“Become This Whole World”: The Phenomenology of Metaphysical Religion in Chāndogya Upaniṣad 6–8
Abstract
:… you must have surely asked about that teaching by which one hears what has not been heard of before, thinks of what has not been thought of before, and perceives what has not been perceived before?2
1 |
1. Heidegger’s Theory of Religion: The Structural Reorientation of Experience
2. The Problem of Philosophy as Religious Life
In other words, the efforts of the great philosophers are directed towards what is in every sense ultimate, universal, and of universal validity. The inner struggle with the puzzles of life and the world seeks to come to rest by establishing the ultimate nature of these.(TDP 7)7
…in the after effect or renewal of Kant, then the hope for a metaphysics in the old sense will be essentially diminished: an experientially transcendent knowledge of super-sensible realities, forces, causes, is regarded as impossible.(TDP 7)
- (i)
- Could there be a notion of the divine that is continuous with finite human experience of the world, whilst remaining significantly divine? That is, does divinity imply inaccessibility to human consciousness?
- (ii)
- What do we mean by human finitude? Are there any ways of being that can broaden the self, and any forms of infinity that the mind can encompass? Could there be a way of accessing the divine (or any other thing) that does not reduce it to an object within consciousness, but which instead accesses ideas without reducing them?
3. Heidegger’s Phenomenological Hermeneutics: Five Levels of Understanding Religion
Today, worldview is a spiritual concern of everyone: the peasant in the Black Forest has his worldview, consisting in the doctrinal content of his confession; the factory worker has his worldview, whose essence, perhaps, consists in regarding all religion as a superseded affair; certainly the so-called educated person has his worldview; the political parties have their worldviews. One hears nowadays about the antagonism between the Anglo-American and German worldviews.(TDP, 6)
… experience and view the world with heightened inner vitality, penetrating to its final sense and origin. They recognise nature as a cosmos of the ultimate lawfulness of simple movements or energies.(p. 6)
One must free oneself from drawing out certain concepts… Equally mistaken is the thought of a theological system in Paul. Rather, the fundamental religious experience must be explicated, and, remaining in this fundamental experience, one must seek to understand the connection to it of all original religious phenomena.’(PRL 51).
4. Reading Religion Phenomenologically: Hermeneutic Themes
4.1. Soteriological Goals
4.2. Change, Contrast, and Language
5. Primal Experience and Re-Structured Subjectivity
2 |
6. Chāndogya Upaniṣad 6–8: A Drama of Philosophically Transformed Life
“The easterly [rivers] flow toward the east, and the westerly ones flow toward the west. From the ocean, they merge into the very ocean; they become just the ocean… The finest essence here—that constitutes the self of this whole world; that is the truth; that is the self (atman). And that’s how you are…”17
Historical Context and Textual Content
7. Content: Transformation through Philosophical Analysis
- 6.1:
- A priestly father says to his recently graduated son: ‘So you must have surely asked about that teaching by which one hears what has not been heard of before, thinks of what has not been thought of before, and perceives what has not been perceived before?"… "It is like this, son. By means of just one lump of clay one would perceive everything made of clay—the transformation is a verbal handle, a name—while the reality is just this: ‘It’s clay.’29This teaching (ādeśa) promises a further knowledge that will make Śvetaketu truly a brahmin, party to realities beyond his empirical experience. The point is that diverse instances of name-and-form (nāma-rūpa) can be understood in terms of their broader underlying materials or qualities, which are termed the real or true (satya). Initially, substances are used as an example of the truth underlying individual forms (e.g., clay), but this will later be broadened into a ‘“principle” of identity’ in a way that is reminiscent of Heidegger’s argument that the pre-Socratics used materials as metaphors for universal principles (Marx 1971, p. xxxi). Phenomenal particulars are designated as a transforming ‘word-handle’ (vācārambhana vikara), while the underlying feature is the truth, knowing which one knows, in advance as it were, the whole world.
- 6.2–6:
- ‘In the beginning, son, this world was simply what is existent—one only, without a second… And it thought to itself: ‘Let me become many. Let me propagate myself’… Then that same deity thought to itself: ‘Come now, why don’t I establish the distinctions of name and appearance by entering these three deities here with this living self (atman)’30The father then shifts to a cosmogonic narrative explaining the genesis of differentiated plural name-and-forms from a single original internally-self-differentiating source. The motif of seeing a verbal-handle in terms of its underlying reality is linked to the idea (found elsewhere in the Chāndogya Upaniṣad) that certain perceptible signs can be recognized as indicating those (ordinarily invisible) underlying features. We see here idea and language proleptic of syllogistic inference from the passing phenomena of experience to an underlying substrate. The text offers a warning that the realities can also go through quite radically different formations, as when milk becomes curd (6.6.1) and food channels its energies into new beings (6.5, 6.6.2–5).31 Thus the previous reasoning from shared properties is assimilated into a model of inference that shows us the wider reality.
