A Compensatory Response to the Problem of Evil
Abstract
:1. Univocity Thesis and the Goodness of God
As it is usually presented, the problem of evil is a problem which arises on the assumption that if God exists, he must be morally good. Hence, it is that writers like Swinburne and Hick to deal with it by attempting to exonerate God from the moral point of view in spite of the existence of evil. But now suppose we introduce a new question into the discussion. Suppose we ask whether the theist is bound to regard God as a moral agent. Once we do this a whole new line of defense is open to someone who thinks it is reasonable to believe in the existence of God along with the existence of evil. For, clearly, if belief in God is not necessarily belief in the existence of a moral agent, then the problem of evil … it turns into a pseudo-problem.6
… classical theism thinks of God as the source of all beings … But if God is the source of all beings, something has to be done to distinguish him from all beings, and the obvious thing to do is to deny that God is a being. Yet moral agents, whether bad or good, are obviously beings. If God is not, in terms of classical theism, properly spoken of as a being, he is not properly spoken of as a moral agent8
[God] is distinct from everything, … He is so in a peculiar and pre-eminent fashion, … as no created being confronts any other … God stands at an infinite distance from everything else, not in the finite degree of difference with which created things stand towards each other.10
- (1)
- Either God’s goodness is completely different in kind from the kind(s) of moral goodness we admire in ourselves or other human beings, or it is the same kind of moral goodness we admire in ourselves or other human beings.
- (2)
- If it is completely different in kind from the kind(s) of moral goodness we admire in ourselves and other human beings, then God’s goodness is unintelligible to us.
- (3)
- If it is the same kind of moral goodness we admire in ourselves or other human beings, the God’s goodness is intelligible to us.
- (4)
- Therefore, either God’s goodness is unintelligible to us or God’s goodness is intelligible to us.
the standards of good reasoning about God are exactly the same standards for good reasoning about anything. Piety does not excuse fallacies. The theory of univocity holds that some of our words mean exactly the same thing as when used of God as they mean when used of creatures.13
Neither is all predication purely equivocal, as some have said, since this would entail that nothing can be known or demonstrated about God, but rather would always be subject to the fallacy of equivocation. This would be contrary to the philosophers, who prove many things about God through demonstration.14
are so depraved that our ideas of goodness count for nothing; or worse than nothing—the very fact that we think something good is presumptive evidence that it is really bad. The word good, applied to Him, becomes meaningless: like abracadabra. [However, if so]16 We have no motive for obeying Him…If cruelty is from His point of view ‘good,’ telling lies may be ‘good’ too…If His ideas of good are so very different from ours, what He calls Heaven might well be what we should call Hell, and vice versa. Finally, if reality at its very root is so meaningless to us—or, putting it the other way round, if we are such total imbeciles—what is the point of trying to think either about God or about anything else? This knot becomes undone when you try to pull it tight.17
2. God’s Governance of the Universe and Politically Liberal Societies
political states, particularly those aiming at securing a high level of justice for their members, are structured to secure a range of important freedoms for all of their members, even when doing so requires interfering with the freedoms of some of their members. For example, consider laws against assault. Such laws are designed to help protect people against assault, where assault is understood characteristically as intentionally acting to cause serious physical injury to another person. Whenever such assaults occur, they result in morally unacceptable distributions of freedom. What happens is that the freedom of the assaulters, a freedom no one should have, is exercised at the expense of the freedom of their victims not to be assaulted, an important freedom everyone should have.21
- (1)
- The politically liberal state has an obligation to provide for its citizens those goods to which they have a right, when it can be done easily, and doing so does not violate the morally significant rights of others.
- (2)
- God’s governance of the universe is analogous to the head of a politically liberal state.
- (3)
- God is a being perfect in power, knowledge, and goodness—a good God.
- (4)
- If a good God exists and created human beings, then God is obligated to provide for the well-being of human beings just as the head of a politically liberal state is obligated to provide for the well-being of its citizens, as best as he or she is able.
- (5)
- If God is obligated to provide for the well-being of human beings, then God is able to provide all human beings those goods to which they have a right without violating the morally significant rights of other human beings.
