Religious Interactions in Deliberative Democratic Systems Theory
Abstract
:1. Pragmatist Faith in Deliberative Democracy
1.1. Beyond Pragmatist Secularism, Relativism, and Narcissism
1.2. Pragmatist Truth in Deliberative Democracy
2. Religion in Deliberative Democratic Systems Theory
2.1. Criteria of Inclusion in DDST
2.2. Precluding Religion in DDST
3. Religious Interactions in Pragmatist DDST
Funding
Conflicts of Interest
References
- Bächtiger, Andre, John Dryzek, Jane Mansbridge, and Mark Warren, eds. 2018. Deliberative Democracy: An Introduction. In The Oxford Handbook of Deliberative Democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Barton, Carlin, and Daniel Boyarin. 2016. Imagine No Religion: How Modern Abstractions Hide Ancient Realities. New York: Fordham University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Bell, David Avrom. 2019. An Equal Say: Where Does Truth Fit into Democracy. The Nation. January 24. Available online: https://www.thenation.com/article/archive/david-bell-democracy-and-truth (accessed on 2 February 2019).
- Blackford, Russell. 2012. Freedom of Religion and the Secular State. Malden: Blackwell Press. [Google Scholar]
- Bohman, James. 1996. Public Deliberation: Pluralism, Complexity and Democracy. Cambridge: MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
- Bohman, James. 2001. Participants, Observers, and Critics: Practical knowledge, Social Perspectives, and Critical Pluralism. In Pluralism and the Pragmatic Turn: The Transformation of Critical Theory. Edited by James Bohman and William Rehg. Cambridge: MIT Press, pp. 87–113. [Google Scholar]
- Bohman, James. 2007. Democracy across Borders: From Demos to Demoi. Cambridge: MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
- Bohman, James. 2012. Representation in the Deliberative System. In Deliberative Systems: Deliberative Democracy at the Large Scale. Edited by John Parkinson and Jane Mansbridge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 72–94. [Google Scholar]
- Brahm Levey, Geoffrey, and Tariq Modood, eds. 2009. Liberal Democracy, Multicultural Citizenship and the Danish Cartoon Affair. In Secularism, Religion and Multicultural Citizenship. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 216–42. [Google Scholar]
- Brandom, Robert. 1994. Making It Explicit: Reasoning, Representing, and Discursive Commitment. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Brandom, Robert. 2000. Vocabularies of Pragmatism: Synthesizing Naturalism and Historicism. In Rorty and His Critics. Edited by Robert Brandom. Malden: Blackwell Publishers, pp. 156–82. [Google Scholar]
- Brandom, Robert. 2011. Perspectives on Pragmatism: Classical, Recent, and Contemporary. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Cavanaugh, William. 1995. A Fire Strong Enough to Consume the House: Wars of Religion the Rise of the State. Modern Theology 11: 397–420. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Chambers, Simone. 2012. Deliberation and Mass Democracy. In Deliberative Systems: Deliberative Democracy at the Large Scale. Edited by John Parkinson and Jane Mansbridge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 52–71. [Google Scholar]
- Chastain, Charles. 1975. Reference and Context. In Language, Mind, and Knowledge. Edited by Keith Gunderson. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 194–269. [Google Scholar]
- Davidson, Donald. 2006. Truth and Meaning. In The Essential Davidson. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 155–70. First published 1967. [Google Scholar]
- Davidson, Donald. 2006. A Coherence Theory of Truth and Knowledge. In The Essential Davidson. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 225–37. First published 1983. [Google Scholar]
- Davidson, Donald. 2006. Appendix: Afterthoughts. In The Essential Davidson. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 238–41. First published 1987. [Google Scholar]
- Davidson, Donald. 1990. The Structure and Content of Truth. Journal of Philosophy 87: 281–328. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Davidson, Donald. 1995. Could There Be a Science of Rationality. International Journal of Philosophical Studies 3: 1–16. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Davidson, Donald. 1996. The Folly of Trying to Define Truth. Journal of Philosophy 93: 263–78. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Davidson, Donald. 2000. Truth Rehabilitated. In Rorty and His Critics. Edited by Robert Brandom. Malden: Blackwell Publishers, pp. 65–73. [Google Scholar]
- Derrida, Jacques. 1972. Limited Inc. Evanston: Northwestern University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Derrida, Jacques. 1984. My Chances/Mes Chances: A Rendezvous with Some Epicurean Stereophonies. In Taking Chances: Derrida, Psychoanalysis, and Literature. Edited by Joseph H. Smith and William Kerrigan. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, pp. 1–32. [Google Scholar]