- 6.7–8:
- “It is like this, son. Out of a huge fire that one has built, if there is left only a single ember the size of a firefly and if one were to cover it with straw and set it ablaze—by means of that, the fire thereafter would burn very much.32In the first enacted teaching, Śvetaketu is asked to consume nothing, but water for a time, so that his vital and mental faculties diminish, but when he eats again, the ‘fire’ of the mind is reignited. This is the first of a series of examples that stress that temporary forms can rise repeatedly from a single ground, as embers are the ‘root’ of blazing fires, and consciousness arises from the ‘root’ self in the highest deity, the self of the whole world, from which presumably he can arise again even after death.33
- 6.9–13
- “The finest essence here—that constitutes the self of this whole world; that is the truth; that is the self (atman). And that’s how you are, Svetaketu.34A new set of examples is now given to build the idea that diverse instances often indicate a broader reality (different trees/same honey, different rivers/same water, different branches/same sap). This insight is applied to the self by the repeated refrain ‘thus you are’ (tat tvam asi), despite variations in the precise relations described.35 Ostensibly this mirrors the earlier ‘clay’ idea of a material substrate, but it now incorporates the ‘root’ model to build a notion that contingent forms are evolutions of the substrate, and their ceasing is dissolution back into it. Soteriologically, this is now less about ‘rebirth-from-a-root’, than about ‘merging-into-a-deeper-identity’ and it sets the stage for ideas of liberation (mokṣa) as a permanent shift to the pervasive level of being, in contrast to the repeated arising of contingent forms in reincarnation. In two further enacted teachings, Śvetaketu is invited to open a seed to find the source of the banyan tree (famed for its complex network of limbs, roots, and trunks), but he sees nothing, just a fine ‘essence’. He dissolves crystals of salt in water, and then tastes the invisible quality of salt throughout the fluid. We learn that the underlying ‘essence’ can be invisible, but we may realise it through inference to a shared cause.
- 6.14–16:
- [when a man] is innocent of the crime, then he turns himself into the truth; uttering the truth and covering himself with the truth, he takes hold of the ax and is not burnt, upon which he is released. "What on that occasion prevents him from being burnt—that constitutes the self of this whole world; that is the truth; that is the self. And that’s how you are, Svetaketu." And he did, indeed, learn it from him.36The analogies of a lost, blindfolded man going home when his sight is restored, a dying man whose conscious faculties merge back into the ‘highest deity,’ and an accused man who proves his crime by passing the test of grasping a heated ‘truth-telling’ axe, suggest that humans can be united with broader properties. The last analogy crucially connects the foregoing metaphysical points to human agency: One can embody properties, like ‘true’ or ‘false,’ that transcend our finite individuality, and change our very fabric.
8. Soteriological Aims: Inference as Phenomenological Liberation from Finitude
This deeply serene one who, after he rises up from this body and reaches the highest light, emerges in his own true appearance—that is the self," he said, "that is the immortal; that is the one free from fear; that is brahman." Now, the name of this brahman is “Real” (satyam).38
- We can see things in terms of the broader principles that they instantiate. These principles are both actual and potential (one can know what has not been seen through them, etc.) so that when one sees the world as ‘clay, iron and gold’ it is really the universals that one learns to perceive.
- An origin story lays the ground to envision (a) all beings, and (b) different qualities as forms of a single underlying reality.
- A new model explaining contingent phenomena as the evolved manifestation of more basic principles invites us to see particular forms (rūpa) as the sign of an underlying evolving substrate.
- We are invited to see becoming as an arising out of that substrate and ending as a return. All things become inferential signs of the divine. As we can understand that salt is unseen in water, so we can see brahman in the world; and as we see the signs of an underlying vital force in our selves, so we can experience ourselves as ‘buds’ of the ‘root’ reality.
- The examples are turned back upon the human person: We can reorient ourselves like the un-blindfolded man, merge our faculties back into the substrate, and knowing and embodying brahman, we can become it as an honest man becomes an instance of truth.
