An Alternative to the Orthodoxy in Animal Ethics? Limits and Merits of the Wittgensteinian Critique of Moral Individualism
Abstract
:Simple Summary
Abstract
1. Introduction
2. The Wittgensteinian Critique of MI
The core claim of moral individualism asks us to regard the impairments of the cognitively radically impaired as drastically weakening their claim to moral consideration. The claim thus flies in the face of the thought that, precisely in view of their special susceptibility, cognitively impaired human beings merit special solicitude.[1] (p. 21)
If the point of the Singer–Regan vegetarian’s argument is to show that the eating of meat is, morally, in the same position as the eating of human flesh, he is not consistent unless he says that it is just squeamishness, or something like that, which stops us eating our dead. If he admitted that what underlies our attitude to dining on ourselves is the view that a person is not something to eat, he could not focus on the cow’s right not to be killed or maltreated, as if that were the heart of it.[12] (p. 468)
3. Limits
What distinguishes approaches in ethics that count as forms of moral individualism is the claim that a human or nonhuman creature calls for specific forms of treatment only insofar as it has individual capacities such as, for instance, the capacity for suffering or the capacity to direct its own life.[1] (p. 20, emphasis in the original)
It would be held by many people uninfluenced by theories of what can count as moral relevance that the conviction by a court of a severely retarded [sic] person for a crime that required an intention the retarded person could not form was unjust; the less capable of forming such an intention the person is, the more palpable the injustice.[33] (p. 53)
[T]here are other thinkers who take up questions of animals and ethics and who, while differing substantially from Singer et al. in their views, nevertheless resemble them in basing their conclusions about moral standing on attention to individual creatures. In light of this convergence, it makes sense to withhold the generic label “moral individualism” from the projects of Singer and likeminded others and to place their work instead under the heading of traditional moral individualism.[2] (p. 158)
4. Merits
- (1)
- Rationalism: Traditional MI is rationalistic in the sense that emotions are purposefully left aside in the discussion of what is owed to animals. Ethical theory is construed as a close-to-scientific endeavour, where anything that might cloud or distort rational discussion is shunned. In a famous passage of Animal Liberation, Singer describes how he is not particularly fond of animals, and that he was not moved by any sentiment of love towards animals to write that book. He explains that throughout the book he “makes no sentimental appeals for sympathy” towards animals, and that this work is instead “an attempt to think through, carefully and consistently, the question of how we ought to treat nonhuman animals” [4] (pp. xi, xii). While he acknowledges that the descriptions he makes of factory farming and animal experimentation will stir some emotions in the reader, the justification he gives for opposing these practices is “not emotional”, but instead “an appeal to basic moral principles which we all accept” where “the application of these principles...is demanded by reason, not emotion” [4] (p. xii). This attempt to leave all emotions aside and develop a defence of animal ethics in the most rational and aseptic way possible was echoed by Regan (see e.g., [5], (p. lii)) and has since been incorporated by most animal ethicists of the analytic tradition. It mirrors the idea that ethics is about creating rational consistency only (see e.g., [8,39]) and that immoral behaviour can be translated into irrational, i.e., inconsistent behaviour.The rationalist trend in the orthodoxy has been severely criticised by feminist writers, who have argued that emotions such as care are fundamental to treating animals how they should be treated (e.g., [40,41]). Several philosophers outside of the feminist tradition have also defended the importance of emotions in animal ethics (e.g., [42,43,44]). For the Wittgensteinians, especially Diamond, emotions such as pity are crucial for seeing animals in an ethical light. Pity, in her understanding, is fundamentally involved in our conception of suffering and death, in our coming to grasp both what they mean and why they matter to those who experience them, including animals. By making abstract appeals to the prevention of suffering, Singer and company are assuming that we can come to understand why suffering should be prevented without the involvement of emotions such as pity [12] (p. 478). Diamond sees this as confused, and she accuses the “philosophical over-emphasis on principles” that follows from this cold rationalism of alienating people from philosophy and making these philosophers’ arguments ultimately uncompelling [33] (p. 57).Diamond does not give much by way of arguments to defend the need to recruit emotions in animal ethics. However, even a cursory glance at the empirical evidence being gathered in the field of moral psychology supports the need to counter excessive rationalism. Already from Damasio’s work (e.g., [45]) we know that emotions are needed to move from moral judgement to action. However, accumulating evidence shows that emotions can influence and even determine moral judgements (see, e.g., [46]). Prinz, for instance, has argued with reference to empirical evidence that emotions and moral judgements are interrelated to the extent that emotions typically co-occur with moral judgements, emotions often influence moral judgements, and emotions are needed for proper moral development [47]. He mentions the case of psychopathy, where severe emotional deficits lead to an absence of empathic distress, remorse and guilt. Prinz even suggests that emotions may be necessary for moral judgements in a synchronic sense, to the extent that being committed to a moral judgement entails being disposed to feeling certain emotions in certain contexts. Regardless of how strongly one wants to commit to a sentimentalist account of morality, it is undoubtedly the case that emotions are involved to a certain extent in our moral lives. By leaving aside all emotions in one’s theory of animal ethics, one is failing to recruit this powerful ally, while simultaneously treating one’s interlocutors as purely rational—in the sense of non-emotional—and not as the highly emotional moral beings that we are.
