1. Introduction
Lawrence Sullivan (
Sullivan 2000, p. xiii) has observed that religious traditions and their lived manifestations offer “a treasury of motives, disciplines, and awarenesses” that can facilitate earth-friendly living and it is certainly in this spirit that scholars of religion and environmental studies alike have turned to Hindu texts and traditions. The term ‘Hindu’ does not, of course, denote an easily defined, homogeneous, monolithic tradition. What generally goes by the name of Hinduism represents more a “galaxy of worldviews emerging over centuries in India” (
Valpey 2020, p. 1). It is not part of my task in this article to defend or explain the use of the term ‘Hindu’ or ‘Hinduism,’ but along with Julius Lipner, I propose that “‘Hinduism’ is an acceptable abbreviation for a
family of culturally related traditions” (
Lipner 2010, p. 33). Despite the obvious heterogeneity of the Hindu cosmos, it is not too much of a stretch to claim that the
Bhagavad Gītā has singularly informed Hindu self-representations since the turn of the nineteenth century. Gavin
Flood (
1996) notes that the immense popularity the
Bhagavad Gītā now enjoys in India only occurred after the emergence of Hindu revival movements of the nineteenth century. The text had, of course, already gained prominence prior to this, as evidenced by commentaries upon it by famous Hindu theologians such as Śaṅkara, Rāmānuja and Madhva in the
Vedānta tradition and Abhinavagupta in the Śaiva tradition. (Throughout this article, I have, for the most part, shortened the title
Bhagavad Gītā to “the
Gītā.” When specific verses are referenced, the chapter number appears first, followed by the verse number.) Richard Davis notes that the
Gītā “is a vital text for modern Hindus of many persuasions” and outside the Indian subcontinent, the text “is frequently taken as the first and most representative work for those first seeking to understand Hinduism” (
Davis 2015, p. 23). Davis goes on to write: “It appears regularly as a primary reading in hundreds of college courses on Hinduism and Asian religions throughout North America and elsewhere” (
Davis 2015, p. 24). The
Bhagavad Gītā, along with the
Upaniṣads and the
Brahmasūtra, also forms the triple foundations of
Vedānta, the “most influential school of theology in India” (
Flood 1996, p. 238). Graham Schweig highlights the
Gītā’s theological impact when he writes that the
Gītā “is, since the seventh century, the most widely read and commented on holy text in all of India” (
Schweig 2007, p. 13), and Klaus Klostermaier similarly underlines the text’s influence by claiming that the seven hundred verses of the
Bhagavad Gītā constitute the “most popular book of the entire Hindu literature” (
Klostermaier 1994, p. 145).
Given the
Bhagavad Gītā’s significance within the Hindu cosmos, it is noteworthy that Lance Nelson has argued that the ontological vision and soteriological goal promoted by the
Gītā is fundamentally hostile to environmental ethics. In his ecological critique of the
Bhagavad-Gītā, Nelson writes that the
Gītā’s “hierarchical, fundamentally dualistic outlook” which elevates “pure spirit above matter” implies that nature is “finally irrelevant to the
Gītā’s soteriological goals.” From this, Nelson concludes that the
Gītā’s “ideals are in many ways antithetical to ecological ethics as we know it” (
Nelson 2000, pp. 140, 151). My reading of Nelson’s critique is that he is arguing that the task of constructing a normative environmental ethical theory from the metaphysical infrastructure provided by the
Gītā is an incoherent project. That is, the genesis of environmental ethics from the
Gītā’s metaphysical commitments is philosophically problematic. Nelson’s critique is part of a scholarly trend claiming that since Hindu soteriology is primarily focused on liberation from
saṃsāra, the cycle of birth and death, it is inherently world-negating and is thus incapable of fostering “a deep sense of belonging to the universe,” the kind of belonging that is deemed to be a necessary psychological condition for environmental engagement and action (
Nelson 2000, p. 151). John Passmore (
Passmore 1980) has thus argued that the doctrine of stewardship—which entails a regard for nature—is incompatible with the Eastern religious quest for salvation achieved by freeing oneself from every kind of earthly bondage. J. Baird Callicott (
Callicott 1994) has similarly opined that because the
Upaniṣads proclaim the undifferentiated and unmanifest
Brahman to be the source and ground of all manifest and differentiated things, the Hindu religious tradition regards the empirical world of manifest and differentiated things as something less than morally significant, because it is not ultimately real. Lance Nelson (
Nelson 1998) has also argued that the classical
Advaita Vedānta of
Śaṅkara—which he deems to be the central viewpoint of the modern Hindu renaissance—encourages attitudes of devaluation and neglect of the natural universe. Against this interpretation of ‘Hinduism’ as a world-negating religion incapable of inspiring environmentalism, David Haberman (
Haberman 2006) has argued that most Hindus identify themselves with theistic, Purāṇic, and world-affirming traditions that include immanent strands within their theologies and has buttressed his argument with many examples of Indian environmentalists who draw their inspiration from such traditions.
However, what, then, of the
Bhagavad Gītā? Is the text world-affirming or world-negating? More to the point, if the text is fundamentally unsuited to a favourable ecological reading, then the oft-repeated claim that the
Gītā transmits “an eternal teaching that has universal relevance” becomes severely impoverished (
Davis 2015, p. 18). Against this conclusion, I argue that the
Gītā lends itself to a favourable ecological reading on many levels. To demonstrate how so, I will build upon Ithamar Theodor’s articulation of the unifying structure of the
Gītā and its attendant moral psychology. This will allow me to show that the
Gītā contains three concurrent worldviews—a world-affirming worldview, a world-renouncing worldview and a
bhakti worldview, which is simultaneously world-affirming and world-renouncing. More specifically, I will argue that these three worldviews correspond to three different theories of motivation and that the motivation to act for the welfare of individuals in nature, such as animals and plants, can be coherently derived from the interconnected normative, soteriological and ontological dimensions of each of these three worldviews. In making this argument, I will begin by looking at the context of the
Gītā.
2. The Context of the Bhagavad Gītā
The eighteen chapters of the Bhagavad Gītā appear as chapters twenty three through forty in the Book of Bhīshma, the sixth of the eighteen books that comprise the great epic poem Mahābhārata. The text is set on a battlefield with the sons of the congenitally blind king Dhṛtarāṣṭra leading his army into battle against the sons of his deceased younger brother, Pāṇḍu, who inherited the throne due to his older brother’s blindness. When the noble and righteous Pāṇḍu passed away, his five sons, the Pāṇḍavas, were too young to inherit the throne. Their uncle Dhṛtarāṣṭra took over the kingdom and ruled for many years during which time his eldest son, Duryodhana, driven by greed and animosity, conspired to murder the Pāṇḍavas. In the events leading up to the war, Dhṛtarāṣṭra and his sons, the Kurus, led by the eldest son, Duryodhana, have steadfastly denied Yudhiṣṭhira, the eldest of the Pāndavas, his kingdom, have humiliated the Pāṇḍavas’ wife Draupadī, and have repeatedly harassed the Pāṇḍavas in many other ways. War seems imminent because Draupadī wants revenge, and Yudhiṣṭhira wants his kingdom. Dhṛtarāṣṭra is nominally still the king, and therefore with great reluctance, the Pāṇḍavas’ great-uncle and their beloved teachers have bound themselves in duty to the king to fight against the Pāṇḍavas.
Looking across the battlefield, the mightiest warrior of his time, Prince Arjuna, one of the five Pāṇḍava brothers, sees his teachers and uncles, as well as his hostile cousins and their followers. Faced with the prospect of a fratricidal war in which he will have to fight an army composed of many of his esteemed teachers, friends, and the Kuru warriors with whom he shares family bonds, Arjuna is perplexed about his kṣatriya-dharma, his duty as a warrior, and is overcome by debilitating despair. Even though Arjuna recognizes that the Kurus, led by Duryodhana, had cruelly and unjustly usurped the Pandavas’ kingdom, at 1.28–30, Arjuna claims compassion for his kinsmen and refuses to fight for justice. After trying to defend his position with a medley of socio-moral arguments, Arjuna collapses in anxiety and thus ends the Gītā’s first chapter. In the second chapter, at 2.6–7, Arjuna continues to voice his indecision about whether he should dutifully fight or whether he should refrain from fighting but then confesses that he is paralyzed due to miserly weakness and cannot ascertain his dharma—his duty, and consequently, he is unable to act. Following this confession, Arjuna surrenders to his dear cousin, charioteer and friend Kṛṣṇa as his disciple and asks Kṛṣṇa to enlighten him and resolve his inner conflict and dissipate his grief.
Even though the
Gītā proceeds as a conversation between Kṛṣṇa and Arjuna, it really is Kṛṣṇa’s response to Arjuna’s deep despondence and through Arjuna’s despondency the text grapples with a perennially relevant question: How ought we to act in this world, beset at it is with conflict and suffering? More precisely, the
Gītā asks this question through the existential and ethical dilemma faced by the warrior Arjuna.
