The Idea of Religious Minorities and Social Cohesion in India’s Constitution: Reflections on the Indian Experience
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Constitution-Making, Congress Party and Religious Minorities
3. The Constitutionalization of the Idea of Minorities
4. Minority Rights, Secularism and Social Cohesion
5. Reflecting on the Indian Experience
6. Shah Bano and the Idea of Minorities
7. Analysing India’s Model of Social Cohesion
8. Conclusions
Funding
Conflicts of Interest
1 | For a detailed account on the Congress party’s role in Indian national movement: see, among others, Weiner (1967), Brass and Robinson (1987). |
2 | Triangulation, though principally used in quantitative research, is used here as a tool of visual projection. In its traditional research-based understanding, triangulation means ‘that several observations of a datum, a single piece of data, are better than one; the phrase [triangulation] implies that three are desirable … each observation is prone to error, taking the three together will provide a more accurate observation,’ in (Bechhofer and Paterson 2000, p. 57). Similarly, an analysis of the idea of religious minorities based on observation from one of any of the three mentioned points may fail to provide a comprehensive overview of the issue. |
3 | ‘At the time of Independence, the term “Backward Classes” had a less fixed and definite reference. The term had been around [before independence] for some time. But it had a variety of referents, it had shifted rapidly in meaning and had come to mean different things in different places [different government committees before independence mainly used the term to count aboriginal and hill Tribes, untouchables criminal tribes and marginalized inhabitants of British India] … Thus, the term had never acquired a definite meaning at the all-India level … [Later, in post-independence period]. Two major species of [backward classes] usage emerge[d]: (1) as the more inclusive group of all those who need special treatment (2) as a stratum higher than the untouchables but nonetheless depressed. This double usage continues today: the former in the usage of Backward Classes in the wide sense (including Scheduled Castes and Scheduled Tribes); the latter in the ‘usage as equivalent to “Other Backward Classes”,’ in (Galanter 1978). |
4 | Hillal Ahmed ‘underline[s] the ways in which Islamic principles are reshaped by postcolonial, secular Indian political processes, such as elections,’ in (Ahmed 2019, p. 10). |
5 | Lucknow pact is an agreement between the Congress party and Muslim which documented a possible framework on co-operation between the Hindu and Muslim community. The document identified prospective social cohesion model for cordial relationship between Hindus and Muslims. The document of the pact were developed jointly by Muslim League and Congress Party. However, in the post-independence period, various scholars have assessed its limitation and achievements and commented that: ‘The Pact usher[ed] in a period of Hindu-Muslim cooperation’ in (Owen 1972); … [the disagreement among Muslims on Lucknow made it] ‘clear that the political interests of Muslims were not alike’ in (Hasan 1979, p. 97); [merely a] ‘deal’ in (Robinson 1974, p. 256). |
6 | For a critical examination of Gandhi’s philosophy, see (Parekh 1989). |
7 | The efforts were moderately successful because as per the published Report of the Kanpur Riots Enquiry Committee in 1933, from 1920–1930 there were communal riots reported in ‘Malabar (1922), Multan (1922, 1927), Ajmere (1923), Saharanpur (1923), Amritsar (1923), Sindh (1923), Jubbulpur (1923), Agra (1923, 1931), Rae-Bareli (1923), Delhi (1924, 1926), Kohat (1924), Nagpur (1924, 1927), Indore (1924), Lucknow (1924), Calcutta (1925), Allahabad (1925), Sholapur (1925), Lahore (1927), Betiah (1927), Bareilly (1927), Kanpur (1927,1931), Surat (1928), Hyderabad (1928), Kalipaty (1928), Mumbai (1929), Azamgarh (1930), Dacca (1930), Muttra (1930), Mymemsing (1930), Daravi (1930), Basti (1931), Benares (1931), Mirzapur (1931)’, in Report of the Kanpur Riots Enquiry Committee (2007). |
8 | For a detailed analysis of partition, see (Hasan 1993). Aditionally, see (Ambedkar 1945; Seervai 1989; Nair 2011; Khan 2017). For a detailed analysis on communal violence in pre partitioned India, see (Pandey 2001). |
9 | Article 25 says that subject to public order, morality, etc., the practice of religion is free. But government may regulate the economic and other secular activities associated with religious practice … Sikhs (and Jains and Buddhist) are for the purposes of this article classed as Hindus’ in (Austin 2003, p. 547). |