- (2)
- Naturalism: Traditional MI is naturalistic in the sense that it departs from empirical facts about animals and attempts to ground the reasons for the ethical treatment of animals in these facts. For instance, Singer’s utilitarian account of animal ethics departs from the biological fact that certain animals have certain capacities to experience pleasure and pain, and these capacities give rise to certain interests that are to be respected. It is assumed that if we know how the world is, we will be able to easily arrive at reasons for action, since these are ultimately grounded in natural facts; for instance, the fact that pain feels bad and generates an interest in not feeling pain implies that we should aim to minimise the amount of pain in the world. For the Wittgensteinians, this naturalism is problematic for two main reasons. The first reason is that it assumes that we can adopt the “point of view of the Universe” in our thinking about animals and what matters to them (see, e.g., [48]). This is connected to traditional moral individualists’ search for purely rational grounds for treating all beings ethically as impartial spectators. Attempting to adopt the point of view of the Universe is, in Diamond’s words, to attempt to find “reasons which are reasons for anyone, no matter how devoid of all human imagination and sympathy” [12] (p. 479). For Crary and Diamond, not only will this result in a moral theory that is uncompelling, thinking that we could adopt such an impartial and detached perspective is also little more than wishful thinking. They depart from what could be called an “epistemic anthropocentrism”: the view that we simply cannot escape our being human in our way of approaching and understanding the world. This, which proponents of traditional MI would regard as a regrettable loss of objectivity, is constructed by the Wittgensteinians as something that should be embraced and made the most of (see also [16], pp. 91–110). Instead of attempting to approach the world in the cold and aseptic manner of the scientist, the ethicist should make full use of the capacities involved in our moral lives, such as our moral imagination and our capacity to be moved by narratives.The second reason Crary and Diamond reject the naturalism of traditional MI is that it assumes that the grounds for morality are to be found in the characteristics of individuals, whereas the Wittgensteinians defend that the grounds for morality are provided by our practices, and that these practices also often inform how we conceptualise the characteristics of beings we interact with. As we have seen, the Wittgensteinians are not completely against paying attention to the individual one is dealing with, but our practices are understood to be very often at the root of how we conceptualise this individual (what characteristics we attribute to it) and also ultimately at the grounds of any justification for treating the individual in one way or another. In Diamond’s words:We can most naturally speak of a kind of action as morally wrong when we have some firm grasp of what kind of beings are involved. But there are some actions, like giving people names, that are part of the way we come to understand and indicate our recognition of what kind it is with which we are concerned.[12] (p. 469)We believe that this appeal to the importance of practices in the grounding of morality is one of the most insightful contributions of these Wittgensteinian authors, and one that the authors in the orthodoxy are apparently oblivious to, even though it is implicit in their argumentations. Indeed, the argument from “marginal cases”—as a paradigmatic case of orthodox argumentation—would not work at all were it not for a background of practices that support it. Imagine someone who tried to justify slaughtering and eating cows by pointing out that cows do not have a concept of death and so do not care about being killed and eaten so long as we do it painlessly. A possible response, using the argument from “marginal cases”, would be to claim that human babies do not have a concept of death either, and yet we do not eat them. If this argument does anything more than simply prove that there is an inconsistency in our interlocutor’s behaviour, this is because of the moral force that comes from our established practices, from the way in which we treat human babies despite their lack of language and concepts. If it is at all convincing, it is going to be because we manage to get our interlocutor to see the cow in a new light with help from the practices we established in the human realm.Despite this critique of the naturalism involved in traditional MI, it is important to note that it does not follow from Crary’s and Diamond’s work that all biological facts must be left aside. Knowing the biological facts pertaining to a particular animal is important, and in some cases crucial, for treating her properly. This is