Now, the teaching of the ‘’I’—’I am, indeed, below; I am above; I am in the west; I am in the east; I am in the south; and I am in the north. Indeed, I extend over this whole world’39
9. Indian Philosophical ‘Religiosity’ on the Heideggerian Model
Augustine’s entire vision of man… is predicated on the belief that man was made for eternity… Firstly, that God dwells at the centre of each heart and continually recalls it to him… Secondly, that death is not the natural end point of human existence…
I experience value-relations without the slightest element of ought being given. In the morning I enter the study; the sun lies over the books, etc., and I delight in this. Such delight is in no way an ought… There is, therefore, a kind of lived experience in which I take delight, in which the valuable as such is given.(p. 37)
The value ‘is’ not, but rather it ‘values’ in an intransitive sense…. our language is not adequate to the new basic type of lived experience involved here.(p. 37)
In worth-taking the ‘it values’ does something to me, it pervades me… in value-taking there is nothing theoretical: it has its own ‘light’, spreads its own illumination: ‘lumen gloriae’.(p. 39)
Funding
Conflicts of Interest
References
- Acharya, Diwakar. 2015. This World, in the Beginning, was Phenomenally Non-existent: Āruṇi’s Discourse on Cosmogony in Chāndogya Upaniṣad VI.I-VI.7. Journal of Indian Philosophy 44: 833–64. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Acharya, Diwakar. 2017. On the Meaning and Function of Ādeśa in the Early Upaniṣads. Journal of Indian Philosophy 45: 539–67. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Backman, Jussi. 2015. Complicated Presence: Heidegger and the Postmetaphysical Unity of Being. Albany: State University of New York Press. [Google Scholar]
- Black, Brian. 2007. The Character of the Self in Ancient India: Priests, Kings, and Women in the Early Upaniṣads. Albany: State University of New York Press. [Google Scholar]
- Bodewitz, Henk Wilhelm. 2001. Uddālaka’s teaching in Chāndogya Upaniṣad 6, 8-16. Indo-Iranian Journal 44: 289–98. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Brereton, Joel. 1986. ‘Tat Tvam Asi’ in context. Zeitschrift der Deustchen Morgenländischen Gesellschaft 136: 98–109. [Google Scholar]
- Brereton, Joel. 1990. The Upanishads. In Approaches to the Asian Classics. Edited by William Theodore de Bary and Irene Bloom. New York: Columbia University Press, pp. 115–35. [Google Scholar]
- Brereton, Joel. 1999. Edifying Puzzlement: Ṛg Veda 10.129 and the Uses of Enigma. Journal of the American Oriental Society 19: 248–60. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bronkhorst, Johannes. 2007. Greater Magadha: Studies in the Culture of Early India. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar]
- Bronkhorst, Johannes. 2017. Brahmanism: Its Place in Ancient Indian Society. Contributions in Indian Sociology 51: 361–69. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Caland, William, and Victor Henry. 2010. L’Agniṣṭoma: Description Complète de la Forme Normale du Sacrifice de Soma dans la Cultue Védique. Reprint. Geneva: Editions Slatkine. First published 1906. [Google Scholar]
- Caputo, John. 1978. The Mystical Element in Heidegger’s Thought. Athens: Ohio University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Cohen, Signe. 2018. The Upaniṣads: A Complete Guide. Abingdon: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Deutsch, Eliot. 1988. Knowledge and the Tradition Text in Indian Philosophy. In Interpreting Across Boundaries: New Essays in Comparative Philosophy. Edited by Eliot Deutsch and Gerald Larson. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Edgerton, Franklin. 1915. Studies of the Veda. Journal of the American Oriental Society 35: 240–46. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Edgerton, Franklin. 1965. The Beginnings of Indian Philosophy. London: George Allen & Unwin Ltd. [Google Scholar]
- Flood, Gavin. 2013. The Truth Within: A History of Inwardness in Christianity, Hinduism, and Buddhism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Frazier, Jessica. 2014. On Vedānta: Metaphors for the Category of Everything. In Categorisation in Indian Philosophy: Thinking Inside the Box. Farnham: Ashgate. [Google Scholar]
- Frazier, Jessica. 2017. Hindu Worldviews: Theories of Self, Ritual and Reality. London: Bloomsbury. [Google Scholar]
- Frazier, Jessica. 2019. “Speakers of Highest Truth”: Plurilogues about Brahman in the early Upaniṣads. In In Dialogue with Classical Indian Traditions: Encounter, Transformation, and Interpretation. Edited by Brian Black and Chakravarthi Ramprasad. Abingdon: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Frazier, Jessica. forthcoming. The Classical Roots of Hindu Philosophy. In The Blackwell Companion to Hinduism, 2nd ed. Edited by Gavin Flood. Oxford: Blackwell.