- (6)
- It is not the case that most human beings possess the goods to which they have a right and which constitute their well-being.
- (7)
- Therefore, either God is derelict in God’s duties with respect to human beings or God does not exist.
- (8)
- It is not possible that a being perfect in power, knowledge, and goodness is derelict in their duties with respect to human beings.
- (9)
- Therefore, God does not exist.
God keeps faith forever, executes justice for the oppressed, gives food to the hungry, sets prisoners free, opens the eyes of the blind, lifts up those who are bowed down, watches over strangers, and upholds the orphan and the widow.26
3. Marilyn Adams on Horrendous Evils
- (1)
- If God exists, then horrendous evils do not exist.
- (2)
- Horrendous evils exist.
- (3)
- Therefore, God does not exist.
4. Meticulous Divine Intervention and the Horns of a Dilemma
…Matthew Shepard was befriended by two men in a bar in Laramie, Wyoming in 1998. The two men, who were reportedly anti-gay, offered to give Shepard a lift and then drove him to a remote location where they robbed, severely beat, and tortured him, and left him to die hanging on a fence, where he lapsed into unconsciousness and was discovered the next day by a passing cyclist who thought he was a scarecrow. Shepard died two days later in a Laramie hospital never having regained consciousness.”31
So clearly with respect to the broad range of actual cases in the world, God has not chosen to secure the freedoms of those who are morally entitled to those freedoms by restricting others from exercising freedoms that they are not morally entitled to exercise. As a consequence, significant moral evil has resulted that could otherwise have been prevented. So, if God is justified in permitting such moral evils, it has to be on grounds other than freedom because an assessment of the freedoms that are at stake would require God to act preventively to secure a morally defensible distributions of freedom, which, of course, God has not done. So, if God is to be justified with respect to cases like Matthew Shepard’s, it must be because there is a justification for God’s inaction in terms other than freedom because of an assessment of the freedoms that are at stake would require God to act preventively to secure a morally defensible distribution of freedom, which of course, God has not done. It would have to be a justification for permitting moral evil on the grounds that it secures some other good or goods in this life or other goods in an afterlife. Now I am not contesting the possibility of that sort of justification for moral evil in our world here.33
5. A Compensatory Response to the Problem of Evil
“Suppose … there were among us persons with superhuman powers for making our societies more just than they are…like Superman, Wonder Woman, Spider-Man, and Xena … Would we not expect them to do what they can to make our societies more just than they are, and thereby bring about a better distribution of significant freedom?”36
I want to confess something: I do not find the problem of evil compelling. I think to myself: Here, during the blink of an eye, there are horrendous things happening. But there is infinitely long life afterwards if God exists. For all we know, the horrendous things are just a blip in these infinitely long lives. And it just doesn’t seem hard to think that over an infinite future that initial blip could be justified, redeemed, defeated, compensated for with moral adequacy, sublated, etc.45
They all have reasonable stories about how the permission of evils is needed for these goods. There is, in mind, only one question about these theodicies: Are these goods worth paying such a terrible price, the prices of allowing these horrors (horrendous evils)?46
First, the goods gained by soul building and free will last an infinite amount of time. It will forever be true that one has a soul that was built by these free choices. And the value of orderly laws of nature includes an order that is instrumental to soul building as well as aesthetically valuable in itself. The benefits of the former order last an eternity, and the beauty of the laws of nature—even as exhibited during the initial blink of an eye—last forever in memory. It is easy for an infinite duration of a significant good to be worth a very high price.Second, it is very easy for God to compensate people during an infinite future for any undeserved evils they suffered during the initial blip. And, typically, one has no (moral) obligation to prevent someone’s suffering when (a) the prevention would have destroyed an important good and (b) one will compensate the person to an extent much greater than the sufferings. The goods pointed out by the theodicies are important goods, even if we worry that permitting the horrors is too high a price. And no matter how terrible these short-term sufferings were—even if the short period of time, at most a century, “seemed like eternity”—infinite time is ample space for compensation.47