acknowledged by Diamond, for instance, when considering the concept of “friendship” in relation to animals. She claims she used to think friendship with animals “was obviously possible only in some cases, titmice and not hippopotamuses, e.g., but recent films of the relation between whales and their Greenpeace rescuers” made her realise that she “was probably taking an excessively narrow view” [12] (p. 475). Seeing whales in new light is made possible by learning of this practice of the Greenpeace rescuers, but it is also dependent upon biological facts of the whales (which explain why friendship might be possible with them but not with, say, a cactus). Likewise, Crary states that knowing whether an animal is of a kind “that characteristically [possesses] psychological qualities” or whether she is of a kind “so primitive that [she lacks] any characteristic psychological qualities” is of importance for determining the sort of respect she merits [1] (p. 48). The importance of not leaving aside all biological facts is especially salient in cases of uncertainty. Caring for a dog may not require much study of her biological facts, because we are sufficiently acquainted with this species, but insight into other, unfamiliar species, such as octopuses, may be crucial in giving them the treatment they are owed. The point of Crary and Diamond’s insight is not that biological facts must be completely left aside, but rather, that they are not all one needs to know. Biological facts, without the aid and interpretation in light of practices, can neither ground moral action nor moral theory. Therefore, while some naturalism is unavoidable, and indeed desirable, we should aim for an ethics that is empirically informed, and steer clear of misguided attempts to reduce moral life to what can be scientifically described.
- (3)
- Reductionism: Lastly, traditional MI is reductionist because it tries to reduce our moral lives to a theory that postulates as few principles as possible and is even monistic in some cases. The reason why so many scholars are drawn to utilitarianism despite its highly counter-intuitive implications is because utilitarianism is the ethical theory that requires assuming the least. All one needs is to postulate a hedonistic account of the good (which, being a monistic theory, postulates the minimum in terms of values) and an aggregation principle. It is seen as a virtue of this theory over all others that it requires us to assume so little. However, this is only a virtue if one assumes that moral theory should strive to be as close as possible to mathematical theory and not to our moral life. It is not at all clear why this should be so. Instead, one could turn the logic of this argument on its head and argue that precisely because utilitarianism reduces our whole moral lives to the simple claim “pain is bad; pleasure is good; the least pain and the more pleasure there is, the better” that it should be rejected. Along these lines, Midgley argued that any moral philosophy that tries to reduce our moral lives to a “simple formula” can in the end only be considered simplistic and deceitful [49] (p. 30).This mismatch with our lived morality is precisely the reason why the Wittgensteinians criticise traditional MI for being reductionist and see the plurality of moral life as the key to ethics. Although theories developed in the traditional MI framework may have the virtue of logical consistency, they leave aside all the richness and complexity of our moral lives. This is all the more problematic if one takes into account, as argued in the previous point, that it is precisely from our moral lives and established practices that traditional MI ultimately derives its conclusions and normative power. The case against speciesism, for instance, would be impossible to construct were it not for the case against slavery, racism, and sexism that is used as an analogy.14 Moreover, by being so reductionist, these theories ultimately become uncompelling precisely because they are simply unable to account for all of our deeply held moral beliefs, which we might not want to give up precisely for moral reasons. The reasons we would employ care in our dealings with a disabled person, our baby, our neighbour, our grandma or a dead body may all be completely different. An over-emphasis on principles, logical consistency and the least amount of values possible will necessarily leave some of these reasons aside, which will make the resulting moral theory paradoxically incapable of accounting for all our well-established moral practices. In this sense, while the orthodoxy has on its side the virtues of logical coherence and the capacity to simplify the messiness of our moral lives, the Wittgensteinian approach has a potential for higher explanatory power, insofar as leaving aside reductionism and embracing pluralism could allow us to make sense of a higher proportion of our moral beliefs.