- Ganeri, Jonardon. 2007. The Concealed Art of the Self: Theories of Self and Practices of Truth in Indian Ethics and Epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ganeri, Jonardon. 2012. The Self: Naturalism, Consciousness and the First Person Stance. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ganeri, Jonardon. 2017. Attention, Not Self. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Gonda, Jan. 1970. Notes on Names and the Name of God in Ancient India. Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing Company. [Google Scholar]
- Hadot, Pierre. 1995. Philosophy as a Way of Life: Spiritual Exercises from Socrates to Foucault. Translated by Michael Chase. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing. [Google Scholar]
- Hanefeld, Erhardt. 1976. Philosophische Haupttext der alteren Upaniṣaden. Wiesbaden: O. Harrasowitz. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, Martin. 1995. The Fundamental Concepts of Metaphysics: World, Finitude, Solitude. Translated by William McNeill, and Nicholas Walker. Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, Martin. 2004. The Phenomenology of Religious Life. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, Martin. 2008. Towards the Definition of Philosophy. Translated by Ted Sandler. London: Continuum. [Google Scholar]
- Kahrs, Eivind. 1998. Indian Semantic Analysis: The ‘Nirvacana’ Tradition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kane, P. V. 1962–1975. History of Dharma Śástra, rev. ed. 5 vols. Poona: Bhandarkar Oriental Research Institute. [Google Scholar]
- Lincoln, Bruce. 2006. How to Read a Religious Text: Reflections on Some Passages of the Chāndogya Upaniṣad. History of Religions 46: 127–39. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Marx, Werner. 1971. Heidegger and the Tradition. Translated by Theodor Kisiel. Evanston: Northwestern University Press. [Google Scholar]
- McGrath, Sean, and Andrzej Wiercinski. 2010. A Companion to Heidegger’s Phenomenology of Religion. Amsterdam: Brill. [Google Scholar]
- Morgenroth, Wolfgang. 1970. Die Lehre des Uddālaka Āruṇi: Ch.-Up VI. Archiv Orientální 38: 33–44. [Google Scholar]
- Olivelle, Patrick. 1998. The Early Upaniṣads. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Pattison, George, and Kate Kirkpatrick. 2019. The Mystical Sources of Existentialist Thought: Being, Nothingness, Love. Abingdon: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Raveh, Daniel. 2008. Ayam aham asmīti: Self-consciousness and Identity in the Eighth Chapter of the Chāndogya Upanişad vs. Śankara’s Bhāşya. Journal of Indian Philosophy 36: 319–33. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Renou, Louis. 1955. Remarques sur la Chandogya-Upanisad. In His Études Védiques et Paninéennes 1. Paris: E. de Boccard, pp. 91–102. [Google Scholar]
- Scheler, Max. 1973. Phenomology and the Theory of Cognition. In Selected Philosophical Essays. Edited by David Lachterman. Evanston: Northwestern University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Slaje, Walter. 2009. Upanischaden, Arkanum des Veda: Aus dem Sanskrit übersetzt und herausgegeben. Frankfurt: Verlag der Weltreligionen. [Google Scholar]
- Thieme, Paul. 1968. ‘Adeśa’, Mélanges d’ Indianisme: a la Memoire de Louis Renou. Paris: Boccard, pp. 715–23. [Google Scholar]
- Visigalli, P. 2014. ‘Continuity and Change in Chāndogya Upaniṣad VI.1–4’, Puṣpikā: Tracing Ancient India Through Texts and Traditions, Contributions to Current Research in Indology. Edited by G. Ciotti, A. Giornall and P. Visigalli. Oxford: Oxbow Books, vol. II, pp. 191–216. [Google Scholar]
- Visigalli, P. 2018. An Early Indian Interpretive Puzzle: Vedic Etymologies as a Tool for Thinking. Journal of Indian Philosophy 46: 983–1007. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Witzel, Michael. 1997. The Development of the Vedic Canon and its Schools: The Social and Political Milieu. In Inside the Texts Beyond the Texts: New Approaches to the Study of the Vedas. Harvard Oriental Series Opera Minora, 2. Cambridge: Department of Sanskrit and Indian Studies, pp. 257–345. [Google Scholar]
- Wolfe, Judith. 2014. Heidegger and Theology. London: Bloomsbury. [Google Scholar]