10 | ‘Lord Pethick-Lawrence, Secretary of State for India, Sir Stafford Cripps, President of the Board of Trade and Mr A.V. Alexander, First Lord of the Admiralty, collectively known as the Cabinet Mission, or, in Wavell’s words, ‘the three magi’. They had come to India to try and forge a compromise, to create a constitutional package for one united India and to plan the British handover of power’ (Khan 2017, p. 55). |
11 | |
12 | The Constituent Assembly was elected by provincial legislatures, as the franchise was restricted by the tax, educational and property qualifications specified in the 1935 Government of India Act (Bajpai 2000, p. 1844). |
13 | The representation of different groups was based on their respective population and as per the Cabinet Mission, the Assembly reserved seats for Muslims and Sikh minorities. However, ‘it was largely through the support and intervention of the Congress leadership that Parsis, Anglo-Indians, Indian Christians, members of the scheduled castes and tribes and women were brought into the assembly. This fact would have some bearing on the positions that representatives of different minority groups would take during the debates, with those elected through Congress support generally taking a more conciliatory stand towards Congress proposals. The representation of the various minority communities in the assembly after partition was as follows: Nepalis 1, Sikhs 5, Parsis 3, Christians 7, Anglo-Indians 3, backward tribes 5, Muslims 31, scheduled castes 33—a total of 88 of the 235 provincial seats’ (Bajpai 2000, p. 1845). |
14 | Rajeev Bhargava as quoted in Dasgupta (2017). As per India’s right wing scholars Hindutva—the term—was coined in 1892 by scholar Chandranath Basu from eastern India (State of Bengal). Later in 1923, Savarkar used it and proposed the idea of religious nationalism based on three factors: geographical unity, racial features and a common culture: see (Savarkar 1989). Now, Hindutva is used by Bharatiya Janta Party (BJP) to consolidate identity of majoritarian Hindu community and it has turned out as a dominant ideology in Indian democracy specially due to immense electoral success of BJP. BJP in 2014 and 2019 general elections staunchly propagated the ideology of Hindutva and won absolute majority (282 seats in 2014 and 343 seats from a total 545 seats) in the national Parliament of India. Various scholars have explained Hindutva’s ontological importance in Indian democracy and evaluated its epistemological strength and weaknesses in shaping the national identity of India. For a critical reading of Hindutva: see (Jaffrelot 1996; Bhat 2001; Sharma 2011). For a caste based critique of Hindutva from oppressed castes points of view: see (Ilaiah 2002). In recent years, after 2014 there has been a surge in scholarly work encouraging an empathetic reading of Hindutva: see (Dasgupta 2019). |
15 | In India, ‘reservations’ refers to the provisions of positive discrimination where certain number of seats in education institutions, government jobs and electoral constituency at various levels of legislative bodies are reserved for historically marginalised communities such as Schedule Castes (SCs), Schedule Tribes (STs) and Other Backward Class (OBCs). Within aforesaid categories various castes and tribes are notified and enumerated by both state and central governments. For a detailed account of reservation system and debates around it in India: see (Galanter 1984). |
16 | By unhealthy cultural practices of religious communities, here I mean, following those customs that harm the dignity of an individual member of religious community, likewise, healthy cultural practices can be identified as those that enhance the quality of life of its members. The aforementioned classification is influenced by Bhikh Parkeh’s work on multiculturalism. Parekh argued that ‘A culture has two dimensions, a community whose culture it is and the content and character of that culture … The two forms of respect have differed bases. We should respect a community’s right to its culture for a variety of reasons, such as that human beings should be free to decide how to live, that their culture is bound up with their history and identity, that is means much to them, and so forth. Every community has as good a right to its culture as any other, and there is no basis for inequality … As for culture itself, our respect for it is based on our assessment of its content or the kind of life it make possible for its members. Since every culture gives stability and meaning to human life, holds it member together as a community, displays creative energy, and so on, it deserves respect. However, after a sensitive and sympathetic study of it from within, we might conclude that the overall quality of life it offers its members leaves much to be desired. We might then think that we are unable to accord it as much respect as another, which is better in these respects. Although all cultures have worth and deserve basic respect, they are not equally worthy and do not merit equal respect’ in (Parekh 2000, pp. 176–77). |
