Scepticism against Intolerance? Moses Mendelssohn and Pierre Bayle’s “Dialogue” on Spinoza in Mendelssohn’s Philosophische Gespräche (1755)
Abstract
:1. Introduction. Reading Spinoza in Early Modern Germany. The Singularity of the Philosophische Gespräche (1755)1
Did he not [Leibniz] also assert that changes in the soul can be explained by the same reason or ground through which changes in the visible world can be understood? Did he not assert that everything in the soul succeeds something else, just as it does in the context of things? What else does this mean but what Spinoza says in the words cited: «The order and connection of concepts is one and the same with the order and connection of things»3(JubA 1, 9–10; Mendelssohn 1997, p. 103)
2. From the “Religious Blindness” to the “Well-Founded Critics” of Christian Wolff and Pierre Bayle
Here and there he [Bayle] has, to be sure, brought up some correct objections to Spinoza. But he has interwoven them with so many sophisms and invalid inferences that he robs them, as it were, of all force. For example, the concept Spinoza appears to make for himself of extension was contested by Bayle with sound reasons, and he showed adequately that extension could not possibly be regarded as an infinite property [unendliche Eigenschaft] of God. But what purpose is served by the array of inferences that he burdens Spinoza with? What use is it to indicate that, in the opinion of Spinoza, if Christians take the field against Turks, God would take the field against God, or that all acts of murder, theft, adultery, and incest would have to be attributed to the supreme being?(JubA 1, 14–15; Mendelssohn 1997, p. 107).
To understand Leibniz successfully, it is necessary to become a good Leibnizian first. One must be familiar with his fundamental theses and definitions, just like a diligent student who only aims at focusing strictly on his words. At this point, the difficulties will not have to be sought, but will eventually emerge on their own. [...] [W]hoever reaches the top of the road will eventually encounter them. It will only be necessary not to close one’s eyes to what appears there at sight(JubA 1, 21. My translation)
Philopon: You leave me in doubt: will you eventually destroy the doctrine that I thought I had adhered to with good reasons?Neophil: I have already told you: the doctrine of the best of the worlds is directly implied by God’s properties, and even Bayle, when considering the issue from this viewpoint, had to admit it [the doctrine]. Moreover, it is the only one that can provide us with happiness, so that it is necessary for us to cherish it if we wish to gain peace of mind. The remarks against it which I have just exposed to you are only useful because they help us to realize that, as far as this doctrine is concerned, we are far from a perfect certainty, and that much prudence is required to arrive at reliable conclusions in our philosophical speculations about the world10.(JubA 1, 26–27. My translation)
3. The Role of Bayle’s Criticisms of Pre-Established Harmony in Rehabilitating Spinoza
True, Leibniz could very easily have been generous with such a triviality. It is more than parsimoniousness if people worth millions are not willing to have even a farthing stolen from them. And yet, Leibniz is to be excused here. You have to assume that he was so selfishly exact not towards Bayle the philosopher, but towards Bayle the critic. Towards Bayle the critic, I say, who has often made crimes out of smaller historical inaccuracies.(JubA 1, 3; Mendelssohn 1997, p. 97)
Neophil: In the seventh proposition of the second part of his Ethics, Spinoza says: «The order and connection of concepts is one and the same with the order and connection of things». Remember now what Leibniz brings to his defense against Bayle when the latter objects that, without the effect of another substance upon the soul, it would be inconceivable how the soul is frequently able to pass over immediately from pleasure to displeasure and from sadness to joy. Did he not also assert that changes in the soul can be explained by the same reason or ground through which changes in the visible world can be understood? Did he not assert that everything in the soul succeeds something else, just as it does in the context of things? What else does this mean but what Spinoza says in the words cited: «The order and connection of concepts is one and the same with the order and connection of things»?Philopon: How wonderful is the makeup of the human intellect! Through erroneous and bizarre principles Spinoza almost stumbles precisely into the view to which Leibniz was led by the soundest and most correct concepts of God and the world.(JubA 1, 9–10; Mendelssohn 1997, p. 103)