- Zaborowski, Holger. 2010. A “Genuinely Religious Oriented Personality”: Martin Heidegger and the Religious and Theological Origins of his Philosophy. In A Companion to Heidegger’s Phenomenology of Religious Life. Edited by S. J. McGrath and A. Wiercinski. Amsterdam: Editions Rodopi B.V. [Google Scholar]
1 | The Upaniṣads are generally taken as introducing proto-philosophical ideas about metaphysics, identity, causality, and selfhood, that would later be refined in India’s scholastic traditions. Texts, like the Chāndogya Upaniṣad, a c.7th century reflection on language and meaning, universalisation and essence, and finitude and immortality, highlights the uses of philosophical thinking as a spiritual exercise—using inference as a tool for changing the focus of our thought and thereby reshaping the self (Frazier 2017, pp. 87, 113–16, 135–38). |
2 | uta tam ādeśam aprākṣyo yenāśrutaṃ śrutaṃ bhavaty amataṃ matam avijñātaṃ vijñātam iti| kathaṃ nu bhagavaḥ sa ādeśo bhavatīti| (CU6.1.3). Translations of the Upaniṣads are based on Olivelle 1998. The text draws on the rich classical Sanskritic range of vocabulary for mental reflection of different kinds, arguably ‘deepening’ cognitively from perception (śruta) to thought (mata) to understanding or discernment (vijñāta). It also suggests an almost paradoxical magical power in making the ‘unheard heard’, the ‘unseen seen.’ |
3 | All references to the Phenomenology of Religious Life use the translation found in (Heidegger 2004). |
4 | See, e.g., Wolfe (2014); Pattison and Kirkpatrick (2019); and Caputo (1978) on Heidegger’s continuity with mystical thinkers, such as Eckhart and Zaborowski (2010, p. 6), on his early personal theology of grace as ‘immediate relation to a transcendent being.’ |
5 | A number of scholars detail the way certain Indian texts focus on the structures of subjectivity in a manner that could be called ‘phenomenological’; e.g., Jonardon Ganeri’s work on Indian insights into the nature and limits of consciousness (Ganeri 2007), its deconstruction of ‘the first person stance’ (Ganeri 2012), and Hindu-Buddhist debates’ focus on the potential of the fragmented self to be dissolved or unified by the mental capacity of attention (Ganeri 2017). So too, Gavin Flood has given a Heideggerian reading of the Kaśmiri Śaiva tradition’s methods for re-engineering subjectivity (Flood 2013); and Frazier (2017) has looked at the forms and methods of mutability that characterise the Upaniṣadic conception of the self. |
6 | While there are clear cases of monism in the West, and dualism of God and world in India, nevertheless, a metaphysics of divine grounding and emanation predominates in Vedāntic traditions, while creation ex nihilo or from a separate substance is virtually unknown (see Frazier 2014 on Vedāntic ontological monisms). |
7 | All references to On the Definition of Philosophy use the translation found in (Heidegger 2008). |
8 | Heidegger alludes to the presence of a hermeneutic circle in this study of cosmology, philosophy, and values, which must of necessity import the observer’s own cosmology, philosophy, and values: ‘One must forthrightly deliver oneself over to the circle which lies within the very idea of primordial science. There is no escape from this… the Munchausen problem of the spirit’ (p. 15), but this is not a problem for the kind of non-objective reading that phenomenology seeks. It can be overcome not in the sense of getting rid of it, but ‘in such a way that this circularity can immediately be seen as necessary and as belonging to the very essence of philosophy’ (p. 15). |
9 | For this, he makes it clear that a good knowledge of the original language is required, a relatively unbiased translation (Heidegger rejects Luther’s reading), and a full awareness of the historical context (including ‘the struggle with the Jews and Jewish Christians,’ p. 48; ‘the first missionary trip in Corinth,’ p. 60; and the shift from the message of an imminent arrival of Christ to a Christian version of Ancient Near Eastern eschatology, p. 79). |
10 | Heidegger acknowledges some now well-known hermeneutic critiques of empathy as a means of knowing other individuals, arguing ‘that we cannot at all, with our ideas, put ourselves in Paul’s place… the problem of the presentation, empathy, and explication of “autonomized individuals” is badly posed’ (p. 62). |
