Did God Cause the World by an Act of Free Will, According to Aristotle? A Reading Based on Thomistic Insights
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. A Preliminary Point: The Concept of “Will” in Aristotle
3. A Fundamental Text of Physics VIII
4. Texts Clearly Speaking of an Act of Divine Will as the Origin of the Order of the Cosmos
For in everything we say that nature desires what is better, but it is better to be than not to be, […] but this [sc. to be always] cannot happen in all, because they are removed far from the principle. God, then, filled the whole in the remaining manner, making generation uninterrupted; thus they are kept in being as much as possible, because this is the main way in which being is continued, by becoming and generation closest to substance [tês ousías].21
To be always is a property of divine being: this [sc. to be always] cannot be the case in all, because some are too far from the first principle, such as material things which are susceptible of generation and corruption. These things share little in divine being. For this reason, God fulfilled the desire of matter in a different way