17 | Shri Vishwambhar Dayal Tripathi an elected member from United Province constituency, while speaking on the Supplementary Report of the Fundamental Rights Committee tabled by Sardar Vallabhbhai J. Patel, commented: ‘Cow protection is very important for an agricultural country. I am happy to know that a resolution to this effect is coming before you in a very nice form, and I hope that this Assembly will adopt it unanimously. This matter too was hotly discussed. No only from financial point of view but from cultural point of view also, I think it is necessary to make adequate arrangements for cow-protection … and I am happy that a resolution to that effect is coming before you’, in (Constituent Assembly of India 1947b). |
18 | Article 48 of the Indian Constitution states: ‘The State shall endeavour to organise agriculture and animal husbandry on modern and scientific lines and shall, in particular, take steps for preserving and improving the breeds, and prohibiting the slaughter, of cows and calves and other milch and draught cattle’. |
19 | Fundamental Rights are enforceable by the judiciary. Article 32 of the Indian Constitution states: ‘Remedies for enforcement of rights conferred by this Part. (1) The right to move the Supreme Court by appropriate proceedings for the enforcement of the rights conferred by this Part is guaranteed. (2) The Supreme Court shall have power to issue directions or orders or writs … for the enforcement of any of the rights conferred by this Part’. |
20 | There are many reports that link Nehru’s understanding of secularism with Holyoake: ‘Among the many who were inspired by his writings were Jawaharlal Nehru, who championed the idea of secularism and wanted his party, the Indian National Congress, to take its ethos and practice forward’ in (Jinoy 2018). |
21 | The Supreme Court of India in a number of judgements devised new meanings and definitions in its rulings in 1995. For example, the categorization of ‘essential’ and ‘non-essential’ was propagated in Ismail Faruqui v. Union of India, AIR 1995 SC 605 A. In another judgment on the question of religious appeal and uses of term ‘Hindutva’ in election campaign to be considered as corrupt electoral practices, SC in its judgment ‘indicated that the term ‘Hindutva’ is related more to the way of life of the people in the sub-continent’ in Dr. Ramesh Yeshwant Prabhoo v. Shri Prabhakar Kashinath Kunte, AIR 1996 SC 1113. |
22 | Mohd. Ahmed Khan v Shah Bano Begum, AIR 1985 SC 945. |
23 | Iddat is maintenance that is payable after divorce and is intended to provide for the divorced wife during her pregnancy if she is pregnant, or for a period of three months to exclude the possibility of pregnancy. |
24 | In Muslim law, mahr is regarded as consideration for the marriage and is in theory payable by the husband to the wife before consummation. Muslim law allows it to be divided into two parts. One of these is ‘prompt’ and is payable before the wife can be called upon to enter the conjugal domicile. The other is ‘deferred’, which is payable on the dissolution of the contract of marriage by either of the parties or by divorce. |
25 | Section 125 of CrPC states that, ‘if any person having sufficient means neglects or refuses to maintain … his wife, unable to maintain herself … a Magistrate of the first class may, upon proof of such neglect or refusal, order such person to make a monthly allowance for the maintenance of his wife … at such monthly rate not exceeding five hundred rupees in the whole, as such Magistrate thinks fit, and to pay the same to such person as the Magistrate may from time to time direct’. |
26 | Flavia Agnes argues that ‘the Muslim Women (Protection of Rights on Divorce) Act of 1986, was enacted amid protests from women’s rights groups and progressive social organizations. However, as the act gradually unfolded itself in the lower courts, it was invoked to secure the rights of divorced Muslim women. The writ petitions challenging the constitutionality of the act and the appeals filed by husbands (Daniel Latifi among them) were decided together and a verdict was pronounced by a five-judge constitutional bench of the Supreme Court on 28 September 2001, which declared that the act is constitutional. Declaring that the act would be unconstitutional if not interpreted to mean that women would get a reasonable and fair provision and maintenance, the court simultaneously provided greater protection to Muslim women than the earlier right under Section 125 of the Criminal Procedure’ in (Agnes 2007, p. 315). |