11 | The aim of the text and its importance are flagged up at the outset where Heidegger tells us ‘the aim of “salvation,” finally “life.” (PRL 48). |
12 | We will see that Heidegger cautions his students against using the phenomenological method of reading religious texts merely as a way to line up different religious perspectives as ‘a bare collection of material,’ an approach that ‘is entirely usual today, after all’ (PRL 52). |
13 | Heidegger marks as ‘significant’ the ‘complete break with the earlier past, with every non-Christian view of life’ that he sees at 1:10 in Galatians (PRL 48). |
14 | Heidegger intriguingly likens the believer’s rejection of any outside objectification of his belief, to the negative philosopher’s refusal to legitimise any reductive account of the divine (pp. 77–78). |
15 | The choice of Paul as a paradigmatic text seems linked to the importance of experience in the Damascene conversion narrative and the view that Paul’s Christian experience might have been primal, standing independently of the historical advent of Jesus (PRL 49). |
16 | Useful scholarship on the Chāndogya Upaniṣad as a whole includes (Renou 1955; Brereton 1990; Witzel 1997), and a good summary can be found in (Cohen 2018). |
17 | imāḥ somya nadyaḥ purastāt prācyaḥ syandante paścāt pratīcyaḥ| tāḥ samudrāt samudram evāpi yanti| sa mudra eva bhavati| sa ya eṣo ‘ṇimaitad ātmyam idaṃ sarvam| tat satyam| sa ātmā| tat tvam asi… (CU 6.10.1–3). ‘Truth’ here (satya) is the same word used to refer to the pervasive material reality of ‘clay’ in the central metaphor. |
18 | The closest ‘Western’ cultural parallel is with the flourishing of ancient Greek ideas about the basic constituent of the cosmos, amongst which Heidegger included Platos’ Ideas, Aristotle’s Energeia, Heraclitus’ Logos, Parmenides’ Moira, and Anaximander’s Chreon, all of which serve a function as a unifying ‘one’ (see Backman 2015). |
19 | Bronkhorst (2007, 2017) compellingly (if sometimes controversially) describes the cultural development of India’s northern kingdoms as they combined strands of Brahminical, Buddhist, Jain, and other traditions. To some extent, once brahminical culture was ‘no longer primarily a sacrificial tradition, it became mainly a socio-political ideology that borrowed much (including the belief in rebirth and karmic retribution) from the eastern region in which Buddhism and Jainism had arisen.’ (Bronkhorst 2017, p. 361). The process also involved an internal rethinking of the status, expertise, and proper work of the brahminical intelligentsia (see Black 2007). Philosophical material also emerged from continuous evolution of brahminical notions of creation, cosmos, power, and reasoning (Frazier, forthcoming). |
20 | The economy of patronage for the priests’ ritual expertise and new cosmological ideas was also a factor in encouraging the development of philosophical styles of Hindu religiosity (see Black 2007). The Upaniṣads and epics contain episodes in which brahmins struggle for economic advantage using ritual and metaphysical knowledge as their medium (see, e.g., Lincoln 2006). |
21 | This was associated with a stock of tales about ‘celebrities’ of the northern intelligentsia—teachers who were the gospel writers of classical India, as it were. Such characters include the brahmins, Uddālaka Āruṇi, Yajñavalkya, and Satyakāma Jābala; and kings, Janaka and Pravāhana Jaivali. |
22 | The textual situation of the Chāndogya Upaniṣad is that it is part of the Vedic corpus of Sanskrit texts themed around a set of rituals performed by Brahmin priests in the first millennium BCE. It constitutes the last eight chapters in the Chāndogya Brahmana, ritual texts embedded in the Sāma-Veda’s metrically annotated hymns. The first two chapters focus specifically on the syllable, Om, and the High Chant (udgītha), identifying them as equivalent to the whole world, and exploring correlations with other pervasive realities, such as space. Chapters 6–8 are a more sustained development of a central ‘teaching’ (ādeśa) that appears to be about the ability to identify pervasive features of the perceived world. In adducing new material to support his emerging theories, the redactor is also a ‘philosopher-commentator… contributing something to it through it through his creative appropriation of its very life and being’ (Deutsch 1988, p. 170). In redaction ‘each available conceptual structure thus shows the limitations of the others and
