3.2. Theology and Time
Unlike philosophy, which views the time of our experience as being limited by death, theology speaks from beyond death. Theology implies a decision of faith, the only one capable of “winning the reality of
kairos”, the only one through which human existence is constituted as
esse coram Deo (
Lacoste 2024, p. 71). “Owing to its kairological content, this time structures itself by subverting the logic of any purely worldly temporalization” (
Wardley 2014, p. 167). There are two justifications for a theological discourse: (1) the arrival in time of the Absolute itself, through the Incarnation of Christ; and (2) the establishment of a temporality that escapes the logic of being toward death (
Lacoste 1990, p. 75).
Alongside theology, eternity, understood in a Christian sense, enters the scene as a promise of the past visible in the “words of eternal life” (John 6: 68) (
Lacoste 2024, p. 69). Of course, the promises of eternal life are excessive, so their truth is possible only insofar as they are uttered by a faithful God (
Lacoste 2024, pp. 84–85). However, from a phenomenological point of view, eternity is given in the experience of eschatological anticipation.
Lacoste analyzes the phenomenon of anticipation (
Lacoste 2018, pp. 112–33) and considers that it, before having religious relevance, is found in any sketch of a project and in any future promise, in its words, in any “pre-experience” and “pre-donation”. Given that the future phenomenon has not yet occurred but has its own importance in relation to the present, there is a “primacy of inexperience” that must be taken into account. However, this primacy does not cancel the present when it comes to the phenomenon of enjoyment, a phenomenon that is “self-sufficient and unimpaired” (
Lacoste 2018, p. 120). For the fullness of enjoyment, nothing else matters, neither past nor future. Any other simultaneous phenomenon is marginalized in this present of plenitude. The problem that arises is that enjoyment is episodic and, although desired, cannot be repeated under the same conditions. To overcome the suffering of the absence of enjoyment, we need fidelity and hope, two phenomena that anticipate the future. But this anticipation is not complete: “The anticipation appears to us in a ‘non-parousial’ way” (
Lacoste 2018, p. 125). This restrictive conclusion also applies to eschatological anticipation, which is also incomplete and incipient in relation to the future promise of the eschaton. The phenomenon of the eschaton is the model for understanding anticipation: incompleteness, pre-donation, and pre-experience are linked to the eschatological promise: “without eschatological promise eschatological anticipation cannot arise” (
Lacoste 2018, p. 133).
Through eschatological anticipation, liturgical time refers to eschatology. As K. J. Wardley points out, “Liturgical time—a time of inoperativity, of time given over—thus critiques
Dasein’s temporality by offering an alternative, a temporality neither imposed upon the world through consciousness nor determined by practical considerations, a temporality that rather than being determined by mortality, merely stretched between birth and death, looks instead towards eternity and asks what is mankind’s vocation” (
Wardley 2014, pp. 174–75). The opposite of the present is the parousia, the time of the final fulfillment, a time to come; however, compared to the parousia, we are in a penultimate situation (see
Lacoste 2012, pp. 7–10).
The liturgical nontime reveals an eschatological vigil for the one who prays to God as if God were present in the mode of parousia. But this closeness is always accompanied by the awareness of an even greater distance, because the eschaton is not definitively established. Lacoste thus opposes the Heideggerian being-in-the-world to the being-before-God and argues that there are two different kinds of temporalization: the first, in accordance with the logic of the world, and the second, in accordance with the logic of the liturgy. To Lacoste, “the time of liturgy is one of ‘disinterestedness’ in the world” (
Gschwandtner 2013, p. 172). The Absolute rejoices us liturgically in the time leading up to death, and “liturgy is the power to accept such a gift” (
Lacoste 2004, pp. 84–86). However, “Liturgy always remains ambiguous in its manifestation because the reality that is promised in it never becomes fully present” (
Gschwandtner 2013, p. 172). Therefore, the time of the liturgy, which “is far from being ‘inauthentic’ and ‘improper’” (
Schrijvers 2012, p. 7), does not forever suspend the time of the world; instead, it offers itself within it.
