Aḥmad Amīn’s Rationalist Approach to the Qur’ān and Sunnah
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. The Revaluation of Muʿtazilism and the Role of Aḥmad Amīn
3. A Description of the Main Principles of Muʿtazilism
- The doctrine of the state between the two states (al-manzilah bayna al-manzilatayn), in other words anyone who commits a serious offence is neither an unbeliever (kāfir) nor a believer (mu’min), but a transgressor [of divine Law] (fāsiq), and the transgressor deserves Hell for his transgression. This doctrine was evoked by the fact that political clashes, from the killing of ʿUthmān (656) to the battle of the camel (657) and to that of Ṣiffīn (658)10, would lead people to wonder who was right and who was wrong, then from here to wonder if the person that was wrong was an unbeliever or a believer. The Khārijites (Levi Della Vida 2012) affirmed the unbelief of those who committed serious offences, the Murji’ites (Madelung 2012) considered them believers, al-Ḥasan al-Baṣrī (d. 728) (Ritter 2012) hypocrites (munāfiq) and Wāṣil [b. ʿAṭāʾ] (d. 748–749) (van Ess 2012b) declared them transgressors, a state between unbelief and faith, considering that they would forever remain in Hell.
- The doctrine of free will (qadar), [in other words] that God is not behind the actions of people, who instead are themselves solely responsible and for this reason will be rewarded or punished: it is only in this way that God deserves to be called “righteous”. It was probably the excesses of Jahm b. Ṣafwān11 and of his companions in stripping man of his power and making him into an inert body between whose hands actions slide as if over a rock that led them to this idea. It is in fact narrated that Wāṣil b. ʿAṭā’ sent some of his companions to Khurāsān to discuss and dispute with Jahm.
- The doctrine of unicity [of God] (tawḥīd), so they deny that God has eternal attributes, such as science (ʿilm), power (qudrah), life (ḥayāh), hearing (samʿ), sight (baṣar) etc., different from His essence. God [that is] would be knowing, powerful, seeing and hearing by His essence not by attributes that add to it. Asserting the existence of external attributes would in fact mean affirming the multiplicity (taʿaddud), while God is One, does not have associates of any type and has absolutely no kind of plurality (kathrah) in His essence. Therefore these interpret allegorically the verses of the Qur’ān that establish these attributes and from which it is possible to infer that He has attributes that are similar to those of the created beings. Most probably, these were pushed to profess this doctrine because of a wide-spread conviction of their time, in which many, such as Muqātil b. Sulaymān (d. 767) (Plessner and Rippin 2012), who was a contemporary of Wāsil, affirmed the corporeality (tajsīd) of God Almighty and they claimed that He had attributes like those of the created beings12.
- The statement of the authority of reason and of its capacity to recognise good and evil, even if no revealed text (sharʿ) has been received on the matter and [that for which] each thing has an attribute that makes it something good or evil; […] religious law does not make a thing good by commanding it and an evil one by prohibiting it, quite the opposite. It commands a thing because it is good and prohibits another because it is evil and could not do the opposite because the command and the prohibition are the consequence of the good and of the evil of the thing in itself. [The Muʿtazilites] were probably moved to assume this principle because they realised that some people attributed excessive value to the transmitted ḥadīth and fixated on them (mā ra’ū min mughālāt qawm wa-jumūdi-him ʿalā mā warada min ḥadīth), even if they were false, and relied on the text (wa-wuqūfi-him ʿinda al-naṣṣ) and, as such, if they didn’t find a text, they didn’t express an opinion. We saw this tendency when we spoke about the school of the ḥadīth. The Muʿtazilites perceived the danger stemming from an intellectual stalemate of this type and established this principle. For this reason, ḥadīth13 scholars were, among the creatures of God, those who most hated the Muʿtazilites and vice-versa: when the State, at the time of al-Ma’mūn (813–833) and al-Muʿtaṣim (833–842), was in favour of the Muʿtazilites, they imparted a hard lesson to the people of ḥadīth on the occasion of the rift (fitnah) on the [matter of the] creation of the Qur’ān and, when the State withdrew its support, it was the traditionists (muḥaddithūn) who taught them a lesson (Patton 1897; Caspar 1957, pp. 144–56; Martin et al. [1997] 2016, pp. 47–48; Demichelis 2012; Amīn 2011b, pp. 320–21).