Kṣatriya dharma dictates Arjuna should uphold
loka-saṅgraha—the
dharmic order that sustains the world. That is, Arjuna is duty bound to uphold justice and protect the virtuous, but how can Arjuna fight an enemy army composed of loved ones and gurus? In responding to Arjuna’s dilemma, Kṛṣṇa begins his teachings in the second chapter of the
Gītā and over the course of the rest of the text, Kṛṣṇa offers a
variety of reasons to persuade Arjuna to fight. The compendium of reasons Kṛṣṇa gives Arjuna to motivate him to fight constitutes the narrative arc of the
Gītā. To draw out the internal consistency and coherence of this compendium of reasons, I turn to Ithamar Theodor’s articulation of the underlying unifying structure of the
Gītā through “the metaphor of a three-storey house” (
Theodor 2016, p. 5).
3. The Three-Tiered House of the Bhagavad Gītā
Edwin Bryant has termed the
Bhagavad Gītā “a Vedānto-Sāṃkhyan text” in that it expresses the “theism of the older Sāṃkhyan traditions” (
Bryant 2014, p. 33).
Sāṃkhya is often labelled as a monolithic non-theistic tradition, but in fact, most strains of
Sāṃkhya were theistic, as evidenced in the
Mahābhārata and highlighted by Edwin Bryant (
Bryant 2009). The
Gītā explicitly accepts
Sāṃkhya (5.4–5, 13.24), and claims to be transmitting
Sāṃkhya (2.39, 18.13) and also of Kṛṣṇa originally teaching
Sāṃkhya himself (3.3). Not surprisingly,
Sāṃkhya language and taxonomy undergird the narrative of the
Gītā. The
Gītā’s theistic
Sāṃkhya speaks of three irreducible ontological categories:
prakṛti—the primordial matrix of matter,
puruṣas—eternal self-conscious subjects and
puruṣaḥ paraḥ—the Supreme Person, the autonomous independent entity who sustains and is the ultimate cause of both
prakṛti and innumerable selves (
puruṣas). This ontology is expressed at 7.4–7. There have been, of course, a variety of
Vedāntic approaches to the
Gītā’s ontology, but here I am informed by the twelfth century Vaiṣṇava theologian Rāmānuja’s reading of the
Gītā. The text identifies Kṛṣṇa as the Supreme Person, or the supreme deity (7.7, 10.2–3, 10.8, 11.37–46, 15.18–19) and as such, is an exemplar of Indic theistic, or more accurately, panentheistic thought (I will highlight the panentheism embedded in the text further on in the article). Like other
Vedāntic texts, the
Gītā advances the view that reality is hierarchical. That is, there is a higher, absolute reality, and a lower, relative reality. The lower-level reality corresponds to the world of
prakṛti, it corresponds to the empirical and conventional, the changing and the finite. The lower-level reality, which includes the human or worldly realm, also pertains to
dharma, the world of duty, morality and justice. The higher-level reality corresponds to the permanent, absolute, infinite, trans-
prakṛtic realm, it corresponds to the liberated state of
mokṣa.
Through Arjuna’s ethical dilemma, the Bhagavad-Gītā is navigating the deep tension between the dharmic ideal (whose origins can be traced back to the ancient Pūrva Mīmāṁsā school) of pursuing a moral and prosperous life within the world of prakṛti and the Upaniṣadic ideal of completely relinquishing the world of prakṛti, characterized as it is by saṁsāra, the cycle of birth and death, in order to attain the imperishable and eternal state of liberation or mokṣa. The tension between dharma and mokṣa also epitomizes the tension between action and knowledge. The dharma tradition is imbued with a performative flavour and seeks to act in this world and organize it according to principles derived from a purported eternal moral order whereas the Upaniṣadic tradition favours renunciation of action and worldly involvement in order to ‘know’ Brahman (ultimate reality). This tension is exemplified twice in the Gītā, at 3.1–3 and 5.1–2, when Arjuna expresses his confusion whether one should choose the path of action, or alternatively, the path of relinquishing action.
The
Gītā unequivocally prescribes the path of action. Each time Arjuna expresses his confusion over whether he should act or cease acting altogether, the text has Kṛṣṇa tell Arjuna at 3.8, to “perform your
dharmic duty, as action is superior to inaction” and similarly, at 5.2, that “
karma yoga or
yogic action exceeds renouncing action altogether.” (I have used Ithamar Theodor’s translations of
Gītā verses for this article (
Theodor 2016)). Thus, Kṛṣṇa encourages Arjuna throughout the entire
Gītā to follow his
dharma and fight. Yet, the
Gītā also teaches that
through action, one may progress to the state of liberation or
mokṣa. What is the rationale underpinning the
Gītā’s view? Ithamar Theodor (
Theodor 2016, p. 5) has argued that the coherence of the
Bhagavad Gītā as a theological-philosophical text is made apparent when we grasp the
Gītā’s unifying theme or structure. To access the
Gītā’s unifying structure, Theodor offers the metaphor of a three-storey house:
This house not only has three floors, storeys, or tiers, but has a staircase or ladder, leading the residents from the first floor to the second, and from the second to the third. The lower floor represents human life in this world, the second floor is an intermediate floor, whereby one relinquishes worldly life and seeks the state of liberation, and the third floor represents full absorption in the liberated state. The stages of the staircase or the ladder are comprised of various states of action categorized according to their underlying motivation; at the lower stage one’s acts are motivated by some utilitarian principle or gain; a stage still higher is when one seeks gain beyond this life in the heavenly world, and a higher stage is the stage of relinquishment of action’s fruits, thus acting for the sake of duty or dharma alone. A state still higher is the performance of one’s dharmic duty as a practice of yoga, i.e., considering the performance of duty to be the means by which the mind may be subdued. The highest state is the state of performing one’s dharmic duty while being liberated and entirely immersed in the supreme. In this way, the Bhagavad Gītā adheres to both ideals; it supports social responsibility, morality and dharma, and at the same time, it endorses the Upaniṣadic path of self-realization, which leads one from the depth of material existence all the way up to liberation”.
This conceptualization of the
Gītā’s internal schema implies that we progress from the unenlightened state to the highest liberated state by elevating our motives or reasons for performing action, and not by renouncing action. Thus, even though Arjuna is encouraged all along by Kṛṣṇa to follow his
dharma and fight, the text has Kṛṣṇa exhorting Arjuna to progressively refine his motives for fighting. That is, the variety of reasons Krishna gives to Arjuna form an “ethical ladder of motives” for fighting (
Theodor 2016, p. 24). This ladder of motives corresponds to three different tiers or levels of the text, such that as we ascend the
Gītā’s ladder of motives, we are simultaneously moving from a lower tier of the text to a higher one.
The pertinent question: How do we distinguish between the
Gītā’s three tiers? Theodor contends that to differentiate between the
Gītā’s three tiers, we need to examine their underlying assumptions in terms of being and values (
Theodor 2016, p. 19). Before we can clarify these underlying assumptions, a closer look at the
Gītā’s core ontological presupposition is in order. The
Gītā pivots around the idea that a human being (and all living organisms, for that matter) is a composite of three parts: a physical body, a subtle mental body and an irreducible, beginningless, self-aware subject or
puruṣa. The ‘subject’ part of ‘self-aware subject’ denotes an entity capable of conscious experiences. The ‘self-aware’ part of ‘self-aware subject’ denotes an entity that is aware of oneself. By the term self-aware subject, then, I mean an entity that is aware of themselves
as themselves; it is manifest to a self-aware subject that they themselves are the object of awareness. This implies that a self-aware subject, while perceiving any other thing, also perceives their own existence, implying that awareness entails self-awareness. On this view, both the physical body and the mental functions of the subtle body belong to the inert and unconscious category of
prakṛti but the
puruṣa is ontologically distinct from
prakṛti in that the
puruṣa being a non-material entity inherently consists of pure subjectivity or self-luminous conscious awareness. (In this article, I will use ‘awareness’ to denote the inherent subjectivity of the
puruṣa). In keeping with the characteristically
Vedāntic project of distinguishing the real self from the not-self, the
Gītā (2.13, 2.20 and 13.6–7) consistently demarcates the physical and subtle mental body from the
puruṣa, claiming that only the
puruṣa—the diachronically unchanging eternal self-conscious subject that observes the constantly changing mind-body complex—is the real self, whereas the subtle and physical body belong to the category of not-self.
What does it mean, then, to say that the
Gītā speaks of three different levels of being? For
Vedāntic theologians, phenomenological subjectivity, i.e., the first-person experience of being, is an act where the
puruṣa identifies with something. Theodor (
Theodor 2016) consequently writes that someone on the
Gītā’s first-tier identifies with one’s
prakṛtic embodiment or one’s mind/body complex. Someone on this tier views oneself as a human being and other living beings similarly, that is, as humans, animals or plants, and values a just and moral society and the pursuit of worldly happiness and prosperity. The Gita’s third or highest tier represents the liberated state of
mokṣa itself. Immersed in the liberated state one identifies as transcendent self-luminous awareness (an impersonal account of the liberated state) or as an eternal servant or lover of the Supreme Person (a theistic account of the liberated state). Someone on this level values the experience of
brahmananda (the bliss of
Brahman) or in case of the theist perspective, the experience of being constantly absorbed in the worship and glorification of the Supreme Person. The
Gītā’s second storey or the intermediate level may be termed the
yogic level as it connects the first-storey or the level of
dharma with the third-storey or the state of
mokṣa. The
yogic level is characterized by the endeavour to escape
saṁsāra while simultaneously trying to yoke oneself to the state of
mokṣa. Someone on this level identifies all living beings as units of self-luminous awareness transcendent to the mind-body complex, and values indifference to the happiness and distress produced by the three
guṇas comprising
prakṛti along with the endeavor to yoke oneself to
Brahman or the eternal state of
mokṣa.
