The Imago Dei and the Market Economy: Libertarian Tensions in Michael Novak’s Political Theology
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. The Imago Dei and Novak’s Case for the Market Economy
2.1. The Imago Dei and the Unplanned Common Good
As [Novak] characterized it, this drive [toward freedom] is (1) unstructured or preoccupied in the sense that it is open to receive whatever data might be presented to it; (2) unlimited in the sense that its object is to grasp everything that is to be understood, and even why the unintelligible is so; (3) objective in the sense that it seeks the critically verified real, as opposed to the imagined; and (4) unifying in the sense that it draws together the various activities of inquiry, namely, attention, insight, reflection, and understanding.
2.2. The Imago Dei, the Market, and Moral Virtue
3. Novak and Natural Rights Libertarians
3.1. Libertarian Methodological Independence from Religious Presuppositions
Religious ideas do not work in history as premises in logic or postulates in geometry; they work as yeast in dough. For their aim is not so much to chance logic as to change personal and social life. To fulfill this process, mediation, reflection, and the slow process of self-criticism as needed. Thus, the conviction that the one God is the Creator of all and made every woman and man in his image became the main ground in history for the growing sense of dignity of every human person, even among slaves and the poor and the vulnerable….That the creator calls all humans to himself, and is also the undeceivable Judge of all, further became the main historical ground for the idea that truth is weightier than power and interest, and that therefore, it is the truth that sets us free. Against every power and interest, the human being rightly appeals to truth. It is the same for the idea that every person is responsible for his own free choices in life, on which he or she will be judged. It is under the tutelage of Judaism and Christianity that, in due course, the operation (and the nature) of conscience emerged in human consciousness, and also the idea that the power of the state is limited in the realm of the sacred.
In the case of man, the natural law ethic states that goodness or badness can be determined by what fulfills or thwarts what is best for man’s nature. The natural law, then, elucidates what is best for man—what ends he should pursue that are most harmonious with, and best tend to fulfill, his nature.
Thus natural law, rather than being external to the human being, expresses what human beings are. We are creatures whose participation in God’s providential rule takes the form of using our reason to reflect on our natural inclinations and thus, when reason is functioning properly, arriving at directives that coincide with God’s eternal law for human life.
3.2. Libertarian Idealism and the Market Economy
[T]he notion that one can defend reason and liberty apart from the conviction that truth derives from the Creator and Judge has turned out to be a weak reed, just as Nietzche predicted. Usually, we use the word “truth” as a characteristic either or propositions or of the reality of things. But the suppressed implication of this usage, as Nietzsche saw clearly, is that truth in the end is personal; it is grounded in God. Take out God and truth floats free, flimsily related if at all to either propositions or things. It comes then to seem rooted in nothing more than our own desires and projects. It thereby loses its original force. We are thus once again (after an exception interval of two millennia) left embedded in a world whose moving forces are power and interest”.