4. Criticism of the ḥadīth
The absence of transcription of the ḥadīth in the early days in a specific book, the entrusting to memory and the difficulty in distinguishing what God’s Messenger had said or done over a period of twenty-three years from the start of the Revelation to his death, [all these aspects] resulted in some fabricating the ḥadīth and falsely attributing them to God’s Messenger. This must have already occurred at the time of the Prophet, as it is a ḥadīth that proclaims “Who attributes falsehood to me, may he have his place in Hell!” which leads to the notion that it had been uttered on the occasion of an event in which falsehood was attributed to the Prophet. After the death of God’s Messenger, it became easier to lie and more difficult to verify facts […]. Then when the conquests took place and numerous people of the conquered nations entered Islam, such as the Persians, Byzantines, Berbers, Egyptians and Syrians, including those whose faith was not particular deep-seated, falsification increased prodigiously and the river flowed until the villages were submerged. […] To give an idea of the level of falsification that was reached, just think that the ḥadīth relating to the Qur’ānic exegesis—of which Aḥmad b. Ḥanbal (d. 855) (Holtzman 2009) stated that none was genuine—numbered thousands and that the work of al-Bukhārī (d. 870) (Melchert 2012), that includes approximately seven thousand ḥadīth, of which around three thousand are repetitions, is the result of a choice that he made starting from six hundred thousand ḥadīth who were travelling around in his time.
[…] The falsifiers were led to do so for various reasons:1. Political conflicts: the conflicts between ʿAlī (d. 661) and Abū Bakr (d. 634), between ʿAlī and Muʿāwiyah (d. 680), between ʿAbd Allāh b. Zubayr (d. 692) and ʿAbd al-Malik (d. 705), then between Umayyads and Abbasids (Laoust 1977, pp. 1–83), all these were the cause of the fabrication of many ḥadīth […]. It can then be noted, reading them, that many ḥadīth were clearly falsified to support or belittle Umayyads, Abbasids or Alids […]. Related to these are the ḥadīth that were falsified to celebrated the Arab tribes because these tribes competed for power, glory and honour and, as such, found in the creation of the ḥadīth a gateway to pride where [previously] they had found it in poetry […]. And how many ḥadīth were falsified to emphasise the superiority of the Arabs over the Persians and Byzantines and to which they opposed falsified ḥadīth to show the superiority of the Persians, the Byzantines, the Abyssinians and the Turks […]!2. The theological and legal controversies: the theologians for example had different ideas on free will (qadar) or predestination (jabr), and some took the liberty of supporting their doctrine by means of falsified ḥadīth, in which they also reported tiny details that the Messenger would not normally address, even going so far as to mention the name of the adverse faction or even the name of its head and cursing both. Similarly, in the law (fiqh) there is no branch in which there is no ḥadīth to support this and one to support that. Even the books of the school of Abū Ḥanīfah (d. 767) (Yanagihashi 2007)—of which the ʿulamā’ state that he considered [only] very few ḥadīth to be genuine, seventeen according to Ibn Khaldūn (d. 1406) (Cheddadi 2018)—are filled with countless ḥadīth, and at times with reports that more resemble legal texts, but it would take up too much page space to present some examples of these, for which the fact is simply alluded to.3. The propensity of some, who called themselves “scholars”, to comply with the wishes of rulers and caliphs, for whom they fabricated ḥadīth in order to please them, in the hope of obtaining something from them in return […].4. The adaptations that some made, in the field of virtue, encouragement, intimidation, etc., in cases where what was unlawful could not be lawful or what was lawful was unlawful. In this way they falsified ḥadīth in this sphere and filled the books of ḥadīth with the virtues of people, even of those that the Prophet had never seen, such as Wahb b. Munabbih (d. 728 or 732) (Khoury 2012), or with the merits of the Qur’ānic verses and suras […].5. But one of the most important causes of the falsification seems to me to be the fact that people were excessively driven not to accept knowledge unless it was firmly linked to the Book and to the Sunnah, instead disregarding any other. The rules of what constituted lawful and unlawful based solely on individual reasoning (ijtihād) did not have [for them] the same value as those based on ḥadīth or on other similar sources. Many ʿulamā’ of the time even ended up rejecting and considering them [=the rules based solely on ijtihād] worthless and some even insulted those who advocated them.
The ʿulamā’ had established rules for [the discipline of the] impugning and accrediting (al-jarḥ wa-l-taʿdīl) that it is not possible to recall here but—quite honestly—they gave more importance to the criticism of the chain of transmitters (isnād) than to the criticism of the text (matn). It is very rare to find a criticism that states that a sentence attributed to the Prophet does not agree with the circumstances in which it would have been said or that the established historical circumstances contradict it, or that the ḥadīth contains a sort of philosophical expression that contradicts the usual manner of expression of the Prophet, or that the ḥadīth more resembles, in the conditions and in the obligations [that it poses], the legal texts and so on. In this context, we have not found in them even a tenth of the attention that they dedicated to the impugning and accrediting of people, to the point that we see the same al-Bukhārī, despite his value and his precision in research, confirming ḥadīth that the passing of time and the experimental observation have proved not to be genuine, for example the ḥadīth “In a hundred years, no living being will remain on the earth” […].