Lacoste expresses the same idea of the penultimate and the pre-eschatological when he talks about the present of tradition (
paradosis, in Greek). Tradition, understood both as transmission and content transmitted, can be thought of under the spectrum of four phenomena. To begin with, tradition expresses the new and eternal alliance between God and humankind, expressed in the words that have been transmitted. Secondly, tradition permits a present, which unites the promise of the past with the present of faith and with future hope. We note that Lacoste, although he does not use the term temporalization, refers to what we might call theological temporalization—a synthesis of the three temporal ecstasies, but this time within the horizon of faith. The present time of faith is a penultimate time, not the eschaton. Thirdly, tradition is also a happy memory, being at the service of the Church. Finally, tradition is qualified theologically as communion (
koinonia) and associated with the saints. In the case of the saints, the intersection between history and eschaton becomes visible in a phenomenon that Lacoste describes as “the pre-eschatological phenomenon par excellence” (
Lacoste 2024, pp. 119–22).
Through the Resurrection of Christ, God inaugurates an “eschatological way of life” (
Lacoste 1990, p. 76), in which the body transcends its role as merely a sign of worldly existence. In this context, theology emerges as “the science of the definitive”, which both contradicts the provisional and, paradoxically, is anticipated by it (
Lacoste 1990, p. 78).
Through the hypostatic union of the two natures, human and divine, in the divine-human person of Christ, time enters into relation with eternity, and they must be viewed as non-contradictory. Here is how this new logic is described: “On the one hand, temporality in its integral dimensions (the bodily relation to death included) does not exclude in Jesus of Nazareth a rigorously ecstatic relation with God (i.e., a relation in which ipseity is totally subordinate to, or revealed in, being-toward-death). And, on the other hand, the eternity of God, whatever we are to think under this concept, does not exclude a divine experience of temporality both because the human time of Jesus of Nazareth is wholly the human time of God, and because the Christological relation of God and man affects the form of temporalization and history, in which before and after find their meaning in God Himself—because for man, as well as for God, there was a ‘time’ in which God did not take the human condition. The Christological alliance of time and eternity establishes, less than it restores, the mutual non-contradiction of man’s temporality and God’s eternity” (
Lacoste 1990, p. 80).
3.4. Restlessness and Exposition
Consciousness is concerned with the future through care. “The future is the perpetual questioning of every present; that which does not exist exerts a surprising influence on that which is” (
Lacoste 1990, p. 169). Care is not the last word, however, because through eschatological hope, “the future ceases to press upon the present as a threat, and appears as a field of promise” (
Lacoste 1990, p. 205).
Lacoste provides a theological critique of the Heideggerian existential of care (Sorge); firstly, “filial non-care” (
Lacoste 1990, p. 207) and, secondly, eschatological restlessness. Restlessness, which relates to man’s religious destiny (
Lacoste 2004, p. 82), is the fundamental theological existential, which is not oriented ontologically and historically, but eschatologically (
Lacoste 1990, p. 97).
From the perspective of temporality, then, we would have the time of care, which passes toward death, and the time of restlessness, which aims at the Absolute. The two are in a dialectical relationship, because neither can definitively replace the other in this life. I disagree with the idea that, in Lacoste, there is a “rigid separation between the liturgical being [...] and the worldly
Besorgen” (
Marren 2020, p. 328). In my view, worldly care and eschatological restlessness do not cancel each other out definitively. The time of care and the time of restlessness both propose themselves, both intersect and return, in a never-ending dialectic (
Lacoste 1990, p. 100). But for the man who exposes himself to the Absolute, the man who has been called to an absolute future, the affection of restlessness is more fundamental than that of care, even if he recognizes himself as “caught up in the game of care” (
Lacoste 1990, p. 127). Man remains a prisoner of the world, but nothing can stop him from worrying about his absolute destiny and recognizing the anarchic power of eschatology toward the world (
Manoussakis 2009, p. 71).