3.3. The Limitations of Novak’s Tripartite System
4. Conclusions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Novak credits Aquinas as the greatest contributor to this development because it was Aquinas who drew upon the Greek understanding of the common good and the Judeo-Christian understanding of the person to formulate a unique natural ordering of individual and community situated in a theological hierarchy of law. Novak also credits later thinkers, particularly Jacques Maritain and Yves Simon, for advancing a uniquely modern and uniquely theological understanding of the human person by applying Aquinas’ to modern pluralistic societies. Maritain’s insights into Thomas were especially profound: the central importance of the controversy of the 1940s was the Christian understanding of the human person and its purpose in life. “Each human”, writes Novak, “is ordered to union with [God], fulfilling thereby the deepest quest for his or her own being…[T]his communion…is the final purpose of all humans together” (Novak 1989, p. 30). |
2 | Novak depicts the unplanned market economy as metaphorical “darkness” and human persons, as sovereign creatures under God, counteracting that “darkness” with the light of their intelligent subjectivity. Each person must interact with the darkness through the exercise of their reason and will and develop moral virtues through the uncertainties and challenges of life (Klos 2014, p. 115). Klos is particularly helpful for drawing out these motifs. Klos notes that Novak’s broader conception of rationality—a view which understands that the act of assent to a belief entails more than mere rationalistic inferences from premises to conclusions—creates space for free persons acting within an unplanned order. Novak considered a formalistic view of human rationality, wherein human minds are “automatons encapsulated in an iron cage”, to be too restricting of a notion to secure the freedom human beings require. |
3 | Human beings are both individual and social, born into families that “begin to experience and to reflect within lived social worlds” (Klos 2014, p. 116). This fact underscores Novak’s insistence on the preservation of the middle-class, bourgeois family unit: it is the “formative institution of strong personalities”; it is the pre-societal, natural, informal institution. Even though Novak considered the bourgeois family to be a “modern product, the founding element of the middle class”, he also believed the market economy to be essential not only as a faithful depiction of human nature and rationality but also as the necessary landscape for the development of the human person in the form of middle-class families that derive their self-worth through “self-direct accomplishments” and derive their social status through “excellences” (virtues). |
4 | Novak is quite amenable to Friedrich Hayek’s notion of a spontaneous order. This allows Novak to simultaneously affirm the essential freedom of the individual and a concern for the common good. The mediating position for Novak is not one between libertarianism and totalitarianism. It is between totalitarianism and self-interest turned in on itself. In other words, the mediating position is one that respects the free choice of individuals to associate with others in community without being imposed upon by an external force whose vision of the common good is singular and totalizing. It is also one that understands that human beings are social by nature and therefore require participation in social life. The economic implications for such a society comport with Novak’s vision of the market economy—an economic order arising from the self-interested choices of free individuals that contribute indirectly to the common good. |
5 | Novak explains, “The specific vitalities of the person spring from the capacities for insight and choice (inquiry and love). From these derive principles of liberty and responsibility, in which human dignity is rooted. The human person is dignus, worthy of respect, sacred even, because he or she lives from the activities proper to God. To violate these is to denigrate the Almighty. Moreover, the person is not solitary. The free person, enjoying liberty and finding justification for it in his very endowment (by the Creator) with “unalienable rights” is obliged to recognize these same rights in every human person. It is an error to define the individual without reference to God and without reference to those other persons who also share in God’s life….The self-enclosed, self-centered individualism rests upon a misapprehension of the capacities of the human person, in which light each person is judged by God, by other persons, and by conscience itself (whose light is God’s activity in the soul). The person is a sign of God in history…or participates in God’s own most proper activities, insight and choice. The human person is theophanous: a shining-through of God’s life in history, created by God for union with God” (Novak 1989, p. 35). |