4. Conclusions: A “Sceptic Brotherhood” against Religious Intolerance?
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
1 | From now on, all references to the critical edition of Mendelssohn’s works (Mendelssohn 1971) will take the form ‘JubA 1, 54’, where ‘1’ refers to the volume and ‘54’ to the page from which the quotation is extracted. In turn, the few references to Christian Wolff’s Gesammelte Werke (Wolff 1965, 1972) will take the form ‘GW I.2, 22’, where ‘I’ refers to the division, ‘2’ to the volume, and ‘22’ to the page. |
2 | In fact, Mendelssohn’s claim cannot be said to be original stricto sensu. Corey Dyck (2018) observed that, in saying that Leibniz had borrowed the notion of pre-established Harmony from Spinoza, Mendelssohn claims that there is a link between Leibniz and Spinoza, which had already been assumed by Joachim Lange (1670–1744) during the polemic he led against Christian Wolff (1679–1754) with his fellow Pietist theologians from Halle. Interestingly, Mendelssohn’s defence of Spinoza is based on a philosophical connection that had outraged the Pietists and led to their finally expelling Wolff from Prussia under the charge of Spinozism. Therefore, Mendelssohn’s hermeneutical move is original in that he turns what was originally conceived of as a strenuous objection into a defensive instrument. I will address the core philosophical tenets of the Wolff-Lange polemic later in note 7. |
3 | Though most of Mendelssohn’s quotations are taken from the English translation of the Gespräche by Dahlstrom (Mendelssohn 1997), some of them have had to be extracted from the German original. Dahlstrom’s English translation is not based on the 1755 editio princeps of the Gespräche, but on the later 1771 reprint. This 1771 edition reproduces the second version of the Gespräche, which was published in 1761 and included substantial changes as compared to the editio princeps (like, for instance, an almost complete rewriting of the third dialogue). For all this, some passages from the first edition are not to be found in Dahlstrom’s version and must be quoted from the German original. Regarding the two different versions of the Gespräche, see Sales Vilalta (2022, pp. 103–5). |
4 | Jimena Solé (2011) recent account of the reception of Spinoza in the German lands from 1670 to 1789 offers a panoramic and accessible insight into the whole process and its main contributors. In fact, the author does also include a useful overview of previous approaches to the subject matter. When addressing them, Jimena Solé notes that most generalist works dealing with the reception of Spinoza have tended to divide the process into three phases. The specific characterization of these phases changes from one author to another. Nonetheless, they all generally assume that: (1) the initial phase is one of clear rejection marked by Jakob Thomasius’s and the subsequent reviews of the TTP; (2) the second brings about an arousing, often enthusiastic interest in Spinoza, and has mostly to do with Romantic and post-Romantic authors; (3) by the last one, modern scientific studies on Spinoza come to be eventually normalized. (Jimena Solé 2011, pp. 11–27). |
5 | Musaeus’s zeal against Spinoza is worth noting in order to grasp the kind of stigma that these first reviewers came to develop: “it is right to doubt whether, among those whom the devil himself has hired to subvert divine and human rights, there can be found anyone who, to the disgrace of the Church and the harm of the State, has shown himself more industrious in destroying them than this trickster” (quoted and adapted from: Domínguez 1995, p. 120). |