O Lord, our Lord,How majestic is Thy name in allthe earth,Who hast displayed Thy splendorabove the heavens!…When I consider Thy heavens,the work of Thy fingers,The moon and the stars, whichThou hast ordained;What is man, that Thou does takethought of him?And the son of man, that Thoudost care for him?48
For I consider that the sufferings of this present time are not worthy to be compared with the glory that is to be revealed to us. For the anxious longing of the creation waits eagerly for the revealing of the sons of God. For the creation was subject to futility, not of its own will, but because of Him who subjected it, in hope that creation itself also will be set free from its slavery to corruption into the freedom of the glory of the children of God. For we know that the whole creation groans and suffers the pains of childbirth together until now. And not only this, but also we ourselves, having the first fruits of the Spirit, even we ourselves groan within ourselves, waiting eagerly for our adoption as sons, the redemption of our body. For in hope we have saved, but hope that is seen is not hope; for why does one also hope for what he sees? But if we hope for what we do not see, with perseverance we wait eagerly for it … And we know that God causes all things to work together for good to those who love God, to those who are called according to his purposes.49
But we have this treasure in earthen vessels, that the surpassing greatness of the power of God and not from ourselves; we are afflicted in every way, but not crushed; perplexed, but not despairing; persecuted, but not forsaken; struck down, but not destroyed; always carrying about in the body the dying of Jesus, that the life of Jesus may be manifested in our body. For we who live are constantly being delivered over to death for Jesus’s sake, that the life of Jesus also may be manifested in our mortal flesh. So death works in us, but life in you. But having the same spirit of faith, according to what is written, “I BELIEVED; THEREFORE I SPOKE,” we also believe; therefore we speak; knowing that he who raised the Lord Jesus will raise us also with Jesus and will present us with you … Therefore we do not lose heart, but though our outer man is decaying, yet our inner man is being renewed day by day. For momentary, light affliction is producing for us an eternal weight of glory far beyond all comparison, while we look not at the things which are not seen; for the things which are seen are temporal, but the things which are not seen are eternal.50
This present universe is only one element in the kingdom of God. But it is a very wonderful and important one. And within it the Logos, the now risen Son of man, is currently preparing for us to join him (John 14.2-4). We will see him in the stunning surroundings that he had with the Father before the beginning of the created cosmos (John 17:24).We will not sit around looking at one another or at God for eternity but will join the eternal Logos, “reign with him,” in the endlessly ongoing creative work of God. It is for this that we were each individually intended, as both kings and priests (Exod. 19:6; Rev 5:10).Thus, our faithfulness over a “few things” in the present phase of our life develops the kind of character that can be entrusted with “many things.” We are, according, permitted to “enter into the joy of our Lord” (Matt. 25:21). That “joy” is, of course, the creation and care of what is good, in all its dimensions51
What then could God give those deprived of the opportunities for soul-making in this life? Well, then God could give them what we could call them, in contrast to the goods we have just considered, consumer goods, that is, experiences and activities that are intensely pleasurable, completely fulfilling, and all encompassing. Surely the beatific vision, which is said to involve ultimate communion or friendship with God, would presumably be the primary consumer good that would be experienced and enjoyed by those in the traditional heavenly afterlife.53
6. Conclusions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | |
2 | |
3 | |
4 | In the book, by “good God”, Sterba means a Being maximally perfect in knowledge, power, and moral goodness. |
5 | Some theists affirm that the assertion “God is the Good” is a metaphysical claim, which may or may not entail moral goodness. One such proponent is Robert Adams. See (R. Adams 1999, especially Chapter 1, pp. 13–49 and Chapter 2, pp. 50–82). |