5. An Alternative to the Orthodoxy?
[L]eading a human life involves [a pre-theoretical] understanding of a distinction between good and bad. We do not need the discipline of ethics or moralists to teach us that there is such a distinction, but it already informs our lives.[56] (p. 39)
[T]he object of moral principles is to supply standpoints and methods which will enable the individual to make for himself an analysis of the elements of good and evil in the particular situation in which he finds himself. […] A moral principle, then, is not a command to act or forbear acting in a given way: it is a tool for analysing a special situation.[61] (p. 280, emphasis in the original)
6. Conclusions
Author Contributions
Funding
Conflicts of Interest
References
- Crary, A. Minding What Already Matters: A Critique of Moral Individualism. Philos. Top. 2010, 38, 17–49. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Crary, A. Ethics. In Critical Terms for Animal Studies; Lori Gruen, Ed.; University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 2018; pp. 154–168. [Google Scholar]
- Gaita, R. The Philosopher’s Dog: Friendships with Animals; Random House Trade Paperbacks: New York, NY, USA, 2005. [Google Scholar]
- Singer, P. Animal Liberation: The Definitive Classic of the Animal Movement, reissue ed.; Harper Perennial Modern Classics: New York, NY, USA, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Regan, T. The Case for Animal Rights, 1st ed.; University of California Press: Berkeley, CA, USA, 2004. [Google Scholar]
- DeGrazia, D. Taking Animals Seriously: Mental Life and Moral Status; Campridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1996. [Google Scholar]
- Francione, G. Animals, Property & The Law; Temple University Press: Philadelphia, PA, USA, 1995. [Google Scholar]
- McMahan, J. Our Fellow Creatures. J. Ethics 2005, 9, 353–380. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pluhar, E. Beyond Prejudice: The Moral Significance of Human and Nonhuman Animals; Duke University Press: Durham, NC, USA, 1995. [Google Scholar]
- Rollin, B.E. The Unheeded Cry: Animal Consciousness, Animal Pain, and Science, 2nd ed.; University of Missouri: Columbia, MO, USA, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Varner, G.E. Personhood, Ethics, and Animal Cognition: Situating Animals in Hare’s Two Level Utilitarianism; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Diamond, C. Eating Meat and Eating People. Philosophy 1978, 53, 465–479. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- De Mesel, B.; Thompson, J. Wittgensteinian Approaches to Moral Philosophy. Ethical Perspect. 2015, 22, 1–14. [Google Scholar]
- Gleeson, A.; Taylor, C. (Eds.) Morality in a Realistic Spirit. Essays for Cora Diamond; Routledge: New York, NY, USA; London, UK, 2020. [Google Scholar]
- De Mesel, B.; Kuusela, O. (Eds.) Ethics in the Wake of Wittgenstein; Routledge: New York, NY, USA; London, UK, 2019. [Google Scholar]
- De Mesel, B. The Later Wittgenstein and Moral Philosophy. In Nordic Wittgenstein Studies; Forsberg, N., Ed.; Springer: Cham, Switzerland, 2018; Volume 4. [Google Scholar]
- Agam-Segal, R.; Dain, E. Wittgenstein’s Moral Thought. In Routledge Studies in Ethics and Moral Theory; Agam-Segal, R., Dain, E., Eds.; Routledge: New York, NY, USA; London, UK, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Richter, D. Thinking with Animals. In Morality in a Realistic Spirit: Essays for Cora Diamond; Gleeson, A., Taylor, C., Eds.; Routledge: New York, NY, USA; London, UK, 2020; pp. 229–241. [Google Scholar]
- Crary, A. Comments on a Contested Comparison: Race and Animals. In Ethics in the Wake of Wittgenstein; De Mesel, B., Kuusela, O., Eds.; Routledge: New York, NY, USA; London, UK, 2019; pp. 233–255. [Google Scholar]
- Taylor, C. Our Fellow Creatures. In Ethics in the Wake of Wittgenstein; De Mesel, B., Kuusela, O., Eds.; Routledge: New York, NY, USA; London, UK, 2019; pp. 220–232. [Google Scholar]
- Horta, O. The Scope of the Argument from Species Overlap. J. Appl. Philos. 2014, 31, 142–154. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dombrowski, D.A. Babies and Beasts: The Argument from Marginal Cases; University of Illinois Press: Champaign, IL, USA, 1997. [Google Scholar]
- Ryder, R. Experimenting on Animals. In Animals, Men, and Morals; Godlovitch, S., Godlovitch, R., Harris, J., Eds.; Taplinger: New York, NY, USA, 1971. [Google Scholar]
- Rachels, J. Created from Animals: The Moral Implications of Darwinism; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 1999. [Google Scholar]