Theodor’s conceptualization of the three-tiered house of the Gītā is based on mapping the possible relationships that may exist between the puruṣa and mokṣa; on the first tier are those puruṣas who are not seeking mokṣa, on the second tier are those puruṣas who are actively seeking mokṣa and on the third tier are those puruṣas who have already attained the state of mokṣa. Instead of articulating the Gītā’s moral psychology by mapping the possible relationships between the puruṣa and mokṣa, I will approach the Gītā’s moral psychology by mapping the possible ways the puruṣa may relate to prakṛti. To do this, I draw on the Gītā’s depiction of the puruṣa’s intrinsic nature as an eternal self-conscious subject, which stipulates that the puruṣa can never be not conscious or not aware and so, if the puruṣa’s inherent constitution requires that it be always aware of something, what is it that awareness ends up being aware of? I contend the Gītā text answers this question by claiming that the puruṣa has three basic choices: to be absorbed in prakṛti—the world of matter, to be absorbed in its own nature as self-luminous awareness, or to be absorbed in devotion to and loving service of Īśvara, the source of both prakṛti and selves (puruṣas). Within the Gītā’s theological structure, these three choices that can be made by the puruṣa result in three different theories of motivation which add up to three different predispositions toward the world of prakṛti—a world-affirming approach, a world-renouncing approach and a bhakti approach, which is simultaneously world-affirming and world-renouncing.
In sum, the Gītā depicts the puruṣa relating to prakṛti in three possible ways and mapping this allows me to draw out the Gītā’s environmental ethics. That is, I will argue that the motivation to act for the welfare of animals and plants can be legitimately derived from the Gītā’s three theories of motivation and their corresponding predispositions toward the world of prakṛti. Moreover, I will contextualize the Gītā’s environmental ethics by placing it within the framework of the Gītā’s overarching ethical theory. I interpret the Gītā as advancing a mokṣa-based teleological ethical theory that evaluates choices and actions in terms of whether they contribute to and ultimately achieve the overarching ultimate telos of mokṣa. However, I will show in the following sections that the Gītā’s ethical theory is also multi-layered, meaning that the foundational mokṣa-based teleological ethical theory grounds and explains more superficial foundational normative theories.
4. World-Affirming Environmental Ethics in the Gītā
The argument for environmental ethics from the world-affirming worldview in the
Gītā can be conceptualized as follows:
Premise One: There is a world-affirming worldview in the Gītā.
Premise Two: The world-affirming worldview applies to those who identify with their prakṛtic
Premise Three: The soteriological goal of the world-affirming view is to improve one’s existential situation within prakṛti.
Premise Four: Following the codes of dharma is the means to improve one’s existential situation within prakṛti.
Premise Five: Rules advancing the welfare of animals and plants is included in the codes of dharma.
Conclusion: Therefore, a normative environmental ethical theory can be derived from the world-affirming worldview in the Gītā.
Premise One: The
Gītā subscribes to the
Sāṃkhyan theory that conceives of nature as consisting of three subtle entities called the
guṇas, the highest
guṇa of
sattva representing goodness, insight and wisdom, the intermediate
guṇa of
rajas representing passion, activity and attachment, and the lowest
guṇa of
tamas representing ignorance, indolence and darkness. Though the
guṇas are often rendered as ‘qualities’, they are, as Jitendra Mohanty writes, more accurately represented as “affective components” of
prakṛti (
Mohanty 2000, p. 25). That is, the
guṇas are described in terms of qualia—they are subtle entities or substances that can be known through their effects on the subjectivity of the
puruṣa. Specifically, the
guṇas that pervade and comprise all phenomena born of
prakṛtic stuff are supposed to induce an innumerable variety of emotional and cognitive states. This idea of the
guṇas is foundational to the
Gītā’s metaphysical narrative and elaborate descriptions on how the
guṇas influence the
puruṣa take place throughout the text, especially in chapters fourteen, seventeen and eighteen. The
Gītā goes onto claim that
puruṣas embedded in
prakṛti seek to ‘taste’ experiences born of the permutations and combinations of the
gunas. Consequently, a world-affirming worldview in the context of the
Gītā, is one which affirms the pursuit of experiences born of the
guṇas. In this section, I wish to show that this type of a world-affirming worldview occurs on three different levels in the
Gītā.
At its lowest stage, Kṛṣṇa asks Arjuna to fight the battle simply to gain fame and honour since by withdrawing from the battle he will accrue infamy and dishonor (2.34–36). At the next stage of the world-affirming view, Kṛṣṇa augments his persuasive strategy with scriptural authority, specifically the idea that kṣatriyas or warriors who die in a righteous battle attain the celestial dimension of existence in their next life. This stage is higher than the previous argument to try and avoid infamy because at this stage, Arjuna is being advised to follow dharma to achieve some end not just in this life, but in the next life (2.48). By claiming that an agent is permitted to act to secure a desired outcome for oneself, the Gītā here advances a version of agent-relative consequentialism. A consequentialist approach to normative ethics claims that normative properties depend only on consequences. That is, we can judge the moral rightness of an act based solely on the consequences or outcomes of the act. Consequentialists thus argue that we can choose from among a range of actions by ranking the outcomes of those actions, such that I am permitted to perform an act A if and only if there is no alternative act B whose outcome ranks higher than A on my ranking scale. Agent-neutral consequentialists maintain that different agents will rank a set of outcomes in the same manner but agent-relative or subject-focused consequentialists recognize that different agents will potentially rank the same set of outcomes differently.
Now, the Gītā advances the view that different puruṣas exhibit different behavioural patterns because of being influenced by different permutations of the guṇas. Based on this view, the Gītā categorizes human society into four varnas or social classes. These four classes are that of the brāhmaṇas (teachers, intellectuals, priests), kṣatriyas (warriors, administrators, rulers), vaiśyas (bankers, farmers, business people) and śūdras (artisans, laborers). The Gītā, at 4.13, claims that humans naturally fall into these four social classes not based on birth, but because of exhibiting specific behavioural traits that spring from specific guṇa combinations. All this means that human subjects have four archetypal natures, and these four natures are attracted to different sets of values. When I speak of different human natures, I refer to the traits and behaviors exhibited by the mind-body complex. Because one can come under the influence of different guṇas at different times, human nature is potentially malleable. At the same time, the Gītā seems to hold the position that there are four archetypal human natures that spring from specific guṇa combinations. Accordingly, the reasons given by Kṛṣṇa here to persuade Arjuna are not arbitrary reasons but they are reasons that are supposed to specifically appeal to the set of values that characterize a kṣatriya nature. At 18.41–44, the text outlines the different sets of values that characterize the four archetypal human natures. Here, Kṛṣṇa is appealing to the values of valor, honor and heroism that typify a kṣatriya nature. My argument, then, is the Gītā here is advancing a version of agent-relative consequentialism, where it is recognized that different agents are attracted to different sets of values and consequently rank the same set of outcomes differently.
The third and highest stage of the world-affirming view occurs at 2.38 when Kṛṣṇa requests Arjuna to follow dharma for its own sake, or he asks the agent to perform one’s duty for the sake of duty. In contrast to the agent-relative consequentialist approach expressed at the two lower stages of the world-affirming view, the text now shifts to a deontological approach to normative ethics. The idea is that each of the four social classes have settled duties and while performing those duties one should purge one’s mind of the intent to enjoy the perceived beneficial outcome of those duties. The stage of performing one’s duty for the sake of duty, free from the motivation to enjoy the outcomes accruing from action, represents action born out of sattva guṇa. The Gītā, at 18.45, claims that when one performs one’s dharmic duty for the sake of duty, free from the motive to enjoy the perceived beneficial outcomes of the action, one experiences deep contentment—a characteristic of sattva guṇa. By giving three reasons that affirm the pursuit of happiness born of the guṇas that comprise prakṛti, the Gītā effectively affirms that the world of prakṛti is valuable and consequently, the motivation to maintain moral order and harmony within the prakṛtic world is valuable as well.
Premise Two: Considering that the
Gītā maintains that the
puruṣa is ontologically distinct from unconscious
prakṛti, who does the world-affirming view apply to? The answer is succinctly expressed at 13.21–22:
It is said that material nature is the cause in the matter of producing causes and effects, and that the living entity is the cause in the matter of experiencing pleasure and pain. The living entity situated in material nature experiences the guṇas that are the product of material nature. While its association with the guṇas is the cause of birth in a good or bad womb.