6 | |
7 | |
8 | |
9 | For a rigorous defense of this position, see (Davies 2011, chapter six). |
10 | |
11 | |
12 | |
13 | |
14 | See, St. Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae 1.13.5 (Hause and Pasnau 2014). I am grateful to my colleague, Tom Ward, for suggesting this quote from Aquinas. It supports Ward’s contention that Aquinas’ view on analogy aligns decisively with Scotus’ view about how our language works when we speak about God and human beings. |
15 | |
16 | My insertion is to make explicit Lewis’ clear meaning of this paragraph. |
17 | |
18 | Of course, it is possible that the similarity between God and human beings is sufficient to ground analogous predications of goodness but not strong enough for univocity. Like Sterba, I accept the univocity thesis with respect to a wide range of moral properties asserted of both God and human beings. In doing so, both Sterba and I join Marilyn Adams and Richard Swinburne and the mainstream of the Christian theological tradition in accepting that God’s agency is personal, an agency that acts by thought and will. See (Swinburne 1979, pp. 22–50) and (M. M. Adams 1999, pp. 62–70; 80–82). |
19 | That is, the part of Divine Goodness that is moral goodness. |
20 | I regard Plantinga’s “free will defense” as having a limited but important usefulness in the discussion of the problem of evil. I accept Sterba’s rejection of the free will defense as an adequate response to horrendous evils. Of course, Plantinga never offered it as such. While Sterba devotes considerable attention to Marilyn McCord Adams’ treatment of the problem of evil in her (M. M. Adams 1999), it seems odd to me that he ignores or fails to address the central themes in (Stump 2010). |
21 | |
22 | That many of the dissenters to the Catholic and Protestant churches insisted on natural rights and a kind of political equality is no surprise since each of us bear the image of God. |
23 | I fear being misunderstood on this point. I do not mean to suggest that Christians do not think of God as analogous to a ruler or a king of a Kingdom. The Bible uses that imagery, not surprisingly, a great deal. My point is that that thinking of God governance of the Universe as analogous to the governance by the head of state of a political liberal democracy is an inadequate or misleading analogy. |
24 | Psalm 113:4–6, (Coogan 2010). |
25 | I affirm that God’s good will is directed not merely toward human beings to all God’s creation. After all, in Genesis 1:31, we find that God affirmed that all that God made was very good. An ethically provocative treatment of the implications of God’s affirmation of the goodness of the created order is found in “Shalom and the Community of Creation,” in (Woodley 2012, pp. 41–66). |
26 | Psalm 146: 7–9. |
27 | (M. M. Adams 1999, p. 26). This definition first appeared in her essay, “Horrendous Evils and the Goodness of God”, in (Adams and Adams 1990, pp. 209–21). |
28 | See (M. M. Adams 1999, p. 155). |
29 | Ibid., p. 156. |
30 | Ibid., pp. 155–56. |
31 | |
32 | Ibid., p. 21. |
33 | Ibid., pp. 23–24. |
34 | Ibid., p. 90. |
35 | Ibid., p. 49. |
36 | Ibid., p. 19. |
37 | Ibid., p. 20. |
38 | To the theist, the analogy will be at best limited, and, at worst, demeaning, a false analogy, and impious. |
39 | Perhaps we should be skeptical about how much we know about how much God intervenes to prevent evil, both ordinary and horrific evils. |
40 | |
41 | Ibid. On my reading of Sterba on this point, sometimes the provision of a new good overrides the Pauline Principle. More importantly, that when God permits evil, it is not God’s doing evil that good may come of it. God is not the agent doing evil. |
42 | See the text referenced by footnote 39, in which Sterba suggests that it is permissible for a new good to be a satisfactory response to some instances of evil. |
43 | In her rich and important book, Wandering in Darkness: Narrative and the Problem of Suffering, Eleonore Stump says, in comparing a possible world in which God permits suffering, hence evil, and a possible world in which God does not, that the former, her stories show, possess a “great compensatory beauty”. The compensatory beauty does not provide God, however, on Stump’s account, a morally sufficient reason for permitting the evils God in fact permits. It merely explains one reason why allowing or permitting moral evils is not a defeat for a good God. Both Stump and I are appealing to the concept of compensation or a compensatory aspect to God’s governance of the world. However, my use is somewhat different that Stump’s. However, I commend Professor Stump’s book to the reader, both for its profundity and for the ways in which it is an antidote to the notion that the existence of suffering, hence, moral evil, is incompatible with the existence of a good God (Stump 2010). |
