Sterba’s Logical Argument from Evil and the God Who Walks Away from Omelas
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Sterba’s Logical Argument from Evil
- Necessarily, if God exists, then God does not intentionally permit horrendous evils caused by immoral actions.
- Necessarily, if God exists and there are horrendous evils caused by immoral actions, then God intentionally permits horrendous evils caused by immoral actions.
- So: necessarily, if God exists, then there are no horrendous evils caused by immoral actions.
- However, there are horrendous evils caused by immoral actions.
- Therefore, God does not exist.2
It is immoral to intentionally engage in non-trivial evil so that good may come of it.
It is immoral to intentionally engage in non-trivial evil in order to attain some good or to prevent some evil.
Pauline Principle: It is immoral for God to intentionally permit horrendous evil caused by immoral actions in order to attain some good or to prevent some evil.
3. A Weakness in Sterba’s Argument
Weakened Pauline Principle: It is immoral for God to intentionally permit horrendous evil caused by immoral acts in order to attain some good (unless that good vastly outweighs the horrendous evil and can be attained in no other way) or to prevent some evil (unless that evil vastly outweighs the horrendous evil and can be prevented in no other way).
Suppose parents you know were to permit their children to be brutally assaulted to make possible the soul-making of the person who would attempt to comfort their children after they have been assaulted or to make possible the soul-making that their children themselves could experience by coming to forgive their assailants. Would you think the parents were morally justified in so acting? Hardly. Here you surely would agree with the Pauline Principle’s prohibition of such actions.
[I]ntimate relationship to God is an incommensurable good…A loving relationship with God is the greatest possible good and the loss of this relationship is the worst possible evil…this supreme good is incommensurate not only with other goods, but also with evils. There is simply no way to compare or measure the joy of this supreme good with finite goods or evils. The beauty and goodness of God as experienced “up close” is of such incomparable value that it will utterly swamp any evils we might have experienced.
[God] really does want to fill the universe with a lot of loathsome little replicas of Himself—creatures whose life, on its miniature scale, will be qualitatively like His own, not because He has absorbed them but because their wills freely conform to His…But you now see that the Irresistible and the Indisputable are the two weapons which the very nature of His scheme forbids Him to use. Merely to override a human will…would be for Him useless.
For human beings to cooperate with God in this rescue operation, they must know that they need to be rescued. They must know what it means to be separated from him. And what it means to be separated from God is to live in a world of horrors. If God simply ‘‘canceled’’ all the horrors of this world by an endless series of miracles, he would thereby frustrate his own plan of reconciliation. If he did that, we should be content with our lot and should see no reason to cooperate with him.
[P]eople who experience ego-tropic risks during their formative years (posing direct threats to themselves and their families) or socio-tropic risks (threatening their community) tend to be far more religious than those who grow up under safe, comfortable, and predictable conditions.
Creature C is a hard case = df. For any possible world in which C exists, C freely loves God if and only if the world contains some horrendous evil caused by immoral acts.4
For those who did not experience spiritual struggles, a strengthening rather than a diminishing of the beliefs that typically give rise to theodical attempts seemed to occur. Rather than challenging God’s love, suffering led these participants to experience increased confidence in God’s goodness. Rather than challenging God’s power, their suffering led them to a greater understanding of God’s control. Rather than challenging God’s omniscience, their suffering caused them to express intellectual humility in the face of God’s knowing.
4. God and Omelas
[T]he rape of a woman and axing off of her arms, psycho-physical torture whose ultimate goal is the disintegration of personality, betrayal of one’s deepest loyalties, child abuse of the sort described by Ivan Karamazov, child pornography, parental incest, slow death by starvation, the explosion of nuclear bombs over populated areas.
God faces an Omelas situation = df. in every world that God could create that includes some free creatures who freely love God, there exists at least one free creature that experiences pf-life-ruining evil and does not acquire a good that vastly outweighs that pf-life-ruining evil.
If terrible things had happened to me in this life…and in a future life of peace, and love, and joy that was beyond anything I could have imagined, [and] I can see that but for God’s allowing terrible things to have happened to humanity as a whole, distributed by chance…that me and all my friends here wouldn’t possibly be in this life of peace and love and joy without God’s having done that, if that was the only way to do it, I would say “thank you, God, for having made that choice”.(Sterba et al. 2022, emphasis added)
Agent-Relative Pauline Principle: It is incompatible with God’s moral perfection for God to intentionally permit person P to experience pf-life-ruining evil in order to attain some good—unless that good vastly outweighs the pf-life-ruining evil, can be attained in no other way, and accrues to P.