27 | The distinctiveness of Indian model of social cohesion can be explained by referring to the arguments of Aushtosh Varshney. Among others, Varshney argued that ‘India’s repeated encounters with ethnic violence of all kinds (religious, linguistic, caste) and its equally frequent returns from the brink have a great deal to do with the self-regulation that its largely integrated and cross-cutting civil society provides. Local structures of resistance and recuperation, as well as local knowledge about how to fix ethnic relations, have ensured that even the worst moments—1947–48 and 1992–93—do not degenerate into an all-out collapse of the country into ethnic warfare. A Rwanda, a Burundi, a Yugoslavia are not possible in India unless the state, for an exogenous reason such as a protracted war, kills all autonomous spaces of citizen activity and organization’ in (Varshney 2003, p. 286). For a more nuanced analysis on functioning of civil society in India’s communal violence context: see (Varshney 2014). Aditionally, see (Gottschalk 2000). |
28 | In September 2018, the Supreme Court’s constitutional bench ruled that the customary prohibition of young women between the ages of ten to fifty years (predominantly menstrual age) in Sabarimala as ‘unconstitutional being violative of Article 25(1) and Article 15(1) of the Constitution of India’ in Indian Young Lawyers Association v State of Kerala Writ Petition (Civil) No. 373 of 2006 (2018). However, in November 2019, the Supreme Court in its judgment on review petition filed against 2018 judgment lifting the prohibition has referred the matter to a larger constitutional bench under its review jurisdiction authority to review the 2018 judgment. For more recent development: see (Express News Service 2020). For a detailed analysis of the 2018 judgment: see (Das Acevedo 2018). |
References
- Agnes, Flavia. 2007. The Supreme Court, the Media, and the Uniform Civil Code Debate in India. In The Crisis of Secularism in India. Edited by Anuradha Dingwaney Needham and Rajeswari Sunder Rajan. Durham: Duke University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ahmed, Hilal. 2019. Siyasi Muslims: A Story of Political Islams in India. New Dehli: Penguin Random House. [Google Scholar]
- All Parties Conference (India) and Nehru Committee. 1975. Nehru Report: An Anti-Separatist Manifesto, The Committee Appointed by the All Parties’ Conference, 1928. New Delhi: Michiko and Panjathan. [Google Scholar]
- Ambedkar, Bhimrao Ramji. 1945. Pakistan or Partition of India. Bombay: Thacker and Co. [Google Scholar]
- Austin, Granville. 1966. The Indian Constitution: Cornerstone of a Nation. London: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Austin, Granville. 2001. Religion, Personal Law, and Identity in India. In Religion and Personal Law in Secular India: A Call to Judgment. Edited by Gerald James Larson. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Austin, Granville. 2003. Working a Democratic Constitution: A History of the Indian Experience. New Delhi: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Bajpai, Rochana. 2000. Constituent Assembly Debates and Minority Rights. Economic and Political Weekly 35: 1837–45. [Google Scholar]
- Bajpai, Rochna. 2008. Minority Representation and the Making of the Indian Constitution. In Politics and Ethics of the Indian Constitution. Edited by Rajeev Bhargava. New Delhi: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Bechhofer, Frank, and Lindsay Paterson. 2000. Principles of Research Design in the Social Sciences. Hove: Psychology Press. [Google Scholar]
- Bhat, Chetan. 2001. Hindu Nationalism: Origins, Ideologies and Modern Myths. Oxford: Berg. [Google Scholar]
- Brass, Paul R., and Francis Robinson, eds. 1987. The Indian National Congress and Indian Society, 1885–1985: Ideology, Social Structure, and Political Dominance. New Delhi: Chanakya Press. [Google Scholar]
- Chandhoke, Neera. 2019. Rethinking Pluralism, Secularism and Tolerance: Anxieties of Coexistence. New Delhi: Sage Publications. [Google Scholar]
- Constituent Assembly of India. 1947a. Constituent Assembly of India Debates (Proceedings)—Volume 2. Available online: http://loksabhaph.nic.in/writereaddata/cadebatefiles/C24011947.html (accessed on 27 February 2021).
- Constituent Assembly of India. 1947b. Constituent Assembly of India Debates (Proceedings)—Volume 5. Available online: http://164.100.47.194/Loksabha/Debates/cadebatefiles/C30081947.html (accessed on 27 February 2021).