5. The Dependence on the Textual Datum as an Obstacle to the Reform of Islam
The Muʿtazilites affirmed the authority of reason in the knowledge of good and evil, [saying that] good is not an imposition of things by God and neither is this the case with evil. In other words, it is not the fact that God commands a thing to make it good, nor is it the case that He prohibits it to make it evil. Quite the opposite. God commands a thing because it is good in itself and prohibits another thing because it is evil in itself. In the nature of things, there are in fact attributes that make them good and attributes that make them evil, and the mind is able to recognise these natural characteristics to distinguish good and evil—and in this principle, there is undoubtedly a liberation of reason from immobility (al-jumūd) and from the reliance on texts (al-wuqūf ʿinda al-nuṣūṣ). The legislator can in fact exercise reason on anything that is not mentioned in a text in order to be able to distinguish good from evil, to establish what is lawful and what is prohibited. The procedure is not limited to analogy (qiyās), but research is possible: if there is no foundation that is comparable to the thing, good and evil can be weighed and thus allow recognition of the nature of that thing. It could be said that it is measured by the yardstick of justice and then judged as something that must be done or not. In this way, when the Muʿtazilite was a jurist, this principle made him freer; indeed, it was probably the flowing of Muʿtazilism into Ḥanafism that was one of the reasons that led the Ḥanafites to put their faith in the use of the personal opinion (ra’y) in their school, given that to consider that good and evil are rationally qualifiable involves freedom of opinion and the use of reason in making judgements. […] Similarly, when the Muʿtazilites were engaged in ethics, they didn’t confine themselves to the limits of commands and prohibitions, instead weighing the virtues and vices with the balance of time, of the setting and so on, striving (yajtahidu) to define ethics themselves as their colleagues strove in the field of law.
Probably, before the Muʿtazilites, Islamic history had never been witness to such a complete philosophical doctrine on God, on His attributes and on His acts, based on rational proof and revealed arguments, as was the case with the Muʿtazilites. They gave to reason the freedom to move through the research into all these matters without being hindered by anyone, therefore they allowed research to be conducted on the heavens and on the Earth, on God and on man, on what is modest and what is majestic. It does not have a defined space in which it has the right to move and one in which it is prohibited from doing so, rather reason was created for the purposes of knowing and with the capability of knowing every thing, even that which is beyond nature and matter. Indeed, their research into metaphysics was broader and more in-depth that than into nature, given that they were religious reformers and defenders of the faith.
Their vision of the unicity of God was a vision of the highest level and transcendence. They applied to the phrase of the Most High «Nothing is similar to Him» (Q. 42:11) the most innovative application, they expounded it in the tiniest of details in the best ways possible, they countered the mediocre points of view such as those of the corporalists (mujassimah) who presented God as a body with a face, hands, eyes, flesh and blood. […] So the Muʿtazilites came and raised themselves above these opinions, they understood from the spirit of the Qur’ān that God was devoid of matter, therefore they proceeded to a thorough and wide exegesis, allegorically interpreted what contradicted this principle and logically linked their doctrines. […] From the rational point of view, they dared, decided with courage and audacity the road to be followed, in relation to the transmitted data (naql) they accepted what agreed with the rational proof and allegorically interpreted what contradicted it. It was reason that ruled over the ambiguous verses (āyāt mutashābihah) and among the ḥadīth to determine their interpretability or inauthenticity if they disagreed with reason.