Limited Theodical Individualism (LTI): If God intentionally permits person P to experience pf-life-ruining evil, then P acquires a great good that vastly outweighs the pf-life-ruining evil.8
- Necessarily, if God exists, then God does not intentionally permit unredeemed pf-life-ruining evils.
- Necessarily, if God exists and there are unredeemed pf-life-ruining evils, then God intentionally permits unredeemed pf-life-ruining evils.
- So: necessarily, if God exists, then there are no unredeemed pf-life-ruining evils.
- However, there are unredeemed pf-life-ruining evils.
- Therefore, God does not exist.
[M]any horror participants die defeated, without believing in God, without recognizing divine solidarity with them in horror participation and without appropriating any positive significance that this confers… full recovery from horror participation usually takes place post mortem…God keeps us alive, heals our meaning-making capacities, wins our trust, and teaches us how to make positive sense of our lives.
[S]uppose that an abundantly available vaccine were, despite the painfulness of receiving it, known to produce a net benefit (the painfulness included) for everyone who receives it. Suppose, further, that no less painful procedure produces the same benefit. Under those circumstances, how could we ever have a moral obligation to prevent vaccination?
5. Conclusions
Funding
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
1 | The primary moral principle to which Mackie appeals is that “a good thing always eliminates evil as far as it can” (Mackie 1955, p. 201). As I explain below, Sterba instead appeals to the more plausible “Pauline Principle”. |
2 | See Sterba (2019, pp. 189–90) for a similar formulation of the argument. |
3 | Variations on this basic theme include: Adams (1999, pp. 82–83); Moreland and Craig (2003, pp. 544–48); Stump (2010, pp. 386–88); Tracy (1992, p. 311). |
4 | This concept is similar to Plantinga’s concept of transworld depravity; see Plantinga (1974, pp. 186–88). |
5 | Here I deviate from Van Inwagen, as he denies that there are any true counterfactuals of creaturely freedom (Van Inwagen 2006, p. 80). Plantinga’s free will defense seems to entail that God is unlucky when it comes to the truth values of the counterfactuals of creaturely freedom (Windt 1973); the current proposal entails that God is really unlucky in that regard. |
6 | This scenario is, of course, inspired by Ivan Karamazov’s famous “rebellion” in Dostoevsky’s The Brothers Karamazov; see also James (1891, p. 333). |
7 | Question: why should God not instead be seen as akin to a person who flips the switch to divert the runaway trolley to a side-track so that it kills one person rather than five, or as a platoon leader who sacrifices one soldier to save the rest of the platoon? (see Mawson 2011). Answer: God, as creator of the universe, can avoid all such scenarios by not creating them in the first place. So, God would be more akin to someone who sets up the trolley situation in the first place, and then flips the switch (see Boorse and Sorensen 1988, p. 118). |
8 | Marilyn Adams endorses an even stronger requirement—that the life-ruining evil be defeated (Adams 2013, pp. 19–20). That stronger requirement is compatible with my argument but not required by it. John Zeis (2015) argues for a similar conclusion on the grounds that God’s permission of evil in the world must satisfy a proportionality requirement. Zeis writes: “God’s will is unthwartable, and since He wants the good for everyone, He would bring it about that the evil which every person suffers is defeated. So, the proportionality condition is met by God when the evil state of affairs is ultimately defeated” (Zeis 2015, p. 137). |
References
- Adams, Marilyn. 1999. Horrendous Evils and the Goodness of God. Cornell: Cornell University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Adams, Marilyn. 2013. Ignorance, Instrumentality, Compensation, and the Problem of Evil. Sophia 52: 7–26. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Boorse, Christopher, and Roy A. Sorensen. 1988. Ducking Harm. The Journal of Philosophy 85: 115–34. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Craig, William Lane. 2017. A Molinist View. In God and the Problem of Evil: Five Views. Edited by Chad Meister and James Dew Jr. Downers Grove: InterVarsity Press, pp. 37–55. [Google Scholar]
- de Castella, Rosemary, and Janette Graetz Simmonds. 2013. There’s a deeper level of meaning as to what suffering’s all about’: Experiences of religious and spiritual growth following trauma. Mental Health, Religion & Culture 16: 536–56. [Google Scholar]
- Flint, Thomas. 1998. Divine Providence: The Molinist Account. New York: Cornell University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Freelin, Jeffrey. 2008. Theodicies, Utilitarianism, and Respect for Persons. Paper presented at the 1st Annual Conference on Philosophy & Theology, Jefferson City, MO, USA, October 3–4; vol. 4, pp. 64–76. Available online: https://bluetigercommons.lincolnu.edu/philosophy_and_theology/2008/sessions/4/ (accessed on 16 June 2022).