6 | Properly speaking the right of self-ownership affirms a person’s ownership of his or her body. It asserts that a person is entitled to its exclusive control and free purposive action. Self-ownership serves as the starting point for libertarian natural rights theory. Contrary to many critics of libertarianism, the right of self-ownership is not ownership over oneself strictly speaking, as some critics have mistakenly believed, nor does it necessarily entail a Kantian mind–body dualism (Schlueter 2014, p. 48). However, Attas rejects the criticism that says the self-ownership axiom renders the human being into a mind–body dualism (Attas 2000, pp. 17–18). It is rather a way of speaking about one’s body as a subject on the one hand and one’s body as an object of use on the other. McElwee explains that the notion of self-ownership is another way of describing the difference between subject experience and reflection upon one’s body (McElwee 2010, p. 217). |
7 | Classic natural law tradition is defined here as the Aristotelian–Thomistic tradition. Rothbard sees the same tradition running from Thomas, through the Spanish scholastics and Dutch jurist Grotius, and eventually through the philosophy of eighteenth-century Enlightenment political theorist, John Locke. The crucial distinction, however, between a Thomistic natural law and that, say, of Grotius through Locke, is the relationship of the natural law to the eternal law of God. For Thomas, the natural law was never independent from the eternal law, and it was never sufficient to guide human affairs. Natural law required clarity at points through the divine law. Grotius, in contrast, attempted to distill a natural law that would be true even in the case of God’s non-existence. Whether it is fair to accuse Grotius of constructing a non-theological natural law is another matter, but his influence on the Enlightenment is difficult to overestimate. Rothbard, in fact, adopts Grotius’ natural law tradition—although he draws many insights from Thomas and the Spanish scholastics for economic theory—since Grotius allows him to construct a natural law ethic on purely rational grounds, apart from theological considerations. |
8 | Against the naturalistic fallacy, Rothbard argues that natural law ethic does not derive fact from value directly. Rather, it derives value from what leads to the fulfillment of being. It is illegitimate to infer goodness from a current natural state of affairs, but one may infer goodness from the fulfillment of a better state of affairs. One can determine what these better states might be by reflection upon and observation of the natural tendencies in the structure of the entity. The good of a plant is the healthy supply of sunlight, for the structure of the plant emits the natural tendency to thrive in sunlight. One good for human beings is liberty, for the structure of human beings is such that they tend to thrive in the absence of coercion. Although, it is not entirely clear that Rothbard avoids the naturalistic fallacy, since any assertion about goodness seems to require an objective standard of goodness outside of the natural world to inform nature of what is good. Without this standard, any movement from one state of affairs to another would at most yield a difference in utility. |
9 | Rothbard rejects the criticism that his ethic is a materialistic conception of natural law. It is, rather, a fusion of man’s spirit with matter. Man’s mind produces ideas that interact with and shape matter. Ideas are manifestations of man’s spirit. However, he does not care to explain how the natural law or reason justifies a belief in man’s “spirit” or how the concept of an individual “spirit” is coherent without grounding it in a non-materialist worldview. |
10 | Walter Block notes that the libertarian argument from natural law depends on an assertion of the non-aggression principle (NAP) as the fundamental moral precept for human well-being. However, he notes, humans actually have a greater proclivity toward aggression than non-aggression, and this proclivity has probably furthered the good of humanity’s survival within a hostile environment. It is not likely, Block concludes, that the non-aggression principle could have produced similar results, and it is not clear that the NAP is as good for humanity as it seems to be in the present time (Block 2015, p. 40). Whether one accepts Block’s objection or not, the fundamental problem is the intractable difficulty of discerning what human nature is, and therefore, what natural law is. One need only consider opposing schools of libertarian theory to recognize the problem (Share 2012, pp. 117–50). |