6 | Jean Paul Wurtz is responsible for the first modern and complete accounts of the polemic between Tschirnhaus and Thomasius, as well as contributing crucially to the rediscovery of Tschirnhaus’s own relevance and philosophical interest (Wurtz 1980, 1981). More recently, Miguel Ángel Granada (2021) has offered a new, usefully contextualized survey of the Tschirnhaus-Thomasius affair. By first depicting the “theosophical” intellectual context prevailing in the German lands well into the mid-seventeenth century, Granada argues that Tschirnhaus’s Medicina mentis must be seen as a turning point marking the emergence of a new intellectual, pre-Enlightened sensibility reliant on human reason and its capacity both to inquire into the world and to successfully strive for a virtuous, happy life (Granada 2021, pp. 377–79). This kind of radical and forward-looking move was unacceptable to the much more pro-Pietist Thomasius, who was emphatic on the need to demarcate Theology from Philosophy and remember the constitutive weakness of sinful human reason (for instance, see Thomasius 1699, pp. 1–5 [c.1, §1–15]). |
7 | Wolff’s claim in his German Metaphysics (1720) that Leibnizian pre-established harmony is the best account of mind/body dualism involved a Spinozist kind of determinism and fatalism for Joachim Langue, the leading voice of the Pietist group opposed to Wolff, who had already been very critical of Leibniz’s Essais de Theodicée (Wilson 1995, pp. 446–52). For Lange, the assumption that soul and body remain strictly coordinated at any time denies the possibility of free will, insofar as the soul becomes permanently conditioned by the body to which it is bound and is thus incapable of independent, non-conditioned agency. For a survey on Wolff’s accusation of Spinozism and his political and religious significance, see Goldenbaum’s recent contribution to the historical context surrounding Wolff’s thinking (Goldenbaum 2021, pp. 10–18). |
8 | It is worth noting that Mendelssohn seems here to be assuming Leibniz’s own idea that Descartes is a sort of “ante-chamber of truth”, and that his (Leibniz’s) philosophy is deliberately aimed at detecting and solving the problems within Cartesian thinking that had prevented Descartes from further achieving what, according to the prior metaphor, we might call “the chamber of truth”. In this regard, see Anfray’s recent contribution (Anfray 2019, particularly pp. 721–26). The way in that Mendelssohns says Spinoza to make the transition to Leibnizianism possible will be exposed at length in the next section. |
9 | Wolff made an explicit refutation of Spinozism some years after his expulsion from Halle. He included it at the end of the second part of his Latin Theology (1737), that is, within the section devoted to atheism, in the chapter entitled “De paganismo, manicheismo, spinozismo et epicureismo” (“On Paganism, Manichaeism, Spinozism and Epicureanism”). For Wolff’s refutation of Spinozism, see Buschmann (1994). |
10 | Bayle’s relationship with scepticism is an undeniably complex issue. Although a very small minority denies it (see Hickson 2023), most of current scholars consider Bayle to be some kind of sceptic, led by Popkin’s auhtoritative consideration of Bayle as the “supersceptic” culminating the sceptical crisis of early modern times (Popkin 2019, pp. 628–66). Whatever the extent of Bayle’s de dicto adherence to scepticism, I think it’s reasonable to see the critical Dictionnaire as de facto exemplifying the Pyrrhonian approach to philosophy that Bayle himself describes in the 1702 version of the article “Pyrrhon”. As Bayle puts it: “they [the pyrrhonists] have a kind of weapon that they call the diallel, which they wield at the first instant it is needed. After this is done, it is impossible to withstand them on any subject whatsoever. It is a labyrinth in which the thread of Ariadne cannot be of any help. They lose themselves in their own subtelties […] since this serves to show more clearly the universality of their hypothesis that all is uncertain, not even excepting the arguments which attack uncertainty… Theologians should not be ashamed to admit that they cannot enter a contest with such antagonists. […] The small boat of Jesus Christ is not made for sailing on this stormy sea, but for taking shelter from his tempest in the haven of Faith” (quoted from: Popkin 1997, p. 3). Regarding the constitutive Pyrrhonian character of Bayle’s Dictionnaire, see Rothenberger (2021, specially pp. 141–223). I will return to Bayle’s philosophical ethos within the final section of the article. |
