Humanities 9, no. 2: 46. https://doi.org/10.3390/h9020046
APA StyleBaumlin, J. S. (2020). From Postmodernism to Posthumanism: Theorizing Ethos in an Age of Pandemic. Humanities, 9(2), 46. https://doi.org/10.3390/h9020046