Their vision of the justice of God was in a similar vein. They found themselves addressing the problem of reward and punishment and they realised that they had no meaning unless the free will of man was established, [affirming] that he is the creator of his actions, that he can do or not do something; that, whether he does or does not do something is his choice, therefore his reward or his punishment are reasonable and just. But if God creates man and compels him to act in a certain way, then He compels the obedient to obey and the disobedient to disobey, then He punishes the latter and rewards the other, and therefore there is no justice in anything. Perhaps their weak point is that they pushed themselves excessively in comparing the invisible and the visible, I mean in comparing God to man, and in subjecting God Almighty to the laws of this world. They imposed on God, for example, justice as it is perceived by man and as a worldly system, and they overlooked the fact that the meaning of “justice”—even in this world—is a relative meaning whose perception changes with the passage of time, and that what was understood as justice in the Middle Ages, today is considered an injustice, without even considering what it would be like moving from this world to that of God! […] The same can be said of their doctrine of the attributes of God if these are identical or not to God. All their evidence is based on comparing the invisible and the visible, but the similarity is non-existent; they presumed that identity and otherness, temporality and spatiality, cause and effect, etc., were necessary laws for each existing thing and this, in my opinion, is absolutely wrong. These in fact are human laws and, if we want to be a little indulgent, we could say that they are laws of this, our world, and that we cannot know if they apply or not to another world. Passing judgement on God in the conviction that it is universal law, for man and for God, is an audacity that doesn’t sit well with reason. [The reason indeed] knows his power and does not go beyond his limits. This was not only an error of the Muʿtazilites but also of the theologians who would come after them.
But, in any case, the path of the Muʿtazilites was inevitable, because it was a reaction to the state of certain beliefs of their time. They established the authority of reason, pushing it to the extreme before those who did not recognise them authority and even said: let’s stop at the text (naqifu ʿinda al-naṣṣ), therefore what is established (muḥkam) and clear (wāḍiḥ) we learn, that which is ambiguous (mutashābih) and obscure (ghāmiḍ) we leave to the knowledge of God. The Muʿtazilites argued in favour of free will, pushing it to the far limit before those people who had robbed man of his free will, until making it like a feather in the wind or like a piece of wood in the open sea. In my opinion, the error in affirming the authority of reason and the free will and the extremism in both [the doctrines] is better than the extremism in opposing doctrines. For me, if the teachings of Muʿtazilism prevailed among the Muslims in these two matters—I mean the authority of reason and free will—from the Muʿtazilite era to today, Muslims would have had another position in history, different from the current one, in which they have been made powerless by submission (taslīm), inactive by dependence (tawākul) and paralysed by predestination (jabr).
It is right to say that in each of the two fields [= of the Muʿtazilites and of the traditionists] there were those who were faithful to their belief. I believe that persons, such as al-Ma’mūn (d. 833) (Rekaya 2012), al-Wāthiq (d. 847) (Zetterstéen et al. 2012) and Aḥmad b. Abī Du’ād (d. 854) (Zetterstéen and Pellat 2012), were sincere in their opinions: they believed that what they said was the truth and I agree with them, that it was the truth, even if I do not agree with them [in believing] that each truth should be told to each human being, in the same way that I do not agree with them in [choosing to] force people to say what I believe to be the truth.
It would have been better for the Muslims not to let Muʿtazilites into the web of power and made them live as they had done at the time of al-Manṣūr (754–775) and in the initial phase of that of al-Ma’mūn; if they had followed this road and if the traditionists had followed theirs, the Muslims would have benefitted greatly from it and the history of Islam would have been wholly different. The faction of the Muʿtazilites represents the liberal party and that of the traditionists the conservative party. The fact of there being two parties is in the interest of the nation: the Muʿtazilites push people to use reason and free thought, they guide them with their torches and lights that light up the street before them; the traditionists guard customs and inherited traditions, they cling on to the tails of the Muʿtazilites, preventing them from being careless on the way and thus risking becoming lost. In this way the nation will proceed along the path without obstacles but always advancing. Paving the way for only one of the two sects and losing the other is extremely damaging.
When the light of the Muʿtazilites went out, the people fell under the rule of the traditionists and of their peers, the jurists, and remained under this domination from the time of al-Mutawakkil (847–861) until almost the present day. The result was a total immobilism (jumūd). The science of the scholar (ʿālim) consisted of memorising the ḥadīth and thus transmitting them as he had heard them, explaining them from a linguistic point of view and commenting on the transmitters as those of ancient times once did: this is worthy of faith, this is weak, without any rational criticism; the right of the jurist (faqīh) consisted of narrating the pronouncements of the previous imām and, if a new question was posed, the greatest effort of the mujtahid was invested in deriving it from the principles of his imām. […] All were subject to the command of al-Mutawakkil to «submit and imitate» (al-taslīm wa-l-taqlīd), all were without personality, because personality is the enemy of submission and of imitation. If Muʿtazilism had remained, Muslims would have been bearers of better tendencies than they actually were.