11 | Throughout the text, Mendelssohn refers to pre-established Harmony by using the expressions ‘Hypothesis’, ‘Opinion’ [Meinung] and, less often, ‘Doctrine’ [Lehrmeinung]. This fact is interestingly related with the Wolff-Lange affair. In his German Metaphysics (1720), Wolff presents what he considers to be the three possible accounts of the mind/body relation, mirroring the three-fold division between the Aristotelian-Scholastic, the Cartesian and the Leibnizian mind/body systems that Leibniz himself seemed to sketch for the first time in his 1695 Système nouveau (Leibniz 1986, pp. 201–27). Each account is singularized by a specific kind of causal relation between bodies and souls. (1) Natural influence [natürliche Einfluss] is based on the existence of “reciprocal action” [Wirkung in einander] between bodies and souls, so that bodily movements can cause thoughts and vice versa; (2) in the comunion [Gemeinschaft] defended by the Cartesians, body and soul simply “give occasion” [Gelegenheit geben] to God’s action, God being the only One with real agency to cause effects in the world; (3) Leibniz’s pre-established Harmony [vorherbestimmte Harmonie] involves two separate, yet divinely (and thus perfectly) coordinated causal realms, one including bodies and their movements and the other constituted by souls and their thoughts. Wolff successively refutes natural influence and occasionalism, showing pre-established Harmony to be the only plausible approach. Though he is not really explicit on that, Wolff thus seems to suggest that Leibnizian Harmony is the only true account of mind/body dualism. (GW I.2, 470–88). Things become slightly different in his posterior Psychologia Rationalis (1734). After the many troubles caused by Lange’s ardour against pre-established Harmony (see note 7), Wolff explicitly granted all three systems on mind/body relation with the status of mere “hypotheses”, that is, of provisional theories subject to possible refutation. Natural influence, occasional causes and pre-established Harmony are thus placed on the same hypothetical level, and none of them can be considered “the best” or “the truest” stricto sensu. In this respect, it is very important to note that, in note L within the article “Rorarius” of his Dictionnaire, Bayle had also used the label “hypothesis” [hypothèses] for any of the three existing approaches to mind/body dualism (following Leibniz’s Système) (Bayle 1991, pp. 235–38). Therefore, Wolff’s trouble with the Piestists lead him to mirror Bayle’s much more prudent treatment of mind/body dualism. For all this, Mendelssohn inherits both Bayle’s and also Wolff’s later terminology regarding mind/body dualism, in a seemingly cautious gesture against those with a tendency to deluge their rivals “with calumnies”. |
12 | The French theologian François Lamy (1636–1711) used the expression ‘Pre-established Harmony’ [Harmonie préetablie] in the second of the five volumes within his De la connaissance de soi-même (On knowledge of oneself, 1694–1698; Bayle 1991, p. 245). Incidentally, it is important not to confuse François Lamy with Bernard Lamy (1640–1715), a mathematician at the time, mostly centred on Mechanics and Geometry and with some incidental incursions into the fields of Logics and Language (La Rhetorique ou l’art de parler—Rhetoric or the art of speaking—1675). I do emphasize this because, in Dahlstrom’s English translation, the Lamy adduced by Bayle is erroneously said to be Bernard Lamy. |
13 | Following Wolff (GW I.2, 56–68), Mendelssohn implicitly assumes that each soul essentially owns a specific representative force [Vorstellungskraft] of its own, which in fact constitutes it as a unique and indivisible substance [Substanz]. |