11 | Hoppe’s argument has been widely used among natural rights libertarians (Block 2015, p. 41). Commonly referred to as argumentation ethics, Hoppe’s strategy has been widely used among libertarian thinkers. The roots of this strategy may be credited to the political theorist and philosopher, Alan Gewirth, who popularized the concept that undergirds Hoppe’s reasoning: the notion of PGC—the Principle of Generic Consistency. The PGC is intended to demonstrate that if one individual (following the implications of his rational agency) is compelled logically to believe in his own rights, then he must apply the same rights in principle to other rational agents. In his seminal work, Human Rights, Gewirth makes a formal argument to this affect. One of Gewirth’s students and a renowned libertarian philosopher, Roger Pilon, has built upon Gewirth’s theory to produce a libertarian version (Gewirth 1981; Pilon 1979, pp. 1171–96). |
12 | Mack grounds natural rights in the fact that “each individual has, in her own well-being, a goal worthy of her own pursuit”. Having this goal provides a reason for non-interference because it is the “appropriate response to the separate moral importance of others as beings with ultimate ends of their own” (Mack 2016, p. 77). Robert Nozick’s natural rights justification is similar to Mack’s in grounding rights in each individual’s pursuit of her ultimate ends, but where Nozick only provides a refutation of utilitarianism—against treating individuals as means instead of as ends—Mack argues that individuals who each have their own ultimate ends provide a reason for thinking interference would not only be unjustified on practical terms but would be morally wrong. This is because each individual possesses the same unique capacities for pursuing those ends (Nozick 1974, pp. 48–51). |
13 | The thrust of Hoppe’s argument is that by using one’s mind and body to argue, one must presuppose basic right of ownership in oneself and the person receiving the argument, since by engaging in argumentation one is assuming that the other person has the free will to accept or reject the argument. Hoppe explains, “Argumentation… is a form of action requiring the employment of scarce means; and furthermore, that the means, then, which a person demonstrates as preferring by engaging in propositional exchanges are those of private property. For one thing, obviously, no one could possibly propose anything, and no one could become convinced of any proposition by argumentative means, if a person’s right to make exclusive use of his physical body were not already presupposed”. So, if a person argues against the right of self-ownership, he or she presupposes that the person receiving the argument has the right of self-ownership, because he or she is free to either accept or reject the argument. In this sense, the critic of the right of self-ownership presupposes the same right in his or her listeners. |
14 | This method is like Kant’s “kingdom of ends” ethic wherein each person sees himself as an end in himself and rationally deduces that all other persons ought to be treated as ends in themselves. Kantian deontologist, Jason Kuznicki, explains that the key difference between deontological and natural rights arguments is that the latter essentially begin with a hypothetical imperative about human nature, namely, “If I am a human being, then I must believe or do X with respect to other human beings”. Kuznicki points out that under a strict Kantian argument, no claims about human nature are necessary to establish a deontological framework for ethics. In contrast, natural law/natural rights arguments rely on the hypothetical imperative about human nature, and this hypothetical cannot serve as a fundamental moral law, for ethics may consider but should never be founded on a hypothetical imperative. |
15 | Rothbard’s natural law/natural rights ethic requires that natural rights be species-specific. That is, only members of the homo sapien species possess these rights and animals do not. In his chapter on animal rights, Rothbard distinguishes human beings from animals on the basis of rationality. “In short, man has rights because they are natural rights. They are grounded in the nature of man: the individual man’s capacity for conscious choice…In short, man is a rational and social animal. No other animals or beings possess this ability to reason” (Rothbard 2012, p. 155). |