These two verses convey the familiar Vedāntic theme of a self-aware subject (puruṣa) identifying with prakṛti or the mind-body complex and thus desiring to enjoy the experiences that are generated by the mind-body complex. Even though ontologically distinct from the mind-body complex, the puruṣa becomes completely absorbed in the mind-body complex due to intense meditation on the objects of the senses (2.63). When the puruṣa becomes totally absorbed in the mind-body complex, then the puruṣa makes the mind-body complex one’s own and thus also becomes totally absorbed in the experiences generated by the guṇas that make up both the mind-body complex and the objects of the senses. Here, the text also makes the significant claim that the puruṣa generates the specific circumstances of its future rebirth according to how the puruṣa interacts with the guṇas.
Premise Three: For those who identify with their prakṛtic embodiment, the soteriological goal—the highest good—is to aspire for the best kind of experiences prakṛti can offer. Here, the Gītā seems to concur with the Mīmāṁsā notion that the highest experience prakṛti can offer is celestial existence or life in heaven. In keeping with Indic thought in general (by ‘Indic’ I refer to Hindu, Buddhist, and Jain commonalities), the Gītā advances a cosmological view in which the prakṛtic domain contains numerous celestial realms—svārga— the abodes of the devas or celestial beings or demigods—which are the destination of those with sufficient karmic credit (which, sooner or later, expires). I have noted how Kṛṣṇa tried to persuade Arjuna to fight based on the idea that if Arjuna wins, he will win the earthly kingdom, but if he is killed, he will attain heaven, since according to the principles of dharma, warriors killed in fighting a dharmic war attain heaven. At 2.42–43, Kṛṣṇa acknowledges that those who abide by the dharmic injunctions and rituals laid down in the Veda, get “good karma, good birth and good fruits of action. Full of desires and with heaven as their aim, these people practice an abundance of rituals, with the purpose of achieving pleasure and power.” At 9.20, the text has Kṛṣṇa reiterate that those who perform the sacrificial rituals of the Vedas with a desire to attain heaven, do indeed reach “the meritorious world of Indra, the lord of the gods,” where “they enjoy the celestial joys of the gods.” Finally, at 14.15, the text specifies that for one who has attained the state of sattva, meaning someone whose actions are primarily influenced by sattva guṇa, is destined to reborn in “the pure worlds of those possessing the highest knowledge” after giving up their present human body. We can conclude that for a puruṣa who identifies with his prakṛtic embodiment, the soteriological goal is to improve one’s existential situation within the prakṛtic domain. For the Gītā, improving one’s situation within the prakṛtic domain is tantamount to attaining the higher dimensions of the cosmos, where one can experience different grades of celestial existence.
Premise Four: The
Gītā prescribes the path of following
dharma as the means to improve one’s existential situation within the world of
prakṛti. In Premise one, I have clarified the
Gītā’s position that one can act in accordance with
dharma but with the desire to enjoy the outcomes of actions (an agent-relative consequentialist approach), or better still,
dharma can be performed in a mind-set characteristic of
sattva guṇa, that is, one can perform
dharmic duty for the sake of duty—a deontological approach (an idea explicitly stated at 17.11–12). For the
Gītā, acting in
sattva guṇa is the ideal one should aim for and “as such, being established in the
guṇa of goodness, one finds oneself adhering to
dharma” (
Theodor 2016, p. 10). At 18.6, Kṛṣṇa thus claims: My final judgment, Pārtha, is that these actions should be performed out of duty, abandoning attachment and interest in their fruits. 18.23 further specifies “an action is of the nature of goodness when performed according to the injunctions of dharma, without attachment, devoid of attraction or repulsion, by one who desires not its fruits.” Why does the
Gītā try to coax agents to gradually shift their allegiance to ideals born out of
sattva guṇa? One answer is what I have already previously mentioned, shifting to
sattva guṇa is the way to improve one’s existential situation within the domain of
prakṛti. In this sense, the
guṇas represent existential pathways through
sāṁsara with those
puruṣas predominated by
sattva guṇa being reborn into favourable circumstances in higher celestial dimensions of the cosmos. However, I contend there is a deeper motive driving the
Gītā’s agenda to persuade
puruṣas to act within the jurisdiction of
sattva guṇa. The clue to this deeper motive is found in chapter fourteen of the text, a chapter that explicitly engages with the topic of the three
guṇas. The chapter begins with Kṛṣṇa claiming that the knowledge he is about to speak is of a distinctly soteriological flavor and twice in the chapter, at 14.14 and 14.17, Kṛṣṇa equates
sattva guṇa with knowledge.
When the embodied soul meets death influenced by goodness, it attains the pure worlds of those possessing the highest knowledge.
From goodness arises knowledge.
The question arises: What kind of knowledge is this? The answer is specified at 18.20:
Know that knowledge to be of the nature of goodness, through which one sees a single imperishable reality in all beings, unified in the diversified.
Here, the text is indicating that shifting to
sattva guṇa qualifies one to perceive the underlying transcendent unity pervading all things. We can infer then that
sattva guṇa is the necessary pre-condition or the launching pad to attain the state of
mokṣa, a state characterized by the ability to
constantly perceive the underlying transcendent unity pervading the diversity of phenomena. The
Gītā’s agenda to persuade
puruṣas to act within the jurisdiction of
sattva guṇa can thus also be seen as a way of preparing a fertile existential ground where the pre-condition for
mokṣa can take root and sprout. Put differently, the text seems to suggest that by doing one’s
dharmic duty for the sake of duty one gradually qualifies oneself to attain the liberated state. On this view, the framework of
dharma becomes the instrumental device to attain the highest good—the ultimate
Upaniṣadic telos of
mokṣa. In this context, the
Gītā is advancing a multi-layered ethical theory where the foundational telos of
mokṣa grounds and explains a plurality of more superficial foundational normative theories. In approaching this idea, let me observe that to see how theories in normative ethics differ it is useful to “distinguish between normative
factors and normative
foundations” (
Perrett 2005, p. 325). Ethicists readily acknowledge a variety of normative factors—factors relevant to determining the moral status of a choice—outcomes, rules, constraints, obligations, virtues, and so on. However, the point of contention is which factor is most basic and most important and how to rank various normative factors in the likely event of conflict. The normative foundations of an ethical theory are supposed to clarify these issues by offering a conceptual device that justifies establishing one type of normative factor as most basic and most important. Normative ethical theories differ, then, because they offer competing foundational conceptual devices which allow one to rank normative factors differently and consequently claim that in making sense of the moral universe, one normative factor grounds and explains all other normative factors. Now, where a pluralist at the factoral level holds that more than one normative factor has significance, a pluralist at the foundational level holds that the different factors are grounded in different foundational devices. Roy Perrett suggests that there are two routes to justify the latter position:
One is right to insist that that there is an ultimate and irreducible pluralism at the foundations of normative ethics. The other is a bit more exotic: a foundational pluralism which also admits of the possibility of multilayering. The idea here is that there may be at a deeper foundational level still some single foundational theory that grounds and explains the plurality of more superficial foundational theories.
I contend that the Gītā advances exactly such a multi-layered ethical theory. First, Kṛṣṇa persuades Arjuna to perform his dharmic duty with the desire to enjoy the outcomes of actions and this is, as I have argued, an agent-relative consequentialist approach. However, then Kṛṣṇa tries to persuade Arjuna to perform his dharmic duty for the sake of duty, a deontological approach, or in the terms of the Gītā, a sattva guṇa approach. The Gītā clearly favours the sattva guṇa approach. My argument is that the deeper motive behind the Gītā’s agenda to recommend actions within the jurisdiction of sattva guṇa is that sattva guṇa is the pre-condition for attaining mokṣa. In this sense, the foundational teleological mokṣa theory grounds and explains the more superficial foundational normative theories of agent-relative consequentialism and deontology.
Premise Five: Considering that the
Gītā holds that
dharma is synonymous with
sattva guṇa, the question is: does the
Gītā text specify
dharmic ideals, ideals that are supposed to emerge out of
sattva guṇa? Along with Theodor (
Theodor 2016, p. 13), I contend that 16.1–4, offers a list of such ideals, “ideal qualities to be pursued while living in accordance with
dharma” (
Theodor 2016, p. 13):
Fearlessness, purification of one’s whole being, firmness in spiritual knowledge, generosity, self control and sacrifice, studying the Veda, austerity, righteousness, nonviolence, truthfulness, absence of anger, renunciation, tranquillity, avoiding vilification, compassion for all beings, absence of greed, gentleness, modesty, reliability, vigour, tolerance, fortitude, purity, absence of envy and pride—these are the qualities of one born to divine destiny, O Bhārata.
I consider these ideals to be synonymous with
sattva guṇa because at 18.5, the text specifies these “qualities lead to liberation” (
daivī sampad vimokṣāya) and as I have discussed in premise four, the text considers that
sattva guṇa bestows the type of salvific knowledge which is a precondition to attaining liberation. Note that this list includes two significant ideals:
ahiṁsā (nonviolence) and
dayā bhūteṣu (compassion or kindness toward all living entities). One can legitimately derive prescriptive moral injunctions about obligatory and forbidden actions that advance the welfare of individuals in nature, such as animals and plants, from these two ideals. In this context, it is worth noting that the
Manu Smṛti or
Mānava Dharma Śāstra, widely considered to be the most important text of the Dharma Śāstra genre, contains numerous injunctions proscribing the injury of animals and plants and even imposes religious penalties (
prāyaścitta) as well as civil penalties for injuring trees. Mary McGee notes that the authors of the Dharma Śāstras derived their laws for the protection of plants and trees from several perspectives, one of which is “a recognition of plants as sentient beings with consciousness, which therefore should be protected from harm (advocacy of
ahiṃsā)” (
McGee 2000, p. 93).