suggests an alternative possibility unexplored by them’ (Krishna in Larson and Deutsch 1988, p. 81). |
23 | So too, the themes of unifying structures and identity in change were developed in different Upaniṣads according to the ritual expertise of their authors. The Bṛhad Āraṇyaka Upaniṣad, which focused on the dissection of animals in the Aśvamedha sacrifice, furnishes analogies of torso, core, and structure; the Aitareya, Taittirīya, and Māṇḍūkya concern the proper pronunciation of mantras in ritual recitation according to “phonetics—phoneme, accent, quantity, strength, articulation, and connection” (TU 1.2); the Kauṣītaki concerns the ritual transferring the father’s life-force to his son at the time of death, and uses this to reflect on the ‘essence’ of life. |
24 | The offering of Soma was an important part of the Vedic Agniṣṭoma sacrifice (descriptions of which are given in (Caland and Henry [1906] 2010); Kane 1962–1975, II: 1133–1212), and as Olivelle notes, the whole Upaniṣad is illuminated by knowledge of its practical details. |
25 | rasānām rasatamaḥ paramaḥ parārdhyo ‘ṣṭamo yad udgīthaḥ, CU 1.1.2. |
26 | Scholarship seeking to explain the origins and implications of chapter six includes (Edgerton 1915, 1965; Morgenroth 1970; Hanefeld 1976; Brereton 1986, 1999; Acharya 2017; Visigalli 2018). |
27 | The Chāndogya Upaniṣad’s coherence is stressed by scholars, such as Bodewitz (2001, p. 153) and Slaje (2009, p. 565). Others (e.g., Hanefeld 1976; Acharya 2017) have noted the division between sources marked by textual ‘frames’ and reflecting quite different views. Acharya in particular notes the contrast between linguistic (broadly Vedic) teachings that reflect a focus on meaning and ontological foundations, with cosmogonic (noticeably proto-Sāṃkhya) teachings that emphasise transformation and evolution. |
28 | Other sections within the CU depict Vedic knowledge as a beehive: The existing sciences of Rg verses, Yajus ritual-formulas, Sāman chants, as well as the Atharva and Angirasa spells, itihasa histories, and purāṇa tales are part of this coherent body, like parts of a honeycomb. But the honey of knowledge is the secret ādeśa teachings, and brahman, the knowledge of the foundation and essence of all, is the flower. This knowledge makes up the essence (rasa) of the Vedas, from which flow the splendour (yāśas), ardour (tejas) strength (indriya), and energy (anna) of the world, qualities that one can see as a flickering brightness in the sun (3.1–5). |
29 | uta tam ādeśam prakṣyo yenāśrutaṃ śrutaṃ bhavaty amataṃ matam avijñātaṃ vijñātam iti|… yathā somyaikena mṛt-piṇḍena sarvaṃ mṛn-mayaṃ vijñātaṃ syāt| vācārambhaṇaṃ vikāra nāmadheyaṃ mṛttikety eva satyam. 6.1.1–4. Olivelle translates ādeśa as ‘rule of substitution,’ but given the debates over this, here, we use merely ‘teaching’. |
30 | sad eva somyedam agre āsīd ekam evādvitīyam|… tad aikṣata bahu syāṃ prajāyeyeti|… seyaṃ devataikṣata hantāham imās tisro devata anena jīvenātmanānupraviśya nāmarūpe vyākaraṇīti| CU 6.2.2–3 |
31 | This idea seems to be an early version of the Sāṃkhya school’s satkāryavāda theory that all effects are contained in potentio in their source, retaining their identity in/as it. |
32 | taṃ hovāca yathā somya mahato ‘bhyāhitasyaiko ‘ṅgāraḥ khadyota-mātraḥ pariśiṣṭaḥ syāt| tena tato ‘pi na bahu dahet| CU 6.7. |
33 | The whole series of examples is of embers as the ‘root’ source for fires, the mind as a ‘root’ of memory, consciousness as a ‘root’ present even in sleep, a bird resting on the ‘root’ of a tree before flying away again, a flock repeatedly ‘driven’ by its ‘root’ mover who is the shepherd, a literal root as the source from which plant buds arise repeatedly, and a dying man merging back into his ‘root’ in the highest deity, the self of the whole world, from which presumably he can arise again. |
34 | sa ya eṣo ‘ṇimaitad ātmyam idaṃ sarvam| tatsatyam| sa ātmā| tat tvam asi śvetaketo| CU 6.9.4. ‘Aṇiman’ here could evoke a particle or atomic essence, or subtle material (as opposed, for instance, the rasa used here which means a substantial, qualitative or elemental essence. It may be that aṇiman signifies a hidden, subtle metaphysical level of reality. |