44 | I first formulated something like this response in an unpublished paper called “The Problems of Evil”. In it, I addressed what I called the “existential problem of evil” and posed the possibility of a “delayed divine deliverance” from evil. |
45 | (Pruss 2017). |
46 | (Pruss 2017). |
47 | Ibid. |
48 | Psalm 8, (Coogan 1977). |
49 | Romans 8:18–25; 28, (Coogan 1977). |
50 | 2 Corinthians 4:7–14; 16–18, (Coogan 1977). |
51 | |
52 | |
53 | |
54 | See footnote 39. |
55 | |
56 | See also, James H. Cone, “The Meaning of Heaven in the Black Spirituals”, in (Cone 1992, pp. 78–96). In this chapter, he asks, “How was it possible for black people to endure the mental and physical stresses of slavery and still keep the humanity intact? I think the answer is found in their image of heaven”. |
References
- Adams, Marilyn McCord, and Robert Adams, eds. 1990. The Problem of Evil. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Adams, Marilyn McCord. 1999. Horrendous Evils and the Goodness of God. Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Adams, Robert. 1999. Finite and Infinite Goods: A Framework for Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Barth, Karl. 1957. Church Dogmatics. Edinburgh: T. & T. Clark. [Google Scholar]
- Cone, James H. 1992. The Spirituals and the Blues: An Interpretation. Maryknoll and New York: Orbis Books. [Google Scholar]
- Coogan, Michael D., ed. 2010. The New Oxford Annotated Bible, Fully Revised 4th ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Coogan, Michael D. 1977. Holy Bible: New American Standard. Edited by The Lockman Foundation Editorial Board. Nashville: Holman Bible Publishers. [Google Scholar]
- Davies, Brian. 1982. Introduction to the Philosophy of Religion. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Davies, Brian. 2006. The Reality of God and the Problem of Evil. London and New York: Continuum. [Google Scholar]
- Davies, Brian. 2011. Thomas Aquinas on God and Evil. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hause, Jeffrey, and Robert Pasnau, eds. 2014. Aquinas: The Basic Works. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company. [Google Scholar]
- Lewis, Clive Staples. 2001. A Grief Observed. New York: HarperCollins Publishers, Inc. [Google Scholar]
- Lewis, Clive Staples. 2005. The Chronicles of Narnia. New York: HarperCollins Publishers, Inc. [Google Scholar]
- Martin, Charles Burton. 1960. Religious Beliefs. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Pruss, Alexander R. 2017. The Blink of an Eye Response to the Problem of Evil. Available online: alexanderpruss.blogspot.com/2017/08/the-blink-of-eye-response-to-problem-of.html (accessed on 25 August 2017).
- Scotus, John Duns. 1987. “Duns Scotus.” Philosophical Writings: A Selection. Translated and Edited by Allan B. Wolter. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company. [Google Scholar]
- Sterba, James P. 2019. Is a Good God Logically Possible? Cham: Palgrave MacMillan. [Google Scholar]
- Stump, Eleonore. 2010. Wandering in Darkness: Narrative and the Problem of Suffering. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Swinburne, Richard. 1979. The Coherence of Theism. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ward, Thomas M. Forthcoming. Ordered by Love: An Introduction to John Duns Scotus. Brooklyn and New York: Angelico Press.
- Willard, Dallas. 1998. The Divine Conspiracy: Rediscovering Our Hidden Life in God. New York: HarperCollins Publishers Inc. [Google Scholar]
- Woodley, Randy S. 2012. Shalom and the Community of Creation: An Indigenous Vision. Grand Rapids: William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company. [Google Scholar]
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2021 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Beaty, M.D. A Compensatory Response to the Problem of Evil. Religions 2021, 12, 347. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel12050347
Beaty MD. A Compensatory Response to the Problem of Evil. Religions. 2021; 12(5):347. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel12050347
Chicago/Turabian StyleBeaty, Michael Douglas. 2021. "A Compensatory Response to the Problem of Evil" Religions 12, no. 5: 347. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel12050347
APA StyleBeaty, M. D. (2021). A Compensatory Response to the Problem of Evil. Religions, 12(5), 347. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel12050347