In conclusion, the world-affirming worldview of the Gītā applies to those puruṣas who identify with their prakṛtic embodiment and seek to improve their existential situation within prakṛti. The Gīta prescribes dharmic activity as a means to improve one’s existential situation within prakṛti and this includes living by the dharmic ideals of ahiṁsā and dayā bhūteṣu, from which we can legitimately derive specific injunctions for protecting and caring for animals and plants. Therefore, a normative environmental ethical theory can be legitimately derived from the world-affirming worldview in the Gītā.
5. World-Renouncing Environmental Ethics in the Gītā
The argument for environmental ethics from the world-renouncing worldview in the
Gītā can be schematized as follows:
Premise One: There is a world-renouncing worldview in the Gītā.
Premise Two: The world-renouncing worldview applies to those who identify as units of transcendent awareness ontologically distinct from their prakṛtic embodiment.
Premise Three: The soteriological goal of the world-renouncing view is to disconnect from prakṛti and achieve extinction in Brahman.
Premise Four: Engaging in activities advancing the welfare of all beings is the means to achieve the state of extinction in Brahman.
Premise Five: Activities that advance the welfare of animals and plants falls within the category of activities that advance the welfare of all beings.
Conclusion: Therefore, a normative environmental ethical theory can be legitimately derived from the world-renouncing worldview in the Gītā.
Premise One: The world-renouncing worldview appears in a number of places in the
Gītā, but I think the most systematic articulation of this worldview is at 13.7–11:
Absence of pride and arrogance, nonviolence, forbearance, honesty, attendance upon the guru, purity, firmness, self control, lack of attraction to sense objects, absence of ego-notion, visioning the distress and evil of birth, death, old age and disease, detachment, aloofness from sons, wife, home and the like, constant equanimity toward desired and undesired events, single-minded devotion to me supported by yoga, preferring of solitary places and avoiding the crowds, constant contemplation of knowledge of the self, envisioning the purpose of knowledge concerned with the truth—all these are declared knowledge, whereas all else is ignorance.
These verses seem to encourage an ascetic mode of living, wherein the primary purpose driving action is to relinquish the world of prakṛti altogether while simultaneously trying to connect to the unchanging, eternal, transcendent self that is the essential “I.”
Premise Two: The world-renouncing worldview applies to those who identify as transcendent awareness, ontologically distinct from prakṛti. From this perspective, one considers one’s mind-body complex to be external to oneself and consequently, also considers one’s entanglement in prakṛti to be circumstantial and an obstacle to realising one’s true state of being (see, for example, 13.3, 13.32, 13.33 and 13.34).
Premise Three: The soteriological goal—the highest good—of the world-renouncing worldview is liberation from
saṁsāra—the cycle of repeated birth and death that the embodied
puruṣa is said to undergo in the world of
prakṛti. The world-renouncer does not simply wish to transcend the
prakṛtic world, however, but simultaneously seeks to achieve the state of
brahma-nirvāṇa, literally, “extinction in Brahman.” I take this to mean that the world-renouncer intends to detach from the
prakṛtic composite that makes up one’s empirical personhood and solely retain awareness of self-luminous awareness itself. Kṛṣṇa uses the phrase
brahma-nirvāṇam three times, in three consecutive verses, at 5.24–26, a section of the
Gītā dedicated to delineating the world-renouncer’s soteriological goal:
He who can withstand the urges originating from lust and anger in this world, before release from the body, is yoked and is a happy person. He whose happiness is within, whose pleasure is within, and his enlightenment too is within is actually a yogī; with his whole being absorbed in Brahman, he attains to extinction in Brahman. The seers whose evils have been eradicated, who are free from doubt, self-controlled and who wish all beings well, attain extinction in Brahman. For those freed from lust and anger, who are ascetics of controlled minds and who know the self– for them close at hand lies extinction in Brahman.
Premise Four: Given the
Sāṁkhyan framework underpinning the
Gitā’s conception of nature or
prakṛti, the world-renouncer’s attempt to relinquish the world of
prakṛti is tantamount to transcending the
guṇas comprising
prakṛti. Indeed, the
Gītā, at 14.25, defines the liberated person as
guṇātītaḥ—having gone beyond or transcended the
guṇas. From the world-renouncing perspective, what does it mean to transcend the
guṇas? Recall that according to the
Gītā’s underlying
Sāṁkhya framework, the
guṇas make up everything within the world of
prakṛti and thus the endless variety of experiences perceived by the
puruṣa entangled in
saṁsāra are all generated by various permutations and combinations of the three
guṇas. Significantly, the text, at 3.27–29, characterizes ignorance as the inability to discern that conventional action in the world is performed under the influence of the
guṇas.
Although actions in every respect are performed by the guṇas of material nature, the spirit soul, confused by the ego thinks: ‘It is actually me who is the doer’. But, he who knows the truth, O mighty Arjuna, regarding the separation (of the soul) from both the guṇas and activity, and sees clearly that the guṇas act among themselves—he is not attached. Those thus bewildered by the guṇas of material nature, are attached to actions within the guṇas’ scope. However, he whose knowledge is complete may not disturb those fools whose knowledge is incomplete.
According to this analysis, in conventional existence in the world, when ignorant of the real nature of the
puruṣa as being ontologically distinct from
prakṛti, one actively pursues experiences born of
prakṛtic objects and evaluates everything in terms of its instrumental value to the fulfilment of
bhoga—prakṛtic enjoyment. To be “attached to actions within the guṇas’ scope”, then, is equivalent to identifying with the mind-body complex made of
prakṛtic stuff. The
Gītā claims that the
ahaṃkāra or ego, a most subtle aspect of the
prakṛtic psychological mechanism, is the glue that binds awareness to the mind-body complex and the
prakṛtic world. Jonathan Edelmann notes: “The etymological meaning of ahaṃkāra is ‘I-maker’, for it provides the self with the sense of being an individual, or an ‘I”. When the ego is applied to the body and mind, the result is a false concept of personal identity, or a sense of ‘I and mine’” (
Edelmann 2012, p. 65). This false sense of ‘I and mine’ causes the
puruṣa to associate one’s sense of identity with the mind-body complex the
puruṣa is presently embodied in. Specifically, the
puruṣa feel a sense of possessiveness or ownership over this particular mind-body complex, and all the other
prakṛtic objects connected with this mind-body complex (e.g., family members, wealth, fame, nation, etc). As long as the
puruṣa remains under the influence of the
ahaṃkāra, the
puruṣa actively seeks to ‘possess and own’
prakṛtic objects that can generate ‘good’ experiences for the
prakṛtic mind-body complex one is embodied in and this disposition ensures that the
puruṣa continues to remain under the influence of the
guṇas, and continues to be reborn in various types of
prakṛtic bodies according to the
karmic merit and demerit one acquires. To gain release from
saṁsāra, then, one has to become indifferent to the deep-rooted psychological disposition to ‘possess and own’ the experiences generated by the
guṇas that make up the world. This is diametrically opposed to the world-affirming worldview, where one is motivated to act to possess the fruits of one’s actions (the experiences generated by the
guṇas). From the world-renouncer perspective, the motivation for action is to transcend the
guṇas by not desiring to possess the fruits of action but by desiring solely to yoke oneself to
Brahman, as described in chapter two (2.45, 2.47, 2.48, 2.51):
O Arjuna, rise above the three guṇas’ realm! Be free from duality, always planted in the truth, free from the desire to possess and preserve, and established in the self. Your sole entitlement is to perform dharmic activity, not ever to possess its fruits; never shall the fruit of an action motivate your deed, and never cleave to inaction. O Dhanañjaya, perform activities while you are fixed in yoga; relinquishing attachment, be equally accepting of both success and failure, for this equanimity is called yoga. The wise who are rooted in this enlightenment relinquish indeed the fruits born of actions; thus they are freed from the bondage of rebirth, and go to that place which is free from any pain.
To counter the puruṣa’s false sense of ownership and possessiveness, the text is advising the world-renouncer to develop equanimity (sama) toward the guṇas. Indeed, the text seems to suggest that developing equanimity toward the psychological flux produced by the guṇas is the necessary condition for the puruṣa to embark upon the project of liberation from saṁsāra (see 14.21–25). To develop equanimity toward the guṇas, is to become detached from the influence of the ahaṃkara, because it is the ahaṃkara, which focuses the awareness of the puruṣa upon his prakṛtic embodiment and the false sense of “I and mine” that comes from this absorption. This false sense of “I and mine” is what drives the puruṣa to seek endless configurations of guṇa experiences, experiences that arise when the mind and senses which are made up of the guṇas come in contact with sense objects, also made up of the guṇas. To become detached from the ahaṃkara, then, is to become indifferent to the inevitable duality of pleasure and pain that arises from the senses coming in contact with their sense objects, which is, in effect, means relinquishing the pursuit of guṇa-born experiences. All this, of course, leads to the question: What is the ethical means through which the world-renouncer can give up the pursuit of guṇa experiences and develop equanimity toward the influence of the guṇas?