- Derrida, Jacques. 1996. Remarks on Deconstruction and Pragmatism. In Deconstruction and Pragmatism: Simon Critchley, Jacques Derrida, Ernesto Laclau and Richard Rorty. Edited by Chantal Mouffe. New York: Routledge, pp. 79–90. [Google Scholar]
- Dewey, John. 1998. The Problem of Truth. In The Essential Dewey. Edited by Larry Hickman and Thomas Alexander. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, vol. 1, pp. 101–30. First published 1911. [Google Scholar]
- Dewey, John. 1946. The Public and Its Problems. Chicago: Gateway Books. First published 1927. [Google Scholar]
- Dewey, John. 2013. A Common Faith. New Haven: Yale University Press. First published 1934. [Google Scholar]
- Dryzek, John. 2000. Deliberative Democracy and Beyond: Liberals, Critics, Contestations. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Dryzek, John. 2004. Pragmatism and Democracy: In Search of Deliberative Publics. The Journal of Speculative Philosophy 18: 72–79. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dryzek, John. 2005. Deliberative Democracy in Divided Societies: Alternatives to Agonism and Analgesia. Political Theory 33: 218–42. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Fish, Stanley. 1999a. Mutual Respect as a Device of Exclusion. In Deliberative Politics: Essays on Democracy and Disagreement. Edited by Stephen Macedo. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 88–102. [Google Scholar]
- Fish, Stanley. 1999b. The Trouble with Principle. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Fishkin, James. 2009. When the People Speak: Deliberative Democracy and Public Consultation. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Floridia, Antonio. 2018. The Origins of the Deliberative Turn. In The Oxford Handbook of Deliberative Democracy. Edited by Andre Bächtiger, John Dryzek, Jane Mansbridge and Mark Warren. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 35–54. [Google Scholar]
- Fung, Archon. 2005. Deliberation Before the Revolution: Toward an Ethics of Deliberative Democracy in an Unjust World. Political Theory 33: 397–419. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Fung, Archon, and Erik Olin Wright. 2003. Deepening Democracy: Institutional Innovations in Empowered Participatory Governance. New York: Verso. [Google Scholar]
- Galston, William. 1999. Diversity, Toleration, and Deliberative Democracy: Religious Minorities and Public Schooling. In Deliberative Politics: Essays on Democracy and Disagreement. Edited by Stephen Macedo. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 39–48. [Google Scholar]
- Gastil, John, E. Pierre Deess, Philip Weiser, and Cindy Simmons. 2010. The Jury and Democracy: How Jury Deliberation Promotes Civic Engagement and Political Participation. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Goodin, Robert. 2005. Sequencing Deliberative Moments. Acta Politica 40: 182–96. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Gutmann, Amy, and Denis Thompson. 1990. Moral Conflict and Political Consensus. Ethics 101: 64–88. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gutmann, Amy, and Dennis Thompson. 1996. Democracy and Disagreement. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Gutmann, Amy, and Dennis Thompson. 2004. Why Deliberative Democracy? Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Habermas, Jürgen. 1996. Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy. Cambridge: Polity Press. [Google Scholar]
- Habermas, Jürgen. 2001. The Postnational Constellation. Cambridge: MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
- Habermas, Jürgen. 2002. Postscript: Some Concluding Remarks. In Habermas and Pragmatism. Edited by Mitchell Aboiulafia, Myra Bookman and Cathy Kemp. New York: Routledge Press, pp. 223–33. [Google Scholar]
- Habermas, Jürgen. 2004. Religious Tolerance—the Pacemaker for Cultural Rights. Philosophy 79: 5–18. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Habermas, Jürgen. 2006. Political Communication in Media Society: Does Democracy Still Enjoy an Epistemic Dimension? The Impact of Normative Theory on Empirical Research. Communication Theory 16: 411–26. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Harris, Sam. 2005. The End of Faith: Religion, Terror, and the Future of Reason. New York: W.W. Norton and Company. [Google Scholar]
- Heath, Joseph. 2006. Jürgen Habermas. In A Companion to Pragmatism. Edited by John Shook John and Joseph Margolis. Malden: Wiley-Blackwell, pp. 120–26. [Google Scholar]
- Hick, John. 2007. Is there a Global Ethic? A Talk Given to the Center for the Study of Global Ethics: The University of Birmingham, UK. Available online: http://www.johnhick.org.uk/article17.html (accessed on 10 November 2017).