- Constituent Assembly of India. 1948a. Constituent Assembly Debates (Proceedings)—Volume, 7, Article 35. Available online: http://164.100.47.194/Loksabha/Debates/Result_Nw_15.aspx?dbsl=182 (accessed on 27 February 2021).
- Constituent Assembly of India. 1948b. Constituent Assembly Debates (Proceedings)—Volume 7. Available online: http://loksabhaph.nic.in/Writereaddata/Cadebatefiles/C02121948.Html (accessed on 27 February 2021).
- Constituent Assembly of India. 1949. Constituent Assembly Debates: Official Report. Lok Sabha, Secretariat, vol. 11. Available online: http://164.100.47.194/Loksabha/Debates/cadebatefiles/C12081949.html (accessed on 27 February 2021).
- Das Acevedo, Deepa. 2018. Pause for Thought: Supreme Court’s Verdict on Sabarimala. Economic & Political Weekly 43: 12–15. [Google Scholar]
- Dasgupta, Swapan. 2017. Challenging the Nehruvian Consensus: INDIA AT 70 a Symposium on India after 70 Years of Independence, Seminar, 696. Available online: https://www.india-seminar.com/2017/696/696_swapan_dasgupta.htm (accessed on 27 February 2021).
- Dasgupta, Swapan. 2019. Awakening Bharat Mata: The Political Beliefs of the Indian Right. Gurgaon: Penguin. [Google Scholar]
- De, Rohit. 2018. A People’s Constitution: The Everyday Life of Law in the Indian Republic. New Delhi and Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Express News Service. 2020. SC Clarifies on Sabarimala Review Pleas: Can Refer to Larger Bench. The Indian Express. May 12. Available online: https://indianexpress.com/article/india/sc-clarifies-on-sabarimala-review-pleas-can-refer-to-larger-bench-6405622/ (accessed on 27 February 2021).
- Galanter, Marc. 1978. Who Are the Other Backward Classes? An Introduction to a Constitutional Puzzle. Economic and Political Weekly 13: 1812–28. [Google Scholar]
- Galanter, Marc. 1984. Competing Equalities: Law and the Backward Classes in India. New Delhi: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Gopal, Sarvapelli. 1988. Nehru and Minorities. Economic and Political Weekly 23: 2463–66. [Google Scholar]
- Gottschalk, Peter. 2000. Beyond Hindu and Muslim: Multiple Identity in Narratives from Village India. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hasan, Mushirul. 1979. Nationalism and Communal Politics in India, 1916–1928. New Delhi: Manohar Publications. [Google Scholar]
- Hasan, Mushirul. 1993. India’s partition: Process, Strategy and Mobilisation. New Delhi: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- High Court of Australia. 1943. Adelaide Co. of Jehovah’s Witnesses Inc. v. Commonwealth. [1943. 67 C.L.R.]. Available online: http://www.austlii.edu.au/au/cases/cth/HCA/1943/12.pdf (accessed on 6 March 2021).
- Hoeber Rudolph, Susanne, and Lloyd I. Rudolph. 2001. Living with Difference in India: Legal Pluralism and Legal Universalism in Historical C ontext. In Religion and Personal Law in Secular India: A Call to Judgment. Edited by Gerald James Larson. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ilaiah, Kancha. 2002. Why I Am Not a Hindu: A Sudra Critique of Hindutva Philosophy, Culture and Political Economy. Calcutta: Samya. [Google Scholar]
- Jaffrelot, Christophe. 1996. The Hindu Nationalist Movement and Indian Politics 1925 to the 1990s: Strategies of Identity-Building, Implantation and Mobilisation. Delhi: Viking/Penguin. [Google Scholar]
- Jalal, Ayesha. 1985. The Sole Spokesman: Jinnah, the Muslim League and the Demand for Pakistan. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Jinoy, Jose P. 2018. Nehru and Sabarimala. The Hind Business Line. November 20. Available online: https://www.thehindubusinessline.com/opinion/columns/from-the-viewsroom/nehru-and-sabarimala/article25549982.ece (accessed on 27 February 2021).