16 | Wolterstorff identifies a crucial distinction between human beings and the property of possessing rational agency; namely, some humans do not have the property of possessing rational agency but nevertheless remain human. To understand the implications, one must recognize a further distinction between human nature and how that nature stands in relation to rational capacity. All human beings stand in relation to the capacity for rational agency in some way. Some human beings possess it in actuality while others only possess it potentially (e.g., perhaps due to a severe mental deformity). Thus, while all human beings stand in some relation to the capacity for rationality, they do not stand in relation to this capacity equally. All human beings have a basic property of standing in some relation to the capacity, but the basic property is just that: standing in some relation to the capacity. It is not a basic property of human beings to fully actualize the capacity. Wolterstorff’s definition of a “soft relationship” means that to be human means “belonging to a species such that maturation of its properly formed members includes possessing the capacity for rational agency” (Wolterstorff 2008, p. 355). |
17 | If the libertarian grounds natural rights in the exercise of rational agency, this clearly cannot secure rights for all and only human beings. He would have to deny the humanity of any individual who did not exercise rational agency. Some humans (e.g., infants) clearly do not exercise the capacity even though they possess it as a latent capacity, and so this standard would at least eliminate them from the set of rights-bearers. Rothbard balks at this suggestion, but his treatment of newborns suggests that the natural right to self-ownership (that which undergirds all other rights) is not fully obtained until a child can at least exercise rational agency (Rothbard 2012, p. 97). Locke employs a distinction between a child being born in a full state of equality and being born to this state. Building upon Locke, Rothbard asserts, “It is clear that a newborn baby is in no natural sense an existing self-owner, but rather a potential self-owner”. Elsewhere, Rothbard does not consider a fetus to be a self-owner; it is, rather, the property of the mother: “As the creators of the baby, [the mother] becomes its owner. A baby cannot be an existent self-owner in any sense” (Rothbard 2012, p. 100). This seems to suggest that either the fetus is not a living human being with natural rights or that its right of self-ownership is not actual but only potential. Hence, its potential right to self-ownership is not sufficient to override the mother’s actual right of self-ownership. Why cannot a fetus be an actual self-owner? Because it lacks the actualization of rational agency to claim its right to self-ownership. |
18 | Rothbard cryptically refers to these entities as only “scarcely human” (Rothbard 2012, p. 102). If the libertarian objects that those entities that do not possess the capacity are not human—something Rothbard seems willing to entertain when he refers to these individuals as “scarcely human”—then one could ask why it is that the property of possessing the capacity for rationality is the necessary qualification for humanity? In other words, why are certain members of the Homo sapiens species excluded from the category of human beings simply because they lack the property of possessing rational agency and instead only stand in relation to it? The distinction seems arbitrary. |
19 | MacIntyre provides examples of animals who exhibit lower capacities of rational agency. If true, then humans would not be the only creatures who stand in some relation to the capacity for rational agency. A capacities approach would by implication confer a similar worth to these creatures. In fact, some species at maturation exhibit a greater capacity for rational agency than some humans will ever exhibit at maturation. It seems that this capacities approach would confer greater worth on these animals than the human beings in question. To retain its validity, Rothbard’s distinction between humans and animals requires a further distinction between human rationality and animal rationality. Moreover, Rothbard needs to show that human rationality and animal rationality are different in kind and not simply in degree. On a purely secular account, this distinction appears to be unwarranted. |
20 | Although Novak agrees with libertarians in their use of Austrian economics, he is influenced more by Mises and Hayek than he is by Rothbard and Hoppe, and while Novak does not adopt the consequentialist ethics of Mises or Hayek, he agrees with many of their views on the relationship of social, economic, and political institutions. This is not necessarily a strength, however, as Novak has been criticized at times for having too much confidence in political institutions. |
References
- Aquinas, Thomas. 1990. Summa of the Summa. Edited by Peter Kreeft. San Francisco: Ignatius Press. [Google Scholar]
- Attas, David. 2000. The Appeal of Self-Ownership. Social Theory and Practice 26: 1–23. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Block, Walter. 2015. Natural Law, Natural Rights, and Libertarianism. American Journal of Economics and Sociology 74: 29–62. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Crosby, John. 2006. The Witness of Dietrich von Hildebrand. First Things 168: 7–9. [Google Scholar]