- Hoelzl, Michael, and Graham Ward. 2008. The New Visibility of Religion. London: Continuum. [Google Scholar]
- Knight, Jack, and James Johnson. 2011. The Priority of Democracy: Political Consequences of Pragmatism. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Küng, Hans. 1993. Christianity and World Religions: Paths of Dialogue with Islam, Hinduism, and Buddhism. Maryknoll: Orbis Books. [Google Scholar]
- Küng, Hans. 1998. A Global Ethic for Global Politics and Economics. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Küng, Hans, and Karl-Josef Kuschel. 1993. A Global Ethic: The Declaration of the Parliament of the World’s Religions. New York: Continuum. [Google Scholar]
- Lijphart, Arend. 1977. Democracy in Plural Societies: A Comparative Exploration. New Haven: Yale University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Lijphart, Arend. 2000. Varieties of Nonmajoritarian Democracy. In Democracy and Institutions: The Life Work of Arend Lijphard. Edited by Markus Crepaz, Thomas Koelble and David Wilsford. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, pp. 225–46. [Google Scholar]
- Locke, John. 1985. A Letter Concerning Toleration. Edited by James Tully. Indianapolis: Hackett Press, pp. 23–39. First published 1689. [Google Scholar]
- MacKenzie, Michael, and Mark Warren. 2012. Two Trust-Based Uses of Minipublics in Democratic Systems. In Deliberative Systems: Deliberative Democracy at the Large Scale. Edited by John Parkinson and Jane Mansbridge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 95–124. [Google Scholar]
- Maddox, Graham. 1996. Religion and the Rise of Democracy. New York: Routledge Press. [Google Scholar]
- Mansbridge, Jane. 1999. Everyday Talk in the Deliberative System. In Deliberative Politics: Essays on Democracy and Disagreement. Edited by Stephen Macedo. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 211–39. [Google Scholar]
- Mansbridge, Jane, James Bohman, Simone Chambers, Thomas Christiano, Archon Fung, John Parkinson, Dennis F. Thompson, and Mark E. Warren. 2012. A Systemic Approach to Deliberative Democracy. In Deliberative Systems: Deliberative Democracy at the Large Scale. Edited by John Parkinson and Jane Mansbridge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 1–27. [Google Scholar]
- March, Andrew, and Alicia Steinmetz. 2018. Religious Reasons in Public Deliberation. In The Oxford Handboook of Deliberative Democracy. Edited by Andre Bächtiger, John Dryzek, Jane Mansbridge and Mark Warren. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 203–17. [Google Scholar]
- Misak, Cheryl. 2000. Truth, Politics, Morality. New York: Routledge Press. [Google Scholar]
- Misak, Cheryl. 2009. Truth and Democracy: Pragmatism and the Deliberative Virtues. In Does Truth Matter?: Democracy and Public Space. Edited by Raf Geenens and Ronald Tinnevelt. New York: Springer Press, pp. 29–40. [Google Scholar]
- Moufe, Chantal. 1999. Deliberative Democracy or Agonistic Pluralism? Social Research 66: 745–58. [Google Scholar]
- Nagel, Thomas. 1987. Moral Conflict and Political Legitimacy. Philosophy and Public Affairs 16: 223–27. [Google Scholar]
- Nongbri, Brent. 2013. Before Religion: A History of a Modern Concept. New Haven: Yale University Press. [Google Scholar]
- O’Donovan, Oliver. 1999. The Desire of the Nations: Rediscovering the Roots of Political Theology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Parkinson, John. 2006. Deliberating in the Real World: Problems of Legitimacy in Deliberative Democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Patton, Paul. 2016. Multiculturalism and Political Ontology. In The Ashgate Research Companion to Multiculturalism. Edited by Duncan Ivison. New York: Ashgate Press, pp. 57–74. [Google Scholar]
- Posner, Richard. 2003. Law, Pragmatism and Democracy. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Rawls, John. 1985. Justice as Fairness: Political not Metaphysical. Philosophy and Public Affairs 14: 248–51. [Google Scholar]
- Richards, David. 1986. Toleration and the Constitution. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Rorty, Richard. 1979. Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Rorty, Richard. 1991a. Essays on Heidegger and Others: Philosophical Papers II. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Rorty, Richard. 1991b. Objectivity, Relativism and Truth. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Rorty, Richard. 1999. Religion as Conversation Stopper. In Philosophy and Social Hope. New York: Penguin Books, pp. 168–74. [Google Scholar]