- May, T. Moral Individualism, Moral Relationalism, and Obligations to Non-Human Animals. J. Appl. Philos. 2014, 31, 155–168. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Delon, N. Against Moral Intrinsicalism. In Animal Ethics and Philosophy: Questioning the Orthodoxy; Aaltola, E., Hardley, J., Eds.; Rowman Littlefield International: London, UK, 2015; pp. 31–45. [Google Scholar]
- Nussbaum, M.C. Frontiers of Justice: Disability, Nationality, Species Membership; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2007. [Google Scholar]
- Palmer, C. Animal Ethics in Context; Columbia University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Hursthouse, R. Virtue Ethics and the Treatment of Animals. In The Oxford Handbook of Animal Ethics; Beauchamp, T.L., Frey, R.G., Eds.; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Jaworska, A.; Tannenbaum, J. Person-Rearing Relationships as key to Higher Moral Status. Ethics 2014, 124, 242–271. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hsiao, T. In Defense of Eating Meat. J. Agric. Environ. Ethics 2015, 28, 227–291. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Aaltola, E. The Anthropocentic Paradigm and the Possibility of Animal Ethics. Ethics Environ. 2010, 15, 27–50. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Diamond, C. The Importance of Being Human. R. Inst. Philos. Suppl. 1991, 29, 35–62. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wolfe, C. Animal Rites: American Culture, the Discourse of Species, and Posthumanist Theory; The University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA; London, UK, 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Grimm, H. Das Tier an sich? Auf der Suche nach dem Menschen in der Tirethik. In Tierisch Menschlich: Beiträge zur Tierphilosophie und Tierethik; Rippe, K.P., Thurnherr, U., Eds.; Harald Fischer: Erlangen, Germany, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Hadley, J. A Metalevel Problem for Animal Rights Theory. In Animal Ethics and Philosophy: Questioning the Orthodoxy; Aaltola, E., Hadley, J., Eds.; Rowman & Littlefield: London, UK, 2015; pp. 15–30. [Google Scholar]
- Hursthouse, R. Applying Virtue Ethics to our Treatment of the Other Animals. In The Practice of Virtue: Classic and Contemporary Readings in Virtue Ethics; Welchmann, J., Ed.; Hackett Publishing Company: Indianapolis, IN, USA, 2006. [Google Scholar]
- Gruen, L. Dignity, Captivity, and an Ethics of Sight. In The Ethics of Captivity; Gruen, L., Ed.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2014; pp. 231–247. [Google Scholar]
- McMahan, J. Infanticide and Moral Consistency. J. Med. Ethics 2013, 39, 273–280. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Donovan, J. Animal Rights and Feminist Theory. Signs 1990, 15, 350–375. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- McKenna, E. Feminism and Vegetarianism. Philos. Contemp. World 1994, 1, 28–35. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Acampora, R.R. Corporal Compassion: Animal Ethics and Philosophy of Body, 1st ed.; University of Pittsburgh Press: Pittsburgh, PA, USA, 2006. [Google Scholar]
- Milligan, T. Beyond Animal Rights: Food, Pets and Ethics; Continuum: London, UK; New York, NY, USA, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Aaltola, E. Varieties of Empathy: Moral Psychology and Animal Ethics; Rowman & Littlefield International: Lanham, MD, USA, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Damasio, A.R. Descartes’ Error: Emotion, Reason, and the Human Brain; Penguin: New York, NY, USA, 2005. [Google Scholar]
- Haidt, J. The Moral Emotions. In Handbook in Affective Sciences; Davidson, R., Scherer, K., Goldsmith, H., Eds.; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2003; pp. 852–870. [Google Scholar]
- Prinz, J.J. The Emotional Basis of Moral Judgements. Philos. Explor. 2006, 9, 29–43. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- De Lazari-Radek, K.; Singer, P. The Point of View of the Universe: Sidgwick and Contemporary Ethics, reprint ed.; Oxford Universiy Press: New York, NY, USA, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Midgley, M. Animals and Why They Matter; University of Georgia Press: Athens, GA, USA, 1998. [Google Scholar]
- Birnbacher, D. Analytische Einführung in die Ethik; DeGruyter: Berlin, Germany; New York, NY, USA, 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Birnbacher, D. Zwischen Natur und Interesse; Suhrcamp: Frankfurt, Germany, 2006. [Google Scholar]
- Beauchamp, T.L.; Childress, J.F. Principles of Biomedical Ethics, 5th ed.; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2001. [Google Scholar]
- Campbell, R. Moral Epistemology. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosoph; Zalta, E.N., Ed.; 2015; Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2015/entries/moral-epistemology/ (accessed on 28 November 2019).