35 | Bodewitz (2001, p. 195) has brought out the conceptual differences between the examples used in the second section of chapter 6, with some focusing on merging into a prior and posterior base, and others focusing on subtle hidden essences of things; slightly different possible soteriologies are implied in each type. |
36 | atha yadi tasyākartā bhavati| tata eva satyam ātmānaṃ kurute| sa satyābhisandhaḥ satyenātmānam antardhāya paraśuṃ taptaṃ pratigṛhṇāti| san a dahyate| atha mucyate|| sa yathā tatra nādāhyeta| etad ātmyam idaṃ sarvam| tat satyam| sa ātmā| tat tvam asi śvetaketo iti| tad dhāsya vijajñāv iti vijajñāv iti|| CU 6.16.2–3. |
37 | Since Paul Thieme, this has been interpreted in reference to the Paniṇian notion of a grammatical ‘substitution,’ where one understands that one thing generally behaves like (and thus can be substituted for) another (see Kahrs 1998, chp. 5 for discussion of this). Olivelle (1998) carries over this translation, although Acharya (2015) has argued that it is synonymous with ‘upaniṣad’ in signifying a special teaching, and that neti neti apophasis in the Bṛhad Āraṇyaka Upaniṣad is another example. In CU 6, there is debate over whether the ādeśa refers to 6.1.1’s teaching that all ‘name-and-form’ is only the temporary limitation of an underlying reality (later called an upādhi or ‘limiting condition’), or to the cosmogonic teaching that the origin of reality lies in Being’s (sat) evolution through into the many-facetted world. This may be the extension of earlier Vedic cosmogonies from a self-proliferating one, juxtaposed with an ‘evolution’ theory containing Sāṃkhya elements of satkāryavāda, prakṛti and vyakta concepts (Acharya 2015, p. 862). Either way, this ‘theory of knowledge’ echoes repeatedly through the chapter (Thieme 1968; Visigalli 2014). |
38 | atha ya eṣa saṃprasādo ‘smāc charīrāt samutthāya paraṃ jyotir upasampadya svena rupenābhiniṣpadyata eṣa ātmeti|| CU 8.3.4. |
39 | athato ‘haṅkārādeśa eva| aham evādhāstād aham upariṣṭād ahaṃ paścād ahaṃ purastād ahaṃ dakṣinato ‘ham uttarato evedaṃ sarvam iti|| CU 7.25.1. |
40 | This is not to argue that there is no conception of liberation as a future event in this chapter: Certain of the chapter’s analogies depict individuals merging (saṃpad-) back into an underlying source. We see this in 6.9’s image of different flowers united in a single nectar, 6.10’s image of rivers united in a single ocean, or (perhaps) 6.14’s man returning home, and 6.15’s merging of consciousness back into its source. An explicit generalisation of this idea to all beings is made at 6.9.2–3, further amplified in hints at transcending death (6.14–16). That idea is further developed in chapter eight (see also Raveh 2008). |
41 | E.g., Bṛhad Āraṇyaka Upaniṣad 2.4.12 or Māṇḍūkya Upaniṣad 5. More directly introspective forms of phenomenological recognition are implied in Upaniṣads, such as the Kena, Māṇḍūkya, Kāṭha, and Kauṣitakī, and are central to the notions of sensory withdrawal (pratyāhāra) and meditative focus (dhyāna) in the Yoga Sūtras. By contrast the Chāndogya Upaniṣad (and also texts, such as the Sāṃkhya Kārikās) seem more concerned with the realisation that a single ontological substratum must underlie the diversity of changing forms. |
© 2019 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Frazier, J. “Become This Whole World”: The Phenomenology of Metaphysical Religion in Chāndogya Upaniṣad 6–8. Religions 2019, 10, 368. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel10060368
Frazier J. “Become This Whole World”: The Phenomenology of Metaphysical Religion in Chāndogya Upaniṣad 6–8. Religions. 2019; 10(6):368. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel10060368
Chicago/Turabian StyleFrazier, Jessica. 2019. "“Become This Whole World”: The Phenomenology of Metaphysical Religion in Chāndogya Upaniṣad 6–8" Religions 10, no. 6: 368. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel10060368
APA StyleFrazier, J. (2019). “Become This Whole World”: The Phenomenology of Metaphysical Religion in Chāndogya Upaniṣad 6–8. Religions, 10(6), 368. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel10060368