- Rorty, Richard. 2000a. Responding to Brandom. In Rorty and His Critics. Edited by Robert Brandom. Malden: Blackwell Publishers, pp. 183–90. [Google Scholar]
- Rorty, Richard. 2000b. Responding to Ramberg. In Rorty and His Critics. Edited by Robert Brandom. Malden: Blackwell Publishers, pp. 370–77. [Google Scholar]
- Rorty, Richard. 2003. Religion in the Public Square: A Reconsideration. Journal of Religious Ethics 31: 141–49. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rorty, Richard. 2005. Anticlericalism and Atheism. In The Future of Religion. Edited by Santiago Zabala. New York: Columbia University Press, pp. 29–41. [Google Scholar]
- Rorty, Richard. 2011. An Ethics for Today: Finding Common Ground between Philosophy and Religion. New York: Columbia University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Rosenfeld, Sophia. 2019. Democracy and Truth: A Short History. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press. [Google Scholar]
- Santurri, Edmund. 1991. Nihilism Revisited. Journal of Religion 71: 67–78. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sellars, Wilfrid. 1975. Action, Knowledge, and Reality. Edited by Hector-Neri Castaneda. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill. [Google Scholar]
- Smith, Wilfred Cantwell. 1963. The Meaning and End of Religion. New York: Macmillan. [Google Scholar]
- Smith, Graham. 2009. Democratic Innovations: Designing Institutions for Citizen Participation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Steiner, Jürg. 2012. The Foundations of Deliberative Democracy: Empirical Research and Normative Implications. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Stout, Jeffrey. 2001. Ethics after Babel. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Stout, Jeffrey. 2002. Radical Interpretation and Pragmatism: Davidson, Rorty, and Brandom on Truth. In Radical Interpretation in Religion. Edited by Nancy Frankenberry. New York: Cambridge University Press, pp. 25–52. [Google Scholar]
- Stout, Jeffrey. 2004. Democracy and Tradition. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Stout, Jeffrey. 2007. On Our Interest in Getting Things Right: Pragmatism without Narcissism. In New Pragmatists. Edited by Cheryl Misak. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 7–31. [Google Scholar]
- Stout, Jeffrey. 2008. 2007 Presidential Address: The Folly of Secularism. Journal of the American Academy of Religion 76: 533–44. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Stout, Jeffrey. 2010a. Blessed are the Organized. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Stout, Jeffrey. 2010b. Rorty on Religion and Politics. In The Philosophy of Richard Rorty. Edited by Randall Auxier and Lewis Hahn. Chicago: Open Court Publishers, pp. 523–45. [Google Scholar]
- Talisse, Robert. 2005. Democracy after Liberalism: Pragmatism and Deliberative Politics. New York: Routledge Press. [Google Scholar]
- Talisse, Robert. 2009. Democracy and Moral Conflict. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Wolin, Sheldon. 2004. Politics and Vision. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Wolterstorff, Nicholas. 1997. The Role of Religion in Decision and Discussion of Political Issues. In Religion in the Public Square: The Place of Religious Convictions in Political Debate. Edited by Robert Audi and Nicholas Wolterstorff. New York: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers, pp. 67–120. [Google Scholar]
1 | I begin with Dewey as a reminder that some of the difficulties faced by contemporary democracies are not new. For a brief history of these matters, see Sophia Rosenfeld’s recent Democracy and Truth: A Short History (Rosenfeld 2019). In particular, she notes the longstanding threats to democracy’s modern forms from both “the rise of an elite, technocratic approach to the determination and propagation of truth, and then a populist pushback” (Loc 40). While each particular moment of populism comes with its own practical concerns, it is worth noting that such movements are not necessarily antithetical to the deliberation of truth claims over the course of history. As I will intimate in my conclusions below, DDST has novel potential to contextualize particular cases. Moreover, as David Avrom Bell noted in his review, Rosenfeld makes short shrift of the “postmodernism is to blame” mantra in this regard (Bell 2019). My aim here is to reiterate the need to take the critical work of pragmatist thinkers seriously in this context. |