- Kanpur Riots Enquiry Committee. 2007. The Communal Problem. Delhi: National Book Trust. [Google Scholar]
- Kapoor, Ratna. 2019. ‘Belief ’ in the Rule of Law and the Hindu Nation and the Rule of Law. In Majoritarian State: How Hindu Nationalism is Changing India. Edited by Angana P. Chatterji, Thomas Blom Hansen and Christophe Jaffrelot. NewYork: Oxford University Press, pp. 353–72. [Google Scholar]
- Khan, Yasmin. 2017. The Great Partition: The Making of India and Pakistan. London: Yale University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Larson, Gerald James. 2001. Introduction: The Secular State in a Religious Society. In Religion and Personal Law in Secular India: A Call to Judgment. Edited by Gerald James Larson. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Mahajan, Gurpreet. 2008. Religion and the Indian Constitution: Questions of Separation and Equality. In Politics and Ethics of the Indian Constitution. Edited by Rajeev Bhargava. New Delhi: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Mehta, Pratap Bhanu. 2008. Passion and Constraint: Courts and the Regulation of Religious Meaning. In Politics and Ethics of the Indian Constitution. Edited by Rajeev Bhargava. New Delhi: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Nair, Neeti. 2011. Changing Homelands: Hindu Politics and the Partition of India. Ranikhet: Permanent Black. [Google Scholar]
- Owen, Hugh F. 1972. Negotiating the Lucknow Pact. The Journal of Asian Studies 31: 578. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pal, Ruma. 2001. Religious Minorities and the Law. In Religion and Personal Law in Secular India: A Call to Judgment. Edited by Gerald James Larson. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Palshikar, Suhas. 2008. The Indian State: Constitution and Beyond. In Politics and Ethics of the Indian Constitution. Edited by Rajeev Bhargava. New Delhi: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Pandey, Gyanendra. 2001. Remembering partition: Violence, nationalism and history in India. In Contemporary South Asia. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Parekh, Bhikhu. 1989. Gandhi’s Political Philosophy: A Critical Examination. London: Palgrave Macmillan. [Google Scholar]
- Parekh, Bhikhu. 2000. Rethinking Multiculturalism: Cultural Diversity and Political Theory. London: Palgrave, pp. 176–77. [Google Scholar]
- Parekh, Bhikhu. 2006. Defining India’s Identity. India International Centre Quarterly 33: 1–15. [Google Scholar]
- Robinson, Francis. 1974. Separatism Among Indian Muslims: The Politics of the United Provinces’ Muslims, 1860–1923. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Savarkar, Vinayak Damodar. 1989. Hindutva: Who Is a Hindu. Delhi: Bharatiya Sadan. [Google Scholar]
- Seervai, Hormasji Manekji. 1989. Partition of India: Legend and Reality. Bombay: Emmenem Publications. [Google Scholar]
- Sharma, Jyotirmaya. 2011. Hindutva: Exploring the Idea of Hindu Nationalism. New Delhi: Penguin Books India. [Google Scholar]
- Varshney, Ashutosh. 2003. Ethnic Conflict and Civic Life: Hindus and Muslims in India. Yale: Yale University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Varshney, Ashutosh. 2013. How has Indian Federalism done? Studies in Indian Politics 1: 43–63. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Varshney, Ashutosh. 2014. Battles Half Won: India’s Improbable Democracy. Haryana: Penguin Books. [Google Scholar]
- Weiner, Myron. 1967. Party Building in a New Nation: The Indian National Congress. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. [Google Scholar]
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2021 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Choudhary, V.K. The Idea of Religious Minorities and Social Cohesion in India’s Constitution: Reflections on the Indian Experience. Religions 2021, 12, 910. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel12110910
Choudhary VK. The Idea of Religious Minorities and Social Cohesion in India’s Constitution: Reflections on the Indian Experience. Religions. 2021; 12(11):910. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel12110910
Chicago/Turabian StyleChoudhary, Vikas K. 2021. "The Idea of Religious Minorities and Social Cohesion in India’s Constitution: Reflections on the Indian Experience" Religions 12, no. 11: 910. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel12110910
APA StyleChoudhary, V. K. (2021). The Idea of Religious Minorities and Social Cohesion in India’s Constitution: Reflections on the Indian Experience. Religions, 12(11), 910. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel12110910