I believe the answer to this question is found in the phrase sarva-bhūta-hite ratāḥ, which appears in that same form, twice in the Gītā—5.25 and 12.4. The first time it appears, in 5.25, Kṛṣṇa uses the phrase to qualify the person fit to attain brahma-nirvāṇa, or extinction in Brahman. Kṛṣṇa again uses the same phrase, in 12.4, to qualify the person fit to attain akṣaram avyaktaṁ—that is, the imperishable and unmanifest Brahman. The phrase sarva-bhūta-hite ratāḥ may be translated as “concerned with the welfare of all beings” or “engaged in the welfare of all beings.” I believe sarva-bhūta-hite ratāḥ is the primary ethical principle through which the world-renouncer is supposed to develop equanimity toward the influence of the guṇas. The rationale behind this idea is that by focusing on acting for the welfare of all beings, the puruṣa can relinquish the ahaṃkara-centred pursuit of guṇa experiences within saṁsāra, which further allows the puruṣa to detach from the ahaṃkara itself and develop “constant equanimity toward desired and undesired events,” brought about by the guṇas (mind and senses) interacting with the guṇas (sense objects). The idea of “constant equanimity toward desired and undesired events” is conveyed in the phrase “nityaṁ ca sama-cittatvam iṣṭāniṣṭopapattiṣu”, one of the qualities of the world-renouncer described at 13.10.
Premise Five:
Sarva-bhūta-hite ratāḥ is a broad principle, but I contend that the lowest common denominator of this principle is the promotion of non-violence and non-possessiveness toward animals and trees. Christopher Chapple has made the case that non-violence to animals, trees, and self, when combined with non-possessiveness can result in ecological awareness:
[T]he solutions that Gandhi proposed to counter the ills of colonialism can also be put into effect to redress this new and ultimately deleterious situation. The observance of nonviolence, coupled with a commitment to minimize consumption of natural resources, can contribute to restoring and maintaining an ecological balance.
According to Chapple, Gandhi and others who follow ascetic ideals such as non-possession, celibacy, and non-violence, serve as exemplars for limiting resource-consumption and minimizing their ecological footprint and can thus serve as an inspiration for environmental ethics.
Sarva-bhūta-hite ratāḥ can also mean a more proactive brand of social activism that includes environmental activism. The inspiration for this interpretation comes from chapter six of the
Gītā, a chapter dedicated to discussing classical yoga, a psychosomatic manual of meditative practice aimed at helping one realize the actual nature of the
puruṣa. At 6.32, the text has Kṛṣṇa declare:
O Arjuna, one who in relation to himself sees all beings equally, whether in happiness or distress, is considered the supreme yogī.
Vedāntic theologians often gloss this verse as one offering a vision of universal empathy—just as I do not desire to remain in a state of pain and endeavour to mitigate my pain, so it is for all living beings (see, for example, Śaṇkara’s gloss to this verse). Lance Nelson, while acknowledging this, quotes Rāmānuja’s commentary on this verse as saying that the highest
yogī is cognizant of the sameness of all
puruṣas (selves), in that, being of the nature of
Brahman,
puruṣas are ultimately disconnected from and indeed, untouched by the pleasure and pain incurred in embodied existence in
saṁsāra. Nelson argues that this vision is “ecologically unnerving” because by claiming that “spirit is untouched by mere empirical calamities”
Vedāntic thought minimizes the significance of empirical calamities such as the degradation of the environment (
Nelson 2000, pp. 143, 151). Nelson’s claim implies that upon attaining
Brahman absorption, one would view the pain incurred by selves in embodied existence with ‘transcendental indifference’ and do nothing to mitigate it, since, after all,
Brahman is untouched by matter. On this view, Rāmānuja should have done nothing to mitigate the suffering of embodied beings, knowing that
Brahman is untouched by matter. Yet, Rāmānuja devoted his life to spreading the teachings and practices of Śrī Vaiṣṇavism, which, for him, was clearly the means to mitigate the suffering brought about by empirical calamities. In exactly the same vein, Pankaj Jain asks: “If the world was an illusion,
māyā, for Śaṅkara why would he work to “defeat” Buddhist tradition and other ideologies in the popular discourses as captured in the Śaṅkara-Digvijaya?” (
Jain 2011, p. 12). The question is: If the highest
yogī is supposed to be completely indifferent to the events of the empirical world, as suggested by Nelson, then why would such a person initiate reform movements aimed at bringing about change in the empirical world? Put precisely, if
Brahman is untouched by empirical calamities, then why do
Vedāntic theologians go to such great lengths to spread the teachings and practices of their respective
Vedāntic schools, which for them, is ostensibly an endeavour to help
puruṣas be liberated from empirical calamities?
I contend that an answer to this question requires that we read
Brahman absorption as having a rather different effect than what is suggested by Nelson. The vision of universal empathy articulated at 6.32 comes after a series of verses depicting the
yogī attaining
brahma-bhūtam (absorption in
Brahman)
, brahma-saṁsparśam (contact with
Brahman) and
sama-darśanaḥ—equal vision perception—by virtue of seeing the Supreme Person everywhere and everything in the Supreme Person (see 6.27–31). I take this to mean that
sarva-bhūta-hite ratāḥ is not just the ethical means to attain immersion in
Brahman but is also the symptom of one who has attained immersion in
Brahman. The rationale for this interpretation is reinforced by the fact that the
Gītā does not present inaction as a permanent option for the
puruṣa. This being the case, the question may be raised: How does the
puruṣa who has attained absorption in
Brahman act? Eliot Deutsch posits that the world-renouncer who has attained
Brahman absorption is now free and can act “without destructive intentions” (quoted in (
Jain 2011, p. 9)). Anantanand Rambachan says that when a spiritually perfected self dispels the veil of ignorance, they do not view the world as illusory, but rather, they see the world as non-different from
Brahman (
Rambachan 2006, pp. 79–80). Building on all this, I read
Brahman absorption as having the effect of freeing the
puruṣa from the
ahaṃkara-centred instrumentalist vision of seeing the world as a means to fulfilling one’s schemes for
bhoga. However, apart from the emancipatory effect of
Brahman absorption, I read
Brahman absorption as having an ‘activist’ effect as well. On this view, the
brahma-bhūta yogī’s seeing the world as non-different from
Brahman is equivalent to being fully sensitive to the inherent pain of embodied existence. That is, the
brahma-bhūta yogī may know that the eternally changing
Brahman is completely unrelated to matter, but the
brahma-bhūta yogī also knows that
puruṣas under the influence of
māyā (ignorance) do acutely experience the inherent pain of embodied existence in
saṁsāra. Therefore, the
brahma-bhūta yogī ‘works’ to help all beings (re)discover their true ontological status as beings partaking of the inherent bliss of
Brahman. Being proactive about ecological concerns can thus be a legitimate subset of the world-renouncer
yogī’s compassionate outreach to mitigate the pain of embodied beings, both in the stage of yoga practice and in the stage of perfection (
Brahman absorption).
By mandating the world-renouncer to engage in activities for the welfare of all beings, the Gītā is advancing a virtue ethics approach to normative ethics. This is because whether at the stage of practice or of perfection, the Gītā has defined the world-renouncer in terms of virtues. At 13.8–12, the text lists the virtues that characterize the world-renouncer at the stage of practice and at 5.19–26, the text lists the virtues that characterize the world-renouncer at the stage of perfection. That is, from the world-renouncer perspective, virtue is the foundational normative concept and other normative notions are grounded in virtue. Therefore, when the Gītā asks the world-renouncer to advance the welfare of animals and plants, it does so because this is the virtuous thing to do. At the same time, the world-renouncer is intent on attaining brahma-nirvana or Brahman immersion. In this sense, the text is taking what I call a mokṣa-based virtue ethics approach. This is similar to the eudaimonist versions of virtue ethics which define virtues in terms of their relationship to eudaimonia—a key term in ancient Greek moral philosophy usually translated as “flourishing” or “well-being.” A virtue is a trait that contributes to or is a constituent of eudaimonia and we ought to develop virtues, the eudaimonist claims, precisely because they contribute to eudaimonia. In the same way, the world-renouncer is asked to express the virtue of sarva-bhūta-hite ratāḥ because expressing the virtue is necessary for the world-renouncer to attain the state of brahma-nirvana or from the perspective of the perfected world-renouncer, sarva-bhūta-hite ratāḥ is a virtue that is a constituent of Brahman immersion. Again, this exemplifies the Gītā’s multi-layered approach to ethical theory, where the foundational teleological mokṣa theory grounds and explains a more superficial foundational normative theory, in this case, virtue ethics.