2 | With two notable exceptions in the chapters by Williams and de Maeseneer, The New Visibility of Religion compendium did not evaluate pragmatist thought in detail (Hoelzl and Ward 2008, pp. 47, 100). This essay aims to respond to that gap. |
3 | Knight and Johnson devote a chapter to this sentiment (Knight and Johnson 2011, pp. 25–50). They target Richard Posner’s claims to pragmatism’s apolitical nature with regard to Heidegger’s pragmatist affiliations (Knight and Johnson 2011, p. 29; citing Posner 2003, p. 55). They rightly point out that while Rorty drew attention to pragmatist themes in Heidegger’s thought, there remained sufficient distance between Heidegger and pragmatism as such (Knight and Johnson 2011, pp. 30–31; citing Rorty 1991a, pp. 17–19). In sum, because Heidegger cannot be reduced to pragmatism, the political implications of his association with National Socialism do not result in the political ambivalence Posner claims are necessary for pragmatist thought. |
4 | For a more comprehensive history of deliberative democracy, see Antonio Floridia’s “The Origins of the Deliberative Turn” (Floridia 2018). He cites both Habermas and John Rawls as the “consolidation of philosophical foundations” in the 1990s, which is the focus of this essay (Floridia 2018, p. 36). |
5 | It is beyond the scope of this essay, but worth noting that Stout makes a similar argument against Sam Harris’s The End of Faith (Harris 2005): “Either (a) they are merely warning us about the dangers of allowing religion into politics… or (b) they are proposing some more aggressive strategy for curtailing the influence of religion on politics” (Stout 2008, p. 538). In either case, Harris does not explain how the exclusion of religion is to be achieved by democratic means. Moreover, there are aspects of Harris’s argument that promote further intolerance of religious people regardless of the specifics of their political dispositions. In part, this is due to Harris’s criticism of religious moderates whose “beliefs provide the context in which scriptural literalism and religious violence can never be adequately opposed” (Harris 2005, p. 45; cited in Stout 2008, p. 537). In Stout’s view, this imperils democratic culture itself. “The pragmatic effect of this proposal in the contemporary American context is clear: there will be no political alliance between non-believers and moderate theists” (Stout 2008, p. 538). |
6 | Stout’s Ethics after Babel had been reviewed as such in Santurri, “Nihilism Revisited” (Santurri 1991; cf. Stout 2002, p. 33n.11). Stout is acutely aware that the seriousness of moral claims about issues such as slavery and violence cannot be left ambiguous in light of pragmatist skepticism concerning realist metaphysics. To this end, Santurri acknowledged that Stout’s intentions were clearly both realist and constructivist (Santurri 1991, p. 75; citing Stout 2001, p. 77). Stout’s persistent resistance to nihilist relativism is evidenced in his ongoing interventions in pragmatist philosophy. His discussion of Brandom outlined below is a case in point. While beyond the scope of this essay, Stout’s summary of “unconditional obligations” (Stout 2004, p. 192), in his chapter on “Democratic Norms in an Age of Terror”, also provides useful responses to “dirty hands” and “emergency” arguments (Stout 2004, pp. 186, 200). |
7 | Stout is citing ambiguities between Davidson’s essays, “Truth Rehabilitated” (Davidson 2000), “The Folly of Trying to Define Truth” (Davidson 1996), and “The Structure and Content of Truth” (Davidson 1990). He does not cite Davidson’s “A Coherence Theory of Truth and Knowledge (1983)” (Davidson [1983] 2006) and “Appendix: Afterthoughts (1987)” (Davidson [1987] 2006), which also shows some of Davidson’s ambiguity on the topic. |
8 | Stout is here attributing to Rorty the less nuanced version of what he actually wrote with regard to “‘ontological’ explanations of the relations between minds and meaning” in Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature: “The aim of all such explanations is to make truth something more than what Dewey called ‘warranted assertability’: more than what our peers will ceteris paribus [other things being equal], let us get away with saying” (Rorty 1979, pp. 175–76). |