The past becomes essential precisely in that God has already spoken in history. Tradition is the essential past. In this way, the three temporal ecstasies each have their own moment: the past has Tradition; the present has ethics; and the future has the project and the eschatological call (
Lacoste 1990, pp. 117–19). Restlessness targets the future that comes from beyond death.
Joeri Schrijvers has argued that restlessness still characterizes being-in-the-world, even though it is oriented outside the world, but without knowing the direction. “Restlessnes—Lacoste writes—is that mark of the humanity of man which removes man from every satisfaction to which world and earth hold the key, and grants to man the eschatological satisfaction that, by definition, the Absolute alone promises. The restless man can thus become bored with world and earth. He can dream of a beyond to world and earth. It is important in any case to emphasize that restlessness does not as such possess any knowledge. It is immemorially present” (
Lacoste 2004, pp. 198–99, n. 20). Still having an existential–ontological grounding—such as the Heideggerian care that it does not cancel, but disqualifies—restlessness merely opens up liturgical experience, orienting the human toward something other than the world: “restlessness as such is that mode of our being in which our boredom and dissatisfaction with being awakens a desire for an as yet undetermined ‘otherwise than being’” (
Schrijvers 2012, p. 59). It is not yet liturgical, but it has an ambiguous character and positions itself between the Heideggerian care and the Lacostian exposition, a new concept proposed by Lacoste. To clarify the ambiguous character of restlessness and given that it is eschatologically oriented, I have chosen to interpret it as being in opposition to the Heideggerian care, while the exposition would be Lacoste’s theological proposal in the face of the Heideggerian existential of openness. Thus, alongside intentionality, Lacoste adds a new theological concept: exposition. Husserl showed that the transcendental ego receives phenomena through intentionality, whereas Heidegger spoke of the openness (
Erschlossenheit) of
Dasein toward the world, a more primordial openness. Lacoste proposes a new determination of the ego and adds, alongside the transcendental ego,
Dasein, and the empirical I, an “eschatological I”, which he defines as follows: “the figure of the ego in which the relation to the Absolute is his lifeblood and suffices to define man” (
Lacoste 2004, pp. 57–58).
In his opinion, for the “eschatological I”, exposition plays the same role as intentionality, but the former is more adequate to explain the liturgical positioning of man. Although all three—intentionality, openness, and exposition—offer the phenomena they address, exposition, which has an ascetic charge of self-denial, can show God, even if not fully, but only in glimpses (
Lacoste 2004, pp. 41–42).
3.5. Liturgy as a Non-Event and Inexperience
The definitive is accessible through the provisional, i.e., on the horizon of the world (
Lacoste 1990, pp. 129–30). The liturgy transgresses history, it “makes diversion”, but only in anticipation, because the world and history are not transcended (
Lacoste 2004, p. 72). Liturgy could be thought of as a “nonevent”, insofar as the Absolute does not offer itself with evidence to the human being who manages the time of possibility (
Lacoste 2004, pp. 46–47). Since liturgical gestures are eschatologically oriented, Lacoste criticizes the term “religious experience” and proposes the term “inexperience” to emphasize the difference from phenomenological experience (
Lacoste 2004, pp. 46–49). Even if the eschatological I allows for the hermeneutic of the empirical I, there is no apodictic verification of God’s inexperience.
Lacoste does not view mystical experience as an eschatology already fulfilled in history. Any form of rest is rest ‘of something’ or ‘in view of something’; therefore, not eternal rest. “Experiences of peace and joy have the potential to overwhelm the
Daseinanalytik; although this being a phenomenologically grounded theology it is all too grounded in the plurality and diversity of our experiences, the possible ‘liturgical consummation’ of philosophy remains a possibility rather than a given” (
Wardley 2014, p. 192). Likewise, the experience of the definitive in time is not an available fulness, but only a pre-taste (
praegustatio), that is, a pre-experience (
préexpérience) (
Lacoste 2024, pp. 73–77).