- Gewirth, Alan. 1981. The Basis and Content of Human Rights. Nomos 23: 119–47. [Google Scholar]
- Hoppe, Hans-Hermann. 2012. Democracy: The God That Failed. New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers. [Google Scholar]
- Kinsella, Stephen. 1996. New Rationalist Directions in Libertarian Rights Theory. Journal of Libertarian Studies 12: 313–26. [Google Scholar]
- Klos, Jan. 2014. Free Persons—And Their Safe Journey Through Darkness. In Theologian and Philosopher of Liberty: Essays of Evaluation & Criticism in Honor of Michal Novak. Edited by Samuel Gregg. Grand Rapids: Acton Intstitute, pp. 105–24. [Google Scholar]
- Kuznicki, Jason. 2016. Kantianism. In Arguments for Liberty. Edited by Aaron Powell and Grant Babcock. Washington, DC: Cato Institute, pp. 87–122. [Google Scholar]
- MacIntyre, Alasdair C., and Paul Carus. 2011. Dependent Rational Animals: Why Human Beings Need the Virtues. Chicago: Open Court Press. [Google Scholar]
- Mack, Eric. 2016. Natural Rights. In Arguments for Liberty. Edited by Aaron Powell and Grant Babcock. Washington, DC: Cato, pp. 49–85. [Google Scholar]
- McElwee, Brian. 2010. Appeal to Self-Ownership. Social Theory and Practice 36: 213–32. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mises, Ludwig. 1979. Economic Policy: Thoughts for Today and Tomorrow. Chicago: Regnery Gateway. [Google Scholar]
- Novak, Michael. 1981. Toward A Theology of the Corporation. Washington, DC: American Enterprise Institute. [Google Scholar]
- Novak, Michael. 1989. Free Persons and the Common Good. Lanham: Madison Books. [Google Scholar]
- Novak, Michael. 1991. The Spirit of Democratic Capitalism. Lanham: Madison Books. [Google Scholar]
- Novak, Michael. 1996. Business as Calling: Work and the Examined Life. New York: The Free Press. [Google Scholar]
- Novak, Michael. 1999. Seven Whig Amendments to the Liberal Theory of Liberty. In On Cultivating Liberty: Reflections on Moral Ecology. Oxford: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, pp. 31–51. [Google Scholar]
- Novak, Michael. 2015. Catholic Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism. New York: Free Press. [Google Scholar]
- Nozick, Robert. 1974. Anarchy, State, and Utopia. New York: Basic. [Google Scholar]
- O’Donovan, Oliver, and Joan Lockwood O’Donovan. 1999. From Irenaeus to Grotius: A Sourcebook in Christian Political Thought. Grand Rapids: Eerdmans. [Google Scholar]
- Pilon, Roger. 1979. Ordering Rights Consistently: Or What We Do and Do Not Have Rights to. Georgie Law Review 13: 1171–96. [Google Scholar]
- Rothbard, Murray. 2012. The Ethics of Liberty. New York: New York University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Schlueter, Nathan. 2014. Libertarian Delusions. First Things 245: 45–50. [Google Scholar]
- Share, Cade. 2012. A Defense of Rothbardian Ethics via a Mediation of Hoppe and Rand. The Journal of Ayn Rand Studies 12: 117–50. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Shaw, Elizabeth. 2014. Intelligent Subjectivity: Into the Presence of God. In Theologian and Philosopher of Liberty: Essays of Evaluation & Criticism in Honor of Michal Novak. Edited by Samuel Gregg. Grand Rapids: Acton Institute, pp. 1–9. [Google Scholar]
- Tierney, Michael. 1997. The Idea of Natural Rights: Studies on Natural Rights: Studies in Natural Rights, Natural Law, and Church Law 1150–1625. Atlanta: Scholars Press. [Google Scholar]
- Tuck, Richard. 2002. Natural Rights Theory: Their Origin and Development. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Tucker, Jeffrey. 2014. Markets As Extended Communities. In Theologian and Philosopher of Liberty: Essays of Evaluation & Criticism in Honor of Michal Novak. Edited by Samuel Gregg. Grand Rapids: Acton Intstitute, pp. 11–22. [Google Scholar]
- Witherington, Ben. 2010. The Indelible Image: Theological and Ethical Thought of the World of the New Testament. 2 Vol. Lisle: Intervarsity Press. [Google Scholar]
- Wolterstorff, Nicholas. 2008. Justice: Rights and Wrongs. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2024 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Yonts, T.A. The Imago Dei and the Market Economy: Libertarian Tensions in Michael Novak’s Political Theology. Religions 2024, 15, 761. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15070761
Yonts TA. The Imago Dei and the Market Economy: Libertarian Tensions in Michael Novak’s Political Theology. Religions. 2024; 15(7):761. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15070761
Chicago/Turabian StyleYonts, Timothy A. 2024. "The Imago Dei and the Market Economy: Libertarian Tensions in Michael Novak’s Political Theology" Religions 15, no. 7: 761. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15070761
APA StyleYonts, T. A. (2024). The Imago Dei and the Market Economy: Libertarian Tensions in Michael Novak’s Political Theology. Religions, 15(7), 761. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel15070761