- Haack, S. Evidence and Inquiry: A Pragmatist Reconstruction of Epistemology; Prometheus: New York, NY, USA, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Sayre-McCord, G. Coherentist Epistemology and Moral Theory. In Moral Knowledge: New Readings in Moral Epistemology; Sinott-Armstrong, W., Timmons, W., Eds.; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 1996; pp. 137–189. [Google Scholar]
- Kuusela, O. Ethics and Philosophical Clarification. In Wittgenstein’s Moral Thought; Agam-Segal, R., Dain, E., Eds.; Taylor & Francis: New York, NY, USA; London, UK, 2008; pp. 37–65. [Google Scholar]
- Hartnack, S.; Springer, S.; Pittavino, M.; Grimm, H. Attitudes of Austrian veterinarians towards euthanasia in small animal practice: Impacts of age and gender on views on euthanasia. BMC Vet. Res. 2016, 12, 1–14. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Ross, W.D. The Right and the Good; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Hare, R.M. Moral Thinking: Its Levels, Method and Point; Clarendon Press: Oxford, UK, 1981. [Google Scholar]
- Dewey, J. MW5: Ethics 1908. In The Middle Works 1899–1924; Boydston, J.A., Ed.; Southern Illinois UP: Carbondale, IL, USA, 1976–1983. [Google Scholar]
- Dewey, J. LW7: Ethics 1932. In The Later Works 1925–1953; Boydston, J.A., Ed.; Southern Illinois UP: Carbondale, IL, USA, 1981–1992. [Google Scholar]
- Grimm, H. Das Moralphilosophische Experiment. John Deweys Methode Empirischer Untersuchungen als Modell der Problem-Und Anwendungsorientierten Tierethik; Mohr Siebeck: Tübingen, Germany, 2010. [Google Scholar]
1 | Another prominent author who has applied Wittgenstein’s ideas to animal ethics is Raimond Gaita [3]. However, because we are interested specifically in the critique of MI developed by Crary in close connection with Diamond’s ideas, and because we consider Gaita to defend much more of an anthropocentric position than Crary and Diamond, we will be leaving his views aside. Consequently, we use the term ‘Wittgensteinian authors’ or ‘Wittgensteinians’ as a shorthand for Crary and Diamond. |
2 | In fact, only one of us (HG) self-identifies as a Wittgensteinian, and this paper is the result of an attempt to bridge the gap between Wittgensteinian and orthodox approaches to animal ethics. |
3 | Although a lively debate about Wittgenstein and moral philosophy has emerged in the last couple of years (e.g., Gleeson & Taylor [14]; De Mesel & Kuusela [15]; De Mesel [16]; Agam-Segal & Dain [17]; De Mesel & Thompson [13]), the animal issue has for the most part been ignored. Three positive exceptions are Richter [18], Crary [19], and Taylor [20]. |
4 | |
5 | It should be noted that humans may be no different from other animals in not wanting to eat their conspecifics. This makes sense biologically, since diseases are more likely to be transmitted within rather than between species, which makes consumption of other species less risky. |
6 | An argument on how to integrate “objectivity” in Wittgensteinian ethics has been put forward by DeMesel [16] (p. 91–110). |
7 | We write ‘change’ instead of merely ‘difference’ because, despite departing from Rachels’ definition, in the bulk of the text Crary uses the term ‘capacities’ instead of ‘characteristics.’ She does not explain the reason behind this choice of terminology [1] (pp. 20). |
8 | Delon himself alternates between these two terms, but he doesn’t use ‘moral intrinsicalism’ as a synonym for MI, but rather as a way of labelling the foundational assumption of MI, which, following McMahan, he takes to be that “only intrinsic properties can be status-conferring and give rise to agent-neutral moral reasons” [8] (p. 357; cited in [26] p. 33). |
9 | One could argue that by making MI so broad as to include relation-, capacity-, and (as we shall shortly see) group-based reasons, we risk turning it into a principle that is of very limited use in moral theory, since it doesn’t narrow down which characteristics are actually relevant in moral theorising. But this is precisely the point we want to make: MI is an axiological- and normatively-neutral principle, and as such very little follows from it. Moreover, its broad nature reflects the point we aim to make in this section: MI is ultimately inescapable when one is engaged in ethics, and so it is misguided to direct one’s argumentative efforts against it. |