When the position of the Muʿtazilites weakened after the miḥnah, the Muslims remained under the influence of the party of conservatives for around a thousand years, until the modern Renaissance (nahḍah). In fact, there is a tendency in it that is typical of Muʿtazilism, there is doubt and experience, which are two methods of Muʿtazilism, as had been seen in al-Naẓẓām (d. between 835 and 845) (van Ess 2012c) and al-Jāḥiẓ (d. 869) (Pellat 2012); there is the faith in authority of reason and in free will; in other words, man creates his own actions and as a result is responsible for them; there is freedom to debate, research and dispute; there is the awareness of man of his own personality, the not entrusting to destiny of each consequence and responsibility, and much more besides. They are all principles—as we have seen—that are professed and practised by the Muʿtazilites. Perhaps the only difference between the teachings of the Muʿtazilites and that of the modern Renaissance is that the Muʿtazilite teachings of these principles were based on religion, while those of the modern Renaissance are based on pure reason; in other words, the Muʿtazilites considered these principles religious while the modern Renaissance considers them rational.
In my opinion, one of the greatest disasters for the Muslims was the death of the Muʿtazilites, who committed a crime against themselves.
6. Conclusions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | To use just a few examples, Robert Caspar defines the trilogy as a work that successfully achieved the goal determined by the author, namely that of “offrir à l’ensemble du monde arabe un tableau de son histoire intellectuelle conforme aux exigences de la méthode moderne” (Caspar 1957, p. 181); Emmanuelle Perrin describes it as “le premier travail de recherche critique sur la formation de la culture islamique” (Perrin 2002) and Efraim Barak refers to it as “the first attempt by a Muslim writer to research Islamic history using scientific tools” (Barak 2007, p. 295). |
2 | As far as we can ascertain, no Western scholar has ever translated either the trilogy or even part of it. The only translation that we are aware of is that of the first book, Fajr al-Islām, published in French under the title, L’aube de l’Islam by a small Algerian publishing house (Amin 2013). We are currently preparing an anthological translation in Italian of passages selected from the trilogy for the series, Traduzioni, studi e ricerche sulla nahḍah of the Istituto per l’Oriente Carlo Alfonso Nallino. |
3 | A short but useful overview of the vision of Muʿtazilism of the author can be found in (Caspar 1957, pp. 180–84) and is resumed and in part reworked by (Khālid 1969). |
4 | Detlev Khālid highlights that this revaluation already had its roots in the XVIII century in India with Shāh Walī Allāh al-Dihlawī (1703–1762), to then become more organic and explicit during the following century thanks to a younger contemporary of ʿAbduh, Sayyid Aḥmad Khān (1817–1898) (Khālid 1969, p. 321 and p. 323). On the role of Sayyid Aḥmad Khān, see also (Malik 1980). In general, as summarized by (Demichelis 2010, p. 411), the rediscovery of rationalism before ‘Abduh can be found in many other authors such as Khayr al-Dīn (1820–1889) and al-Afghānī (1838–1897). It is true, however, that the role of ʿAbduh in this matter was central, especially for Aḥmad Amīn. |
5 | The discovery of Muʿtazilite manuscripts only began after his death. |
6 | In subsequent editions, the page in question would be removed following the controversy it aroused (Abū Zayd 1995, p. 202). |
7 | All online sources were consulted on 18 January 2022. |
8 | The reference is to the following editions: (Amīn 2011b, 2011c) for Fajr al-Islām and Ḍuḥā al-Islām and (Amīn 2013) for Ẓuhr al-Islām. In the latter, the part dedicated to Muʿtazilism is found in the fourth volume, the one that was published for the first time posthumously in 1955. |
9 | Following his research and independently from the results reached by the Italian orientalist Nallino, Aḥmad Amīn arrived at his same conclusions, considering that the name, muʿtazilah did not originate from the idea of a “secession” from orthodoxy, but from the idea of “abstention” from taking a stance regarding the legal qualification of the sinner. The name, in fact, had been chosen or attributed originally to the group of people who adopted a “neutral” approach with respect to the clash between the partisans of ʿAlī and those of ʿUthmān (Amīn 2011b, pp. 311–20; Nallino 1916, pp. 442–54). |
10 | On these events and more generally on political events in the period from the death of the prophet Muḥammad (632) to that of ʿAlī (661), see the useful summary contained in (Crone 2004, pp. 17–20). |