- Hall, M. Elizabeth Lewis, Laura Shannonhouse, Jamie Aten, Jason McMartin, and Eric Silverman. 2019. Theodicy or Not? Spiritual Struggles of Evangelical Cancer Survivors. Journal of Psychology and Theology 47: 259–77. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hasker, William. 2017. The Open Theist Response. In God and the Problem of Evil: Five Views. Edited by Chad Meister and James Dew Jr. Downers Grove: InterVarsity Press, pp. 151–62. [Google Scholar]
- James, William. 1891. The Moral Philosopher and the Moral Life. International Journal of Ethics 1: 330–54. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Jordan, Jeff. 2004. Divine love and human suffering. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 56: 169–78. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Knapp, Shoshana. 1985. The Morality of Creation: Dostoevsky and William James in Le Guin’s ‘Omelas. The Journal of Narrative Technique 15: 75–81. [Google Scholar]
- ter Kuile, Hagar, and Thomas Ehring. 2014. Predictors of Changes in Religiosity after Trauma: Trauma, Religiosity, and Posttraumatic Stress Disorder. Psychological Trauma: Theory, Research, Practice, and Policy 6: 353–60. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Le Guin, Ursula. 1991. The Ones Who Walk Away from Omelas (Variations on a theme by William James). Utopian Studies 2: 1–5. [Google Scholar]
- Lewis, Clive Staples. 1996. The Screwtape Letters. Uhrichsville: Barbour Publishing. [Google Scholar]
- Mackie, John Leslie. 1955. Omnipotence and Evil. Mind, New Series 64: 200–12. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Maitzen, Stephen. 2009. Ordinary Morality Implies Atheism. European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 2: 107–26. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Maitzen, Stephen. 2013. Atheism and the Basis of Morality. In What Makes Us Moral? On the Capacities and Conditions for being Moral. Edited by Bert Musschenga and Anton van Harskamp. New York: Springer, pp. 257–70. [Google Scholar]
- Mawson, Tim. 2011. Theodical Individualism. European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 3: 139–59. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Moreland, James Porter, and William Lane Craig. 2003. Philosophical Foundations for a Christian Worldview. Downers Grove: InterVarsity Press. [Google Scholar]
- Norris, Pippa, and Ronald Inglehart. 2004. Sacred and Secular: Religion and Politics Worldwide. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Plantinga, Alvin. 1974. The Nature of Necessity. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Sterba, James. 2019. Is a Good God Logically Possible? New York: Palgrave. [Google Scholar]
- Sterba, James, Louise Antony, Peter van Inwagen, and Dean Zimmerman. 2022. Video. 1st Religions Webinar: Atheist/Theist: Point/Counterpoint. Available online: https://religions-1.sciforum.net/ (accessed on 16 June 2022).
- Stump, Eleonore. 2010. Wandering in Darkness: Narrative and the Problem of Suffering. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Tooley, Michael. 1980. Alvin Plantinga and the argument from evil. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 58: 360–76. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tooley, Michael. 1991. The Argument from Evil. Philosophical Perspectives 5: 89–134. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tracy, Thomas F. 1992. Victimization and the Problem of Evil: A Response to Ivan Karamazov. Faith and Philosophy 9: 301–19. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Van Inwagen, Peter. 2006. The Problem of Evil. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Walls, Jerry. 2021. Heaven and the Goodness of God. Religions 12: 316. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Windt, Peter Y. 1973. Plantinga’s unfortunate God. Philosophical Studies 24: 335–42. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Zeis, John. 2015. The Theological Implications of Double Effect. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 89: 133–38. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2022 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Wielenberg, E.J. Sterba’s Logical Argument from Evil and the God Who Walks Away from Omelas. Religions 2022, 13, 782. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13090782
Wielenberg EJ. Sterba’s Logical Argument from Evil and the God Who Walks Away from Omelas. Religions. 2022; 13(9):782. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13090782
Chicago/Turabian StyleWielenberg, Erik J. 2022. "Sterba’s Logical Argument from Evil and the God Who Walks Away from Omelas" Religions 13, no. 9: 782. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13090782
APA StyleWielenberg, E. J. (2022). Sterba’s Logical Argument from Evil and the God Who Walks Away from Omelas. Religions, 13(9), 782. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13090782