14 | Bayle’s attacks on Leibnizian Harmony are the result of a long an interesting discussion between Bayle and Leibniz, beginning immediately after the publication of Leibniz Système nouveau in a June 1695 issue of the Journal des Savants, and lasting for some years after the first edition of the Dictionnaire appeared. For details of this discussion, see Barber (1955, pp. 56–69), Fichant (2015) and Pelletier (2015). |
15 | Interestingly, Mendelssohn does not use the recent German translation of the Ethica by Johann Lorenz Schmidt (1702–1749) to quote Spinoza, but opts instead for adapting Spinoza’s text on his own. Schmidt published his translation in 1744, including both the Ethica and Wolff’s refutation of it, under the title B. V. S. Sittenlehre widerleget von dem berühmter Welteisen unserer Zeit Hernn Christian Wolff (The Ethics of B.V.S. refuted by the well-known philosopher of our time, Mr. Christian Wolff). Regarding Schmidt’s translation and the hostile reaction it aroused within the still fiercely anti-Spinozian Pietist establishment, see Goldenbaum (2011). Incidentally, this constituted a good reason for Mendelssohn to avoid its use. |
16 | As already exposed in note 11, we must not forget that, at the time, occasionalism is said to be one of the three possible systems to explain mind/body dualism. |
17 | In the 1755 edition, Philopon’s question is much more generic than in the second, 1761 version of the text. In it, Mendelssohn completes Philopon’s intervention by specifically facing the great problem posed by Bayle and to be tackled by Neophil all at once: “He [Spinoza] says, to be sure, that the actions and passions of the soul spring from their adequate and inadequate concepts. But what explains those alterations of the soul that are apparently based, not on the foregoing state of the soul, but on the movements of the body instead? If sensuous concepts are things the soul undergoes, where does Spinoza show us the way in which we are to derive these from inadequate concepts (without the help of the body and its limbs)?” (JubA 1, 344; Mendelssohn 1997, p. 102). |
18 | This subtle distinction between cause and reason is a central one within Wolff’s philosophy. As Wolff clarifies in his German Metaphysics, when a thing A contains something that makes it possible to understand what another thing B is, A contains the reason for B and, therefore, A is the cause of B. The example he gives in to illuminate the distinction between both concepts is illustrative: when someone wants to go out because the weather is good, the representation of the good weather is the reason [Grund] of his desire, and the soul, which produces the representation, is the cause [Ursache] of it (GW I.2, 56–68). Philopon’s prior exposition of Leibnizian Harmony includes an interesting modulation of Wolff’s distinction which, in fact, makes Mendelssohn much closer to Leibniz’s Système than to Wolff’s German Metaphysics. As Philopon puts it, every change that the soul undergoes occurs (1) by instigation [auf Veranlassung] of the body, though (2) actually caused by the soul’s constitutive force [ursprungliche Kraft], so that the soul is the only real cause of it. Similarly, everything happening in the body occurs (1) by instigation of the soul but (2) exclusively caused by the action of mechanistic-bodily forces [körperliche mechanische Krafte]. On the basis of this subtle differentiation between “cause” [Ursache] and “insitgation” [Veranlassung], Philopon claims that both psychic representations and bodily movements have two different sufficient reasons [zureichenen Gründe], that is, two complementary ways of being explained and understood. As for the soul’s representations, for instance, the reason through which they emerge [Grund wodurch] is to be found in the mechanical movements of the body, while the final reason or reason why they emerge [Grund zu welchen Ende oder warum] lies in the soul’s constitutive force causing the representation. (JubA 1, 4–5). |
19 | |
20 |
References
- Altmann, Alexander. 1973. Moses Mendelssohn. A Biographical Study. New York: Routledge and Kegan Paul. [Google Scholar]