11 | This was an ancient theologian, presumed founder of the sect of the so-called “jahmites”, who adhered to an extreme form of the doctrine of jabr (predestination), considering that man acts only metaphorically, as the sun “acts” when it sets (Watt 2012b). There is no definite information on Jahm, only that it was the secretary of al-Ḥārith b. Surayj who rebelled against the Umayyads and, between 734 and 746, controlled a number of areas of eastern Khurāsān. Jahm was killed in 746, shortly before the same al-Ḥārith (Watt 2012c). |
12 | The reference here is to the “popular view of God among traditionalist Muslims, who took Quranic statements about God literally”. For example, the Qur’ān “describes God seated on a throne, having a face, seeing with His eyes; therefore God must have a body. […] Those who held such a view of God—and many of the ahl al-hadith and other traditionalists did—were labelled by the mutakallimun as the Mushabbiha, the purveyors of anthropomorphism (tashbih) and as the Mujassima, those who embodied God (tajsim)” (Martin et al. [1997] 2016, p. 96). See also (Strothmann 2012). |
13 | We will use the more common singular form ḥadīth for both singular and plural senses of the term. |
14 | In this regard, see the definitions of jamada and jumūd in the main classical and modern lexicons and dictionaries, available on the website http://arabiclexicon.hawramani.com accessed on 18 January 2022, in particular those contained in (Lane 1863; Ibn Manẓūr 1955–1956). |
15 | In his autobiography, Aḥmad Amīn dedicates much space to the criticism of the teaching methods of al-Azhar, especially in chapter IX (Amīn 2011a, pp. 49–54; Borruso 1980). In an article in 1951, entitled “If I were the shaykh of al-Azhar”, he also explains how he would reform this historic institution (Perrin 2002). |
16 | On the Muʿtazilite principle of the tawḥīd and the consequent interpretation of the created Qur’ān, see also the presentation of Gardet and Anawati in their Introduction à la théologie musulmane, as it is very much based on the trilogy of Aḥmad Amīn (Gardet and Anawati 1970, pp. 47–49). |
17 | He writes on the matter, “This is clearly an invalid affirmation produced from a limited mind and from an unhealthy vision” (Amīn 2011c, p. 717). |
18 | On the different definitions, interpretations and problems related to the label of “neo-Muʿtazilism” and its application to some intellectuals, including Muḥammad Arkūn and Naṣr Ḥāmid Abū Zayd, see: Caspar 1957, pp. 199–201; Khālid 1969; Gardet 1972; Schoen 1976, pp. 132–38; Martin et al. [1997] 2016, pp. 256–59; Hildebrandt 2007; Demichelis 2010; Campanini 2012, pp. 48–49. |
References
- (al-)Ashʿarī, Abū-l-Ḥasan ʿAlī b. Ismāʿīl. 1929–1930. Kitāb maqālāt al-islāmiyyīn wa ikhtilāf al-muṣallīn. Edited by Hellmut Ritter. Istanbul: Devlet Matbaasi. [Google Scholar]
- (al-)Khayyāṭ, Abū-l-Ḥusayn ʿAbd al-Raḥīm b. Muḥammad b. ʿUthmān. 1925. Kitāb al-intiṣār wa-l-radd ʿalā Ibn al-Rawandī al-mulḥid. Edited with an Introduction by Henrik Samuel Nyberg. Cairo: Dār al-kutub al-miṣriyya. [Google Scholar]
- Abū Zayd, Naṣr. 1995. al-Tafkīr fī zaman al-takfīr. Cairo: Maktabat Madbūlī. [Google Scholar]
- Amīn, Aḥmad. 2011a. Ḥayātī. Cairo: Mu’assasat Hindāwī li-l-taʿlīm wa-l-thaqāfah. [Google Scholar]
- Amīn, Aḥmad. 2011b. Fajr al-Islām. Cairo: Mu’assasat Hindāwī li-l-taʿlīm wa-l-thaqāfah. [Google Scholar]
- Amīn, Aḥmad. 2011c. Ḍuḥā al-Islām. Cairo: Mu’assasat Hindāwī li-l-taʿlīm wa-l-thaqāfah. [Google Scholar]
- Amin, Ahmad. 2013. L’aube de l’Islam. Traduction de l’arabe et notes par Ahmida Mimouni. Préface par Tahar Gaïd. Algiers: Editions Mimouni. [Google Scholar]
- Amīn, Aḥmad. 2013. Ẓuhr al-Islām. Cairo: Mu’assasat Hindāwī li-l-taʿlīm wa-l-thaqāfah. [Google Scholar]
- Amin, Hussein Ahmad. 2018. The Sorrowful Muslim’s Guide. Translated by Yasmin Amin, and Nesrin Amin. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Barak, Efraim. 2007. Ahmad Amin and Nationalism. Middle Eastern Studies 43: 295–310. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Borruso, Andrea. 1980. Aḥmad Amīn e l’Azhar. Oriente Moderno 60: 69–77. [Google Scholar]
- Campanini, Massimo. 2012. The Muʿtazila in Islamic History and Thought. Religion Compass 6: 41–50. Available online: https://www.academia.edu/20278182/The_Mu_tazila_in_Islamic_History_and_Thought (accessed on 18 January 2022). [CrossRef]
- Caspar, Robert. 1957. Un aspect de la pensée musulmane moderne: Le renouveau du moʿtazilisme. MIDEO: Mélanges de l’Institut dominicain d’études orientales du Caire 4: 141–202. Available online: https://alkindi.ideo-cairo.org/append_pdf/iu439.pdf/66523 (accessed on 18 January 2022).