9 | It is worth noting that Rorty contends this point with regard to Brandom’s work. Stout defends Brandom against Rorty’s concern that he had reinstated representational metaphysics in Brandom’s essay “Vocabularies of Pragmatism” (Brandom 2000). In sum, Stout thinks that Brandom can be “relying” on social contexts without “referring” to them (Stout 2002, p. 48; cf. Rorty 2000a, pp. 183–90). |
10 | As a case in point, Brandom thinks Derrida, in particular, was overly reliant upon the signified/signifier distinction, which followed from Ferdinand de Sausure (Brandom 2011, p. 204). I do not have the space to examine this relationship here, only to note that Derrida himself was open to pragmatism, intimating a possible “pragrammatology” (Derrida 1972, p. 151; 1984, p. 27; 1996, p. 80). |
11 | Brandom is drawing here upon Charles Chastain’s notion of anaphora in “Reference and Context” (Chastain 1975, pp. 194–269; cf. Brandom 1994, p. 322). |
12 | Not an exhaustive list but relevant examples include the following: Fung and Olin Wright’s Deepening Democracy (Fung and Olin Wright 2003); Gastil et al. The Jury and Democracy (Gastil et al. 2010); Steiner’s The Foundations of Deliberative Democracy (Steiner 2012); Smith’s Democratic Innovations (Smith 2009); Fishkin’s When the People Speak (Fishkin 2009). |
13 | This problem is summarized well in Paul Patton’s essay on multiculturalism (Patton 2016). |
14 | Bohman’s cites the EU, WTO, and UN as cases in point (Bohman 2007, p. 43). As John Dryzek notes, transnational institutions face an increasingly contestatory relation to nationally based civil societies (Bohman 2007, p. 43; citing Dryzek 2000, p. 133). Others, such as Habermas, have tended to emphasize state sovereignty as the location for democratic practices, with more ad hoc arrangements at the international level, or as Habermas calls it, the Postnational Constellation (Habermas 2001; cf. Bohman 2007, p. 39). Bohman recommends deepening the democratic processes at these levels without undermining state democratic practices nor instituting a single governance structure that overrides national sovereignty. I do not have space here to engage in these contested issues, so much as reiterate Bohman’s call to continue to rethink the need to keep the minimum criteria of democratic practices of self-rule and security against domination clearly in view. |
15 | Their full list is worth noting: “Those nodes would include nation-state bodies at different levels of government and with their different legislative houses, administrative agencies, the military, and the staffs of all of these; international bodies at different levels and their staffs; multinational corporations and local businesses; epistemic communities; foundations; political parties and factions within those parties; party campaigns and other partisan forums; religious bodies; schools; universities with their departments, fields, and disciplinary associations; unions, interest groups, voluntary associations and non-governmental organizations (NGOs) both ad hoc and long-standing; social movements with both their enclaves and their broader participation; the media including the internet, blogs, social media, interactive media, books, magazines, newspapers, film, and television; informal talk among politically active or less active individuals whether powerful or marginalized; and forms of subjugated and local knowledge that rarely surface for access by others without some opening in the deliberative system” (Mansbridge et al. 2012, p. 10). |
16 | They cite Rawls’s “Justice as Fairness” (Rawls 1985), Thomas Nagel’s “Moral Conflict and Political Legitimacy” (Nagel 1987), and Richards’s Toleration and the Constitution (Richards 1986). This is not meant to be a comprehensive view of their mature thought. |
17 | They are clear that their interpretation of Locke contains some idiosyncrasies (Gutmann and Thompson 2004, p. 195n.3). My citation of their approach here is not to rehearse Locke so much as demonstrate their inadequate account of religious deliberation at this point. For an alternative recent secularist rehabilitation of Lockean toleration that aims to defend secular dominance, see also Blackford’s Freedom of Religion in the Secular State (Blackford 2012). |
18 | It should be noted in this context that Gutmann and Thompson are not pure proceduralists. As they put it, “the point to keep in mind is that the democratic element in deliberative democracy should turn not on how purely procedural the conception is but on how fully inclusive the process is” (Gutmann and Thompson 2004, p. 9). Stout also goes further in outlining an argument for a democratic tradition. His substantive commitments “are initially implicit in our reasoning, rather than fully explicitly in the form of philosophically articulated propositions… Because they evolve, we need the historical category of ‘tradition’ to bring them into focus” (Stout 2004, p. 5). |