Some commentators imply that from the world-renouncer perspective, the duality of virtue and vice does not exist, since the world-renouncer only sees, or is aiming to see, the non-dual
Brahman. It seems that such an imperative to transcend duality also implies transcending the categories of moral and immoral altogether. Without acknowledging the dual categories of moral and immoral, what is the basis for any kind of ethical imperative, including the imperative to care for animals and plants? Nelson expresses this concern when he writes: “In the Upaniṣads and in the
Gītā, as elsewhere in the tradition (especially in Tantra), there is a marked drift toward an ultimate amoralism (or perhaps transmoralism) in the absolute realm, one that may not bode well for ecological awareness” (
Nelson 2000, p. 144).
In addressing this concern, I contend that when the Gītā speaks of transcending duality, it is referring to transcending the mentality of categorizing experiences as ‘good’ or ‘bad’ in relation to one’s ahaṃkara-centred enjoyment. However, even for the world-renouncer, there still exists the dual categories of virtue and vice. The Gītā makes this point at the beginning of chapter eighteen. The chapter begins with Arjuna asking Kṛṣṇa to clarify the meaning of renunciation (tyāga) and the meaning of the renounced stage of life (sannyasa), and the difference between them. At 18.3, Kṛṣṇa notes that some great thinkers claim that all types of actions should be abandoned, since they are inherently faulty, yet other sages maintain that acts of sacrifice (yajña), giving (dāna) and austerity (tapaḥ) should never be abandoned. Then, at 18.5, the text has Kṛṣṇa give his opinion on the matter:
Acts of sacrifice, giving and austerity are not to be given up, but rather should be performed, as sacrifice, giving and austerity purify even the wise.
Now, if the world-renouncer is to continue acts of sacrifice, giving and austerity, then clearly there must be a basis for him to differentiate between actions that count as acts of sacrifice, giving and austerity, and those that do not. This basis, as I have argued, is provided by the soteriological goal of the world-renouncer, the intent to achieve extinction in Brahman. For the world-renouncer, then, virtuous actions are ones that help oneself and others attain Brahman immersion. A world-renouncer who has already attained Brahman immersion continues acts of sacrifice, giving and austerity, to help other puruṣas attain Brahman immersion.
In summary, the world-renouncing worldview of the Gītā applies to those puruṣas who identify as self-luminous awareness, ontologically distinct from their prakṛtic embodiment. The soteriological goal of the world-renouncer is to achieve the state of extinction in Brahman or to realize the true status of self-luminous awareness freed from its entanglement with prakṛti. Engaging in activities for the welfare of all beings is the ethical means to achieve extinction in Brahman as well as the symptom of one who has achieved extinction in Brahman. Activities to care for and protect animals and plants is included in the category of engaging in activities for the welfare of all beings. Therefore, a normative environmental ethical theory can be legitimately derived from the world-renouncing worldview in the Gītā.
6. Bhakti-Inspired Environmental Ethics in the Gītā
The argument for bhakti-inspired environmental ethics within the
Gītā can be systematized as follows:
Premise One: There is a bhakti worldview in the Gītā.
Premise Two: The bhakti worldview applies to those who identify as an eternal servant or worshipper of Īśvara or the Supreme Person.
Premise Three: The soteriological goal of the bhakti worldview is to attain the state of eternal devotion to and loving service of Īśvara.
Premise Four: To glorify and worship Īśvara is the means to be absorbed in devotion to Īśvara.
Premise Five: Activities that advance the welfare of animals and plants falls within the category of activities that glorify and worship Īśvara.
Conclusion: Therefore, a normative environmental ethical theory can be derived from the bhakti worldview in the Gītā.
Premise One: The
bhakti worldview appears throughout the text of the
Gītā but is most succinctly articulated in the concluding verse of the ninth chapter, 9.34, as follows:
Always think of me and become my devotee, worship me and pay homage unto me; thus yoked to me and intent on me as your highest goal, you shall come to me.
This verse depicts a state of being where the puruṣa’s awareness is completely absorbed in the Supreme Person, and is widely considered to be one of the climaxes of the Bhagavad Gītā. The significance of this bhakti ideal in the Gītā’s overall presentation can be gauged from the fact that the verse appears again almost verbatim at the end of the Gītā’s epilogue at 18.65. Numerous times throughout the text, Kṛṣṇa reiterates the ideal of total absorption in him, the bliss of exchanging loving relations with the Supreme Person and the ultimate goal of returning to the supreme deity’s dhāma or abode (see, for example, 8.14–15).
Premise Two: The bhakti worldview applies to those puruṣas who identify themselves as eternal servants or lovers of the Supreme Person. That is, the identity of the bhakta is defined and constructed through one’s relationship with the Supreme Person. The ontological infrastructure for the bhakti worldview rests on the notion of Īśvara, a supreme puruṣa ontologically different from and indeed, higher than all other puruṣas. This idea is explicated in some detail in the last five verses of the Gītā’s fifteenth chapter. At 15.16, the text asserts there are two types of puruṣas, kṣara-puruṣas, perishable beings, and akṣara-puruṣas, imperishable ones. The kṣara-puruṣas are all living entities, sarvāṇi bhūtāni, and the akṣara-puruṣas are kuṭastha, literally, situated on the top. The term kuṭastha is used twice in the Gītā, in 6.8 to refer to the enlightened yogī and in 12.3 to refer to the quality of the highest truth realized by the enlightened yogī. On this account, we can infer that the kṣara-puruṣa refers to the unenlightened being, and the akṣara-puruṣa refers to the enlightened being. Significantly, 15.17 goes on to describe another, highest puruṣa, the paramātmā, the supreme self who pervades the three worlds and supports them, and uses the term Īśvara to designate this highest puruṣa. 15.18 again reiterates that this highest puruṣa is higher than both kṣara and akṣara puruṣas and is celebrated both in the world and in the Veda-derived literature aspuruṣottama—Supreme Person, 15.19 claims that one who knows this Supreme Person to be Kṛṣṇa knows all that there is to know and finally, 15.20 concludes the chapter by asserting that this knowledge of the supreme self is the most confidential scriptural teaching. Thus, in consonance with other schools of theistic Indic thought, the Gītā advocates a vision of Īśvara as a special puruṣa belonging to a different ontological category from other puruṣas, while at the same time the Gītā puts a name to this Īśvara—Kṛṣṇa.
Premise Three: In contrast to the world-renouncing worldview where the
puruṣa seeks
Brahman immersion, a state where awareness is absorbed in its own nature, the soteriological goal of the
bhakti worldview is two-fold: to be perpetually absorbed in loving devotion to
Īśvara and upon attaining final liberation (through the grace of
Īśvara), to enter
Īśvara’s eternal personal abode to perpetually engage in loving relationships with
Īśvara. The theistic Vedāntins who articulated this view (for example, Rāmānuja’s commentary to Vedānta Sūtras I.1.21) would characterize
Īśvara’s personal realms as
saguṇa-brahman, realms within
Brahman that are made of self-luminous awareness—
Brahman—but that nonetheless contain forms, individuals, and personalities. Foundational to this view, is the idea that
Īśvara’s mind and form are not made of
prākṛtic stuff, even in its purest
sāttvic potential, but made of
Brahman and thus part of the essential nature of
Īśvara rather than an external
prākṛtic covering as is the case with
puruṣas embedded in
saṁsāra. Moreover, the liberated
puruṣas who attain
Īśvara’s personal
Brahman realm again become re-embodied, but this time not in a temporary form made of the evolutes of
prakṛti but in an eternal trans-
prakṛtic Brahman form—a form made of self-luminous awareness in which bliss is inherent and ever-expanding. It is with mind and senses made of Brahman stuff that the liberated
puruṣas see, hear, think about, and lovingly interact with
Īśvara in these
Brahman realms. A number of
Gītā verses seem to support this soteriological goal. At 8.21, the text has Kṛṣṇa characterize
paramāṁ gatim—the supreme destination to be attained—as
tad dhāma paramaṁ mama—“that is
My supreme abode.” The text again gets Kṛṣṇa to use the same phrase
tad dhāma paramaṁ mama in 15.6 to characterize the destination of those liberated
yogīs “constantly absorbed in the supreme self” who will never again return to the
prakṛtic realm. At 18.61–2, the text asserts that
Īśvara abides in the heart of all living beings and exhorts Arjuna to take refuge in
Īśvara in all respects (
sarva-bhāvena) for by
Īśvara’s grace (
tat-prasādāt) “you shall attain supreme peace and the eternal abode.” Approaching the
Gītā’s finale, at 18.65, the text again has Kṛṣṇa declare:
Always think of me, become my devotee, worship me and pay your homage unto me, and thus you shall undoubtedly come to me; I promise you this as you are dear to me.
Premise Four: The means to be absorbed in devotion to
Īśvara is to worship and glorify
Īśvara as expressed at 9.13–14:
But those great souls whose nature is immersed in the divine, worship me intently, O Pārtha, knowing me to be the imperishable source of all beings. Ever striving to glorify me with fortitude, bowing down to me in devotion, they are ever absorbed in worshiping me.
Additionally, again in 10.9–10:
Those whose consciousness is absorbed in me, for whom I am everything, enlighten one another about me, constantly speaking of me; thus absorbed, they are delighted and content. Those thus constantly absorbed in me, who worship me with love, I endow with the understanding by which they can come to me.