- Cheddadi, Abdesselam. 2018. Ibn Khaldūn, ʿAbd al-Raḥmān. In Encyclopaedia of Islam, 3rd ed. online. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Crone, Patricia. 2004. God’s Rule: Government and Islam. New York: Columbia University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Demichelis, Marco. 2010. New-Muʿtazilite Theology in the Contemporary Age. The Relationship between Reason, History and Tradition. Oriente Moderno 2: 411–26. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Demichelis, Marco. 2012. The Miḥna. Deconstruction and reconsideration of the Muʿtazilite role in the “Inquisition”. Annali di Scienze Religiose 5: 257–86. Available online: https://fr.art1lib.org/book/39511094/2cbe9d (accessed on 18 January 2022). [CrossRef]
- Elsadda, Hoda. 2007. Amīn, Qāsim. In Encyclopaedia of Islam, 3rd ed. online. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Esposito, John L., ed. 2003. Taqlid. In The Oxford Dictionary of Islam. Oxford Reference Online. New York: Oxford University Press, Available online: https://www-oxfordreference-com.ezproxy.unibo.it/view/10.1093/acref/9780195125580.001.0001/acref-9780195125580-e-2339 (accessed on 18 January 2022).
- Gardet, Louis, and Marie-Marcel Anawati. 1970. Introduction à la Théologie Musulmane. Essai de Théologie Comparée. Seconde édition corrigée. Paris: Librairie Philosophique J. Vrin. [Google Scholar]
- Gardet, Louis. 1972. Signification du ‘renouveau muʿtazilite’ dans la pensée musulmane contemporaine. In Islamic Philosophy and the Classical Tradition. Essays Presented by His Friends and Pupils to Richard Walzer on His Seventieth Birthday. Edited by Samuel Miklos Stern, Albert Hourani and Vivian Brown. Oxford: Cassirer, pp. 63–75. [Google Scholar]
- Gershoni, Israel. 2019. Luṭfī al-Sayyid, Aḥmad. In Encyclopaedia of Islam, 3rd ed. online. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hildebrandt, Thomas. 2007. Between Muʿtazilism and Mysticism. How much of a Muʿtazilite is Naṣr Ḥāmid Abū Zayd? In A Common Rationality: Muʿtazilism in Islam and Judaism. Edited by Camilla Adang Sabine Schmidtke and David Sklare. Würzburg: Ergon, pp. 495–512. [Google Scholar]
- Holtzman, Livnat. 2009. Aḥmad b. Ḥanbal. In Encyclopaedia of Islam, 3rd ed. online. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ibn Manẓūr, Muḥammad ibn Mukarram. 1955–1956. J-m-d. In Lisān al-ʿarab. Beirut: Dār Ṣādir, Available online: http://arabiclexicon.hawramani.com/search/%D8%AC%D9%85%D9%88%D8%AF?cat=3 (accessed on 18 January 2022).
- Khālid, Detlev. 1969. Some aspects of neo-Muʿtazilism. Islamic Studies 8: 319–47. [Google Scholar]
- Khoury, Raif Georges. 2012. Wahb b. Munabbih. In Encyclopaedia of Islam, 2nd ed. online. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kraus, Paul, and George Vajda. 2012. Ibn al-Rāwandī or al-Rēwendī. In Encyclopaedia of Islam, 2nd ed. online. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar]
- Lane, Edward William. 1863. J-m-d. In An Arabic-English Lexicon. London: Williams & Norgate, Available online: http://arabiclexicon.hawramani.com/search/%D8%AC%D9%85%D9%88%D8%AF?cat=50 (accessed on 18 January 2022).