- Altwicker, Norbert. 1971. Tendenzen der Spinoza-rezeption und-kritik. In Texte zur Geschichte des Spinozismus. Edited by N. Altwicker. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, pp. 1–51. [Google Scholar]
- Anfray, Jean Pascal. 2019. Leibniz and Descartes. In The Oxford Handbook of Descartes and Cartesianism. Edited by Steven Nadler, Tad M. Schmaltz and Delphine Antoine-Mahut. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 721–37. [Google Scholar]
- Barber, William Henry. 1955. Leibniz in France: From Arnauld to Voltaire; a Study in French reactions to Leibnizianism, 1670–1760. Oxord: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Bayle, Pierre. 1991. Spinoza, Benedictus De. In Pierre Bayle: Historical and Critical Dictionary, Selections. Translated and edited by Richard Popkin. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company. [Google Scholar]
- Bäck, Leo. 1895. Spinozas Erste Einwirkungen auf Deutschland. Berlin: Mayer & Müller. [Google Scholar]
- Buschmann, Cornelia. 1994. Wolffs Widerlegung der Ethik Spinozas. In Spinoza in der Deutsche Geistesgeschichte. Edited by Hanna Delf, Julius H. Schoeps and Manfred Walther. Berlin: Hentrich, pp. 126–41. [Google Scholar]
- Domínguez, Atilano, trans. 1995. Biografías de Spinoza. Madrid: Alianza. [Google Scholar]
- Dyck, Corey W. 2018. The Spinozian-Wolffian Philosophy? Mendelssohn’s Philosophical Dialogues of 1755. Kant-Studien 109: 251–69. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Fichant, Michel. 2015. Les réponses de Leibniz au Dictionnaire Historique et Critique de Bayle et l’invention du système. In Leibniz et Bayle: Confrontation et Dialogue. Edited by Christian Leduc, Paul Rateau and Jean-Luc Solère. Stuttgart: Franz Steiner Verlag, pp. 25–48. [Google Scholar]
- Goetschel, Willi. 2004. Spinoza’s Modernity: Mendelssohn, Lessing, and Heine. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press. [Google Scholar]
- Goldenbaum, Ursula. 2011. Mendelssohn’s Spinozistic alternative to Baumgarten’s Pietist Project of Aesthetics. In Moses Mendelssohn’s Metaphysics and Aesthetics. Edited by Reiner Munk. Dordrecht: Springer, pp. 298–327. [Google Scholar]
- Goldenbaum, Ursula. 2021. Who’s Afraid of Wolff’s Psychology? The Historical Context. In The Force of an Idea: New Essays on Christian Wolff’s Psychology. Edited by Saulo de Freitas Araujo, Thiago Constâncio Ribeiro Pereira and Thomas Sturm. Cham: Springer, pp. 7–28. [Google Scholar]
- Granada, Miguel Ángel. 2021. La Medicina mentis de E. W. von Tschirnhaus o el paso en Alemania de la Teosofía a la Preilustración tras la paz de Westfalia. Revista Anales del Seminario de Historia de la Filosofía 38: 377–87. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hickson, Michael. 2023. Pierre Bayle. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Edited by Edward N. Zalta and Uri Nodelman. Stanford: Stanford University. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2023/entries/bayle/ (accessed on 15 December 2023).
- Jimena Solé, Maria. 2011. Spinoza en Alemania (1670–1789). Historia de la Santificación de un Filósofo Maldito. Córdoba: Las Brujas. [Google Scholar]
- Krakauer, Moses. 1881. Zur Geschichte des Spinozismus in Deutschland Während der ersten Hälfte des 18. Jahrhunderts. Breslau: Schottlaender. [Google Scholar]
- Labrousse, Elisabeth. 1985. Pierre Bayle, Tome I: Du pay de foix à la cite d’Erasme. (International Archives of the History of Ideas, 1). Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff. [Google Scholar]
- Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. 1986. Philosophische Schrifften. Bd.1. Kleine Schriften zur Metaphysik. Frankfurt am Main: Insel. [Google Scholar]
- Lennon, Thomas M. 1999. Reading Bayle. Toronto: University of Toronto Press. [Google Scholar]
- Mendelssohn, Moses. 1971. Gesammelte Schriften. Jubiläumausgabe. Bd.1. Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt: Frommann-Holzboog. [Google Scholar]