This constant absorption in Īśvara is supposed to help one transcend the influence of the guṇas, and attain Brahman status, but as opposed to the world-renouncer perspective wherein one seeks to detach from one’s empirical personhood composed of prakṛtic stuff to become immersed in Brahman, in the bhakti worldview, attaining Brahman status is tantamount to being constantly and unwaveringly engaged in the worship and service of Īśvara. At 14.26 the text thus claims that one who serves Kṛṣṇa constantly through bhakti-yoga, “unswervingly and without going astray,” transcends the guṇas and at 18.54 the text presents the idea that one attains supreme devotion to Kṛṣṇa after attaining Brahman status.
Premise Five: The case that acting for the benefit of individuals in nature, such as animals and plants, constitute worship and glorification of
Īśvara is linked to the
Gītā’s panentheistic conception of the divine. Panentheism is the view that God is simultaneously immanent in the world and transcendent to the world. In the terms of the
Gītā this means that
Īśvara is simultaneously immanent in
prakṛti and transcendent to
prakṛti. A panentheistic vision appears throughout the
Gītā text (7.12 and 9.4):
Know that all states of being, be they characterized by sattva, rajas or tamas, have their source in me alone; but I am not in them—rather they are in me.
I pervade the entire world in my unmanifest form; all beings rest in me, but I do not rest in them.
Rāmānuja, the founding theologian and hierarch of the Śrī Vaiṣṇava community articulates this panentheistic vision in his theology of
viśiṣtādvaita—‘differentiated non-duality’—an interpretation of
Vedānta which is as an exemplar of Indic panentheism. Eric Lott has shown that this panentheistic vision does not owe itself to Rāmānuja, rather, it has deep roots in Hindu texts (
Lott 1976). Rāmānuja posited an eternal tripartite differentiation within
Brahman or ultimate reality:
Brahman as supreme personal Being, or
Īśvara, whom he correlated with Viṣṇu/Nārāyāṇa;
prakṛti or matter; and
puruṣas or selves. Rāmānuja claimed these are eternal and real ontological categories but these categories do not compromise the essential nonduality of
Brahman since everything emanates from, and remains wholly contingent on
Īśvara for their existence.
Viśiṣtādvaita affirms that
Īśvara includes, penetrates and sustains the entire universe, so that the conscious selves (
puruṣas) and unconscious matter (
prakṛti) that constitute this world are inseparable from
Īśvara’s being and exists in
Īśvara, but, as opposed to pantheism, this panentheistic vision claims that
Īśvara’s being is still distinct from and transcendent to the universe. Rāmānuja clarified this relationship between
Īśvara,
puruṣas and
prakṛti through the analogy that the world consisting of
puruṣas and
prakṛti is the body of the supreme personal
Brahman, or
Īśvara. Just as in the relationship of self and body, the body, although distinct from the self, is inseparably dependent on and controlled by the self, the world made up of
puruṣas and
prakṛti, although distinct from
Īśvara, is inseparably dependent on and controlled by
Īśvara.
Śrī Vaiṣṇava soteriology, which I take to be an archetype of the
bhakti soteriological goal articulated in the
Gītā, says that to eternally glorify, worship and serve
Īśvara is the ultimate destiny of the
puruṣa on account of one’s inherent subservience to and dependence on
Īśvara. The tradition teaches that the life of a
prapanna, one who has surrendered to
Īśvara, is one of service to and worship of
Īśvara. Significantly, Śrī Vaiṣṇava theologians say that the
prapanna’
s worship of
Īśvara, here on earth, takes primarily three forms: first, one serves
Īśvara’s divine form in his
murti manifestation (
arcavatara) in the temple; second, one serves
Īśvara’s
bhaktas (devotees), those whom
Īśvara especially loves and whom he regards as his very self, and third, one works for the welfare of the world
—loka-
saṅgraha—by supporting the
dharmic order that sustains the world (
Mumme 1998).
This third aspect of the prapanna’s worship of Īśvara needs some elucidation. After all, if the ultimate goal and destiny of the puruṣa is to attain a state of salvation outside of this world, then why should one work for the welfare of this world? To answer this question, let us begin by noting that the term loka-saṅgraha appears twice, at 3.20 and 3.25, in a part of the Gītā where Kṛṣṇa is seeking to motivate Arjuna to fight the battle as a form of detached (asaktaḥ) dharmic duty. The question may justly be raised: If one is detached from acquiring any type of prakṛtic gain, then why should one continue to act in the world of prakṛti? In the context of the bhakti worldview, the answer is that the bhakta’s (or prapanna’s) desire to work for the welfare of the world by supporting the eternal dharmic order is an expression of the bhakta’s devotion to Īśvara. Indeed, the Gītā, at 4.7–8, famously depicts Īśvara repeatedly descending to this prakṛtic world to maintain dharmic order. Therefore, the bhakta’s motivation for supporting dharmic order is to serve and glorify Īśvara, as opposed to those who subscribe to the world-affirming worldview described earlier, who also follow dharmic codes, but not out of a motive to serve Īśvara but because they are driven by the purpose of improving their existential situation within prakṛti. It is in this sense that the bhakti worldview is simultaneously world-affirming and world-renouncing. Bhaktas seek to be detached from pursuing guṇa-born experiences involving any kind of prakṭic object and in this sense, because they do not see the world as a means to fulfil ahaṃkāra-centred purposes, they can be said to have renounced the world. At 12.13, the text delineates the qualities of the ideal bhakta and specifically claims that the ideal bhakta is nirahaṅkāraḥ (without false ego) and nirmamaḥ (with no sense of proprietorship). However, at the same time, bhaktas read the Gītā as saying that the world exhibits the power and excellence of Īśvara and is a divine manifestation expressing Īśvara’s glory (vibhūti) (see 10.16 and 10.41). Moreover, Īśvara is invested in maintaining the dharmic order that sustains the world and it is therefore incumbent upon the bhakta to work for the welfare of the world according to dharmic codes because by doing so one worships Īśvara.
In this vein, Patricia Mumme (
Mumme 1998) has argued that service to the earth and the living beings she supports is consistent with all three forms of service to
Īśvara that the
prapanna is supposed to undertake. Since, in the panentheistic vision of Śrī Vaiṣṇava theology, the earth and the living beings she supports are also
Īśvara’s body, so service to them is also akin to serving
Īśvara’s body, no less than serving his form in the temple. Moreover,
Īśvara loves all
puruṣas in this world, for these are his body, which he regards as his self, and for whose salvation and protection
Īśvara has often descended into this world. Furthermore, Mumme argues that Śrī Vaiṣṇavas have an incentive to undertake ecological activism since service that advances the welfare of the world—
loka-
saṅgraha—is included within service to
Īśvara, which is the
puruṣa’s ultimate goal and destiny, even for
puruṣas that have attained the ultimate soteriological goal of completely surrendering (
prapatti) to
Īśvara.
I contend that these three reasons for engaging in ecological activism constitute a mokṣa-based virtue ethics approach to normative ethics. However, as opposed to the world-renouncer’s conception of mokṣa being equivalent to attaining extinction in Brahman, the bhakta equates the state of mokṣa to a state of being where one is constantly absorbed in worshipping and glorifying Īśvara. The Gītā specifies that the bhakta or prapanna ought to express a host of virtues because expressing those virtues are necessary to please and serve Īśvara. For example, the last eight verses of the twelfth chapter of the text, 12.13–20, catalogues a list of virtues distinguishing the bhakta who is dear (priyaḥ) to Kṛṣṇa. The list claims that the ideal bhakta is adveṣṭā (nonenvious), maitraḥ (friendly) and karuṇaḥ (compassionate) to sarva-bhūtānāṁ (all living entities). Note that the bhakta expresses these virtues in relation to the ultimate telos of becoming dear to Krishna or worshipping Kṛṣṇa. That is, the bhakta sees the ontic equality of all puruṣas, as they are all part of Īśvara’s being and are equally loved by Īśvara, and therefore, the bhakta knows that when one expresses the virtue of being compassionate to all living entities, one simultaneously pleases Kṛṣṇa. In this way, the Gītā indicates that to serve and worship Kṛṣṇa one must also express a host of other virtues or put differently, the state of serving and worshipping Kṛṣṇa constitutes a set of virtues such as being compassionate to all living entities. This is another instance of the Gītā’s multi-layered approach to ethical theory, where the foundational teleological mokṣa theory grounds and explains a more superficial foundational normative theory, in this case, virtue ethics.
In conclusion, despite the evidently other-worldly soteriological goal of the Gītā’s bhakti worldview, the ethical means to achieve this goal can include this-worldly environmental activism. The Gītā advances a panentheistic conception of the divine that sees the world of prakṛti as both real and valuable to Īśvara, so much so that Īśvara specifically descends to this world to uplift and maintain the dharmic order that sustains it. Therefore, puruṣas who identify as eternal servants of Īśvara can serve Īśvara by acting for the benefit of individuals in nature, such as animals and plants, because such activities are a legitimate subset of activities that support the dharmic order that sustains the world, and by acting to support the dharmic order one pleases Īśvara.