- Laoust, Henri. 1977. Les Schismes dans l’Islam. Introduction à une étude de la Religion Musulmane. Paris: Payot. [Google Scholar]
- Levi Della Vida, Giorgio. 2012. K̲h̲ārid̲j̲ites. In Encyclopaedia of Islam, 2nd ed. online. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Madelung, Wilfred. 2012. Murd̲j̲iʾa. In Encyclopaedia of Islam, 2nd ed. online. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Malik, Hafeez. 1980. Sir Sayyid Ahmad Khan and Muslim Modernization in India e Pakistan. New York: Columbia University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Martin, Richard C. 2015. Createdness of the Qurʾān. In Encyclopaedia of Islam, 3rd ed. online. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Martin, Richard C., Mark R. Woodward, and Dwi S. Atmaja. 2016. Defenders of Reason in Islam. Muʿtazilism from Medieval School to Modern Symbol, ebook ed. London: Oneworld Publications. First published in 1997. [Google Scholar]
- Melchert, Christopher. 2012. al-Bukhārī. In Encyclopaedia of Islam, 3rd ed. online. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Nallino, Carlo Alfonso. 1916. Sull’origine del nome dei Muʿtaziliti. Rivista degli studi orientali 7: 429–54. [Google Scholar]
- Patton, Walter M. 1897. Aḥmed ibn Ḥanbal and the Miḥna. Leiden: Brill, Available online: https://archive.org/details/AhmedIbnHanbalAndTheMihna_712 (accessed on 18 January 2022).
- Pellat, Charles. 2012. al-D̲j̲āḥiẓ. In Encyclopaedia of Islam, 2nd ed. online. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Perrin, Emmanuelle. 2002. Le creuset et l’orfèvre: Le parcours d’Ahmad Amîn (1886–1954). Revue des Mondes Musulmans et de la Méditerranée, 95–98. Available online: http://journals.openedition.org/remmm/238 (accessed on 18 January 2022). [CrossRef]
- Plessner, Martin, and Andrew Rippin. 2012. Muḳātil b. Sulaymān. In Encyclopaedia of Islam, 2nd ed. online. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rekaya, Mohamed. 2012. al-Maʾmūn. In Encyclopaedia of Islam, 2nd ed. online. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ritter, Hellmut. 2012. Ḥasan al-Baṣrī. In Encyclopaedia of Islam, 2nd ed. online. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Schoen, Ulrich. 1976. Determination und Freiheit im arabischen Denken heute. Eine christliche Reflexion im Gespräch mit Naturwissenschaften und Islam. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck und Ruprecht. [Google Scholar]
- Strothmann, Rudolf. 2012. Tas̲h̲bīh. In Encyclopaedia of Islam, 1st ed. online. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- van Ess, Josef. 2012a. al-K̲h̲ayyāṭ. In Encyclopaedia of Islam, 2nd ed. online. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- van Ess, Josef. 2012b. Wāṣil b. ʿAṭāʾ. In Encyclopaedia of Islam, 2nd ed. online. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- van Ess, Josef. 2012c. al-Naẓẓām. In Encyclopaedia of Islam, 2nd ed. online. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Von Kügelgen, Anke. 2008. ʿAbd al-Rāziq, Muṣṭafā. In Encyclopaedia of Islam, 3rd ed. online. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Watt, W. Montgomery. 2012a. al-As̲h̲ʿarī, Abu ’l-Ḥasan. In Encyclopaedia of Islam, 2nd ed. online. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Watt, W. Montgomery. 2012b. D̲j̲ahmiyya. In Encyclopaedia of Islam, 2nd ed. online. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Watt, W. Montgomery. 2012c. Ḏj̲ahm b. Ṣafwān. In Encyclopaedia of Islam, 2nd ed. online. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Yanagihashi, Hiroyuki. 2007. Abū Ḥanīfa. In Encyclopaedia of Islam, 3rd ed. online. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Zetterstéen, Karl Vilhelm, and Charles Pellat. 2012. Aḥmad b. Abī Duʾād. In Encyclopaedia of Islam, 2nd ed. online. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Zetterstéen, Karl Vilhelm, Clifford Edmund Bosworth, and Emeri van Donzel. 2012. al-Wāt̲h̲iḳ Bi ’llāh. In Encyclopaedia of Islam, 2nd ed. online. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2022 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Peta, I. Aḥmad Amīn’s Rationalist Approach to the Qur’ān and Sunnah. Religions 2022, 13, 234. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13030234
Peta I. Aḥmad Amīn’s Rationalist Approach to the Qur’ān and Sunnah. Religions. 2022; 13(3):234. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13030234
Chicago/Turabian StylePeta, Ines. 2022. "Aḥmad Amīn’s Rationalist Approach to the Qur’ān and Sunnah" Religions 13, no. 3: 234. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13030234
APA StylePeta, I. (2022). Aḥmad Amīn’s Rationalist Approach to the Qur’ān and Sunnah. Religions, 13(3), 234. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13030234