10 | Diamond’s attempt to defend the significance of being human has been criticised for reproducing the “anthropocentric dualism” [32]. However, we believe that under a more charitable reading it does not amount to a defence of anthropocentrism, for Diamond (like Crary) does not claim that it is the only morally relevant characteristic. In Diamond’s words: “To treat the notion of human beings as important in moral thought, as I have, is not to treat animals as outside the boundaries of moral concern, because it is not any kind of attempt to determine the limits of moral concern” [33] (p. 59, her emphasis). Nevertheless, although Diamond’s account is open to practical change, it runs the risk of preserving and stabilizing current practices. Accordingly, Aaltola criticizes Diamond’s account (and casuistry) on the basis that “[…] the nature of normativity is lost if it is reduced to description” [32] (p. 37). We acknowledge this problem, and deal with it in more detail in Section 5. |
11 | Crary and Diamond criticise MI for their excessive focus on capacities as criterion of moral consideration, and for the reductionism that comes with this. We will discuss their critique of the reductionism in MI in the following section. The orthodoxy’s excessive focus on capacities has also been taken to amount to a form of anthropocentrism, since the capacities that are usually taken as criteria for moral consideration are capacities that are important for humans. For a more extensive debate on the implicit anthropocentrism in animal rights theory and animal ethics in general, see Wolfe [34]; Grimm [35]; Hadley [36]. |
12 | The way in which defenders of hedonism respond to this sort of criticism is by saying that objective harms are morally relevant because they typically impact subjective experiences. Thus, they might respond that the reason why it is wrong to deface or mutilate a corpse is because it would be distressing to the friends or family of the dead individual, who wouldn’t like to see her memory tarnished. The problem with this sort of response is two-fold: first, it doesn’t explain the intuition that the dead individual herself is being wronged by this treatment, and second, it makes the existence of harm entirely contingent on the presence of someone witnessing the deed. |
13 | Diamond seems to be aware of this, for she writes that the difficulty that the orthodox approach to animal ethics finds in justifying our treatment of dead and disabled humans “is a matter of its hardness for any approach to morality deriving much from utilitarianism—deriving much, that is, from a utilitarian conception of what makes something a possible object of moral concern” [12] (p. 469). |
14 | The fact that sexism and racism are used as an analogy to explain what is wrong with speciesism does not mean that this analogy is entirely valid. Diamond, for instance, criticised it by claiming that the relationship between these different forms of domination is not as “simple and straightforward” as traditional moral individualists would have it [12] (pp. 466–467). The point is not that this analogy is a valid one, but rather that it’s impossible to ground a moral theory without reference to our practices. |
15 | Naturally, also moral theory and principles can trigger moral deliberation, however, the point being made here is not that practices are the only source of moral deliberation, but that problems that emerge in practice are a common trigger for ethical deliberation. |
© 2019 by the authors. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Monsó, S.; Grimm, H. An Alternative to the Orthodoxy in Animal Ethics? Limits and Merits of the Wittgensteinian Critique of Moral Individualism. Animals 2019, 9, 1057. https://doi.org/10.3390/ani9121057
Monsó S, Grimm H. An Alternative to the Orthodoxy in Animal Ethics? Limits and Merits of the Wittgensteinian Critique of Moral Individualism. Animals. 2019; 9(12):1057. https://doi.org/10.3390/ani9121057
Chicago/Turabian StyleMonsó, Susana, and Herwig Grimm. 2019. "An Alternative to the Orthodoxy in Animal Ethics? Limits and Merits of the Wittgensteinian Critique of Moral Individualism" Animals 9, no. 12: 1057. https://doi.org/10.3390/ani9121057
APA StyleMonsó, S., & Grimm, H. (2019). An Alternative to the Orthodoxy in Animal Ethics? Limits and Merits of the Wittgensteinian Critique of Moral Individualism. Animals, 9(12), 1057. https://doi.org/10.3390/ani9121057