19 | In this way, I aim to respond to John Dryzek’s question concerning the distinctive pragmatist contribution to democratic thought. As he puts it, “But given that deliberative theory and practice currently seem to develop without much help from pragmatism, what exactly can pragmatism now contribute that could not be found elsewhere?” (Dryzek 2004, p. 78). |
20 | In general, pragmatists are agreed on the need to avoid appeals to abstract principles. Similar criticisms of Habermas and Rawls can be found in Misak and Talisse’s work (Misak 2000, p. 41; cf. Talisse 2005, p. 106). As Misak puts it, she aims to take back “reasonableness from the Rawlsians” (Misak 2009, p. 38). Pragmatists are typically as concerned, as Rawls was to avoid the influence of zealotry, bigotry, and the blindness of “passion or ideology” (Misak 2009, p. 31). For similar reasons Misak also criticized Carl Schmitt’s view that “politics is a battleground between self-defined friends and enemies where the strongest will win” (Misak 2000, p. 10; 2009, p. 29–30). Rather, she aimed to show that “morals and politics fall under our cognitive scope” (Misak 2009, p. 30). |
21 | While I commend Knight and Johnson’s emphasis upon institutional supports, I question their skepticism of Dewey’s concern with matters of faith (Knight and Johnson 2011, p. ix). My contention in this essay is that there are not pragmatic grounds to force that choice. They can inform each other to build trust and enfranchise religious communities. |
22 | Critics, such as Robert Talisse, have suggested that Stout’s failure to overcome religious resentment is due to insufficient reasons to enter into deliberations (Talisse 2009, p. 75). As he puts it, “nothing is said about why citizens should bother having such conversations, rather than simply hiving off with like-minded fellows in order to strategize and plot” (Talisse 2009, p. 78). While Talisse is right in my view to say that Stout relies on the notion of a democratic tradition in which people are situated, he did not adequately engage with the institutional aspects of Stout’s project. He also did not adequately engage with Stout’s discussion of Brandom’s epistemic concerns. This oversight of Brandom’s contribution is also a feature of Knight and Johnson’s account (Knight and Johnson 2011, pp. 30–31). Despite this, in some respects, Talisse’s own “folk epistemology” (Talisse 2009, pp. 79–120) is remarkably similar insofar as it too considers norms of discourse as a “social process of reason exchange” grounded in “a basic conception of epistemic or discursive etiquette” (Talisse 2009, p. 106). |
23 | While not specifically addressed to the religious case, Dryzek’s concluding proposal is strikingly apropos to the proposal advocated for here. In sum, Dryzek focuses on the “institutional specifics” (Dryzek 2005, p. 223) and concludes with a variety of options conducive to systems analysis, such as “deliberative institutions at a distance from sovereign authority; deliberative forums in the public sphere that focus on particular needs rather than general values; issue-specific networks; centripetal electoral systems; a power-sharing state that does not reach too far into the public sphere; the conditionality of sovereignty; and the transnationalization of political influence” (Dryzek 2005, p. 239). |
24 | Stout has in mind Nicholas Wolterstorff’s essay, “The Role of Religion in Decision and Discussion of Political Issues” (Wolterstorff 1997, p. 114). |
© 2020 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Stanley, T. Religious Interactions in Deliberative Democratic Systems Theory. Religions 2020, 11, 210. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel11040210
Stanley T. Religious Interactions in Deliberative Democratic Systems Theory. Religions. 2020; 11(4):210. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel11040210
Chicago/Turabian StyleStanley, Timothy. 2020. "Religious Interactions in Deliberative Democratic Systems Theory" Religions 11, no. 4: 210. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel11040210
APA StyleStanley, T. (2020). Religious Interactions in Deliberative Democratic Systems Theory. Religions, 11(4), 210. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel11040210