- Mendelssohn, Moses. 1997. Philosophical Writings. Translated by Daniel O. Dahlstrom. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Otto, Rüdiger. 1994. Studien zur Spinozarezeption in Deutschland im 18. Jahrhundert. Frankfurt am Main: Lang. [Google Scholar]
- Pätzold, Detlev. 2002. Spinoza, Aufklärung, Idealismus: Die Substanz der Moderne. Oostersingel: Koninklijke Van Gorcum. [Google Scholar]
- Pelletier, Arnauld. 2015. Une dissection du chien de Bayle: La dernière lettre de Leibniz à Bayle, ou l’origine de l’exposé monadologique. In Leibniz et Bayle: Confrontation et Dialogue. Edited by Christian Leduc, Paul Rateau and Jean-Luc Solère. Stuttgart: Franz Steiner Verlag, pp. 165–96. [Google Scholar]
- Popkin, Richard. 1997. Scepticism in the Enlightenment. In Scepticism in the Enlightenment. Edited by Richard Popkin, Ezequiel de Olaso and Giorgio Tonelli. Dordrecht: Kluwer, pp. 1–16. [Google Scholar]
- Popkin, Richard. 2019. Histoire du Scepticism. De la Fin du Moyen Âge à l’aube du XIXe Siècle. Rome: Agone. [Google Scholar]
- Rothenberger, Eva. 2021. Scepticisme Moderne et Historiographie Polémique—Pierre Bayle et le Dictionnaire Historique et Critique. Tübingen: Narr Francke Attempto Verlag. [Google Scholar]
- Sales Vilalta, Guillem. 2022. Leibnizianisme crític, spinozisme encobert? Els Diàlegs filosòfics (Philosophische Gespräche, 1755) de Moses Mendelssohn. Anuari de la Societat Catalana de Filosofia XXXIII: 95–140. [Google Scholar]
- Schröder, Winfried. 1987. Spinoza in der Deutschen Frühaufklärung. Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann. [Google Scholar]
- Strauss, Ze’ev. 2018. The Ground Floor of Judaism: Scepticism and Certainty in moses Mendelssohn’s Jerusalem. In 2018 (Yearbook of the Maimonides Centre for Advanced Studies). Edited by Bill Rebiger. Berlin: De Gruyter, pp. 179–206. [Google Scholar]
- Thomasius, Christian. 1699. Einleitung zur Vernunft-Lehre. Halle: Cristoph Salfeld. [Google Scholar]
- Wilson, Catherine. 1995. The reception of Leibniz in the eighteenth century. In The Cambridge Companion to Leibniz. Edited by Nicholas Jolley. Cambrige: Cambridge University Press, pp. 442–76. [Google Scholar]
- Wolff, Christian. 1965. Gesammelte Werke. I Abteilung, Band 1. Vernünftige Gedanken von den Kräften des Menschlichen Vertsandes und Ihrem Richtigen Gebrauche in Erketniss der Wahrheit. Hildesheim: Olms. [Google Scholar]
- Wolff, Christian. 1972. Gesammelte Werke. II Abteilung, Band 6. Psychologia Rationalis. Hildesheim: Olms. [Google Scholar]
- Wurtz, Jean Paul. 1980. Tschirnhaus et l’accusation de spinozisme: La polémique avec Christian Thomasius. Revue Philosophique de Louvain 78: 489–506. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wurtz, Jean Paul. 1981. Tschirnhaus und die Spinozismusbeschuldigung: Die Polemik mit Christian Thomasius. Studia Leibnitiana 13: 61–75. [Google Scholar]
- Zac, Sylvain. 1989. Spinoza en Allemagne: Mendelssohn, Lessing et Jacobi. Paris: Meridiens Klincksieck. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2023 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Sales Vilalta, G. Scepticism against Intolerance? Moses Mendelssohn and Pierre Bayle’s “Dialogue” on Spinoza in Mendelssohn’s Philosophische Gespräche (1755). Religions 2024, 15, 49. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15010049
Sales Vilalta G. Scepticism against Intolerance? Moses Mendelssohn and Pierre Bayle’s “Dialogue” on Spinoza in Mendelssohn’s Philosophische Gespräche (1755). Religions. 2024; 15(1):49. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15010049
Chicago/Turabian StyleSales Vilalta, Guillem. 2024. "Scepticism against Intolerance? Moses Mendelssohn and Pierre Bayle’s “Dialogue” on Spinoza in Mendelssohn’s Philosophische Gespräche (1755)" Religions 15, no. 1: 49. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15010049
APA StyleSales Vilalta, G. (2024). Scepticism against Intolerance? Moses Mendelssohn and Pierre Bayle’s “Dialogue” on Spinoza in Mendelssohn’s Philosophische Gespräche (1755). Religions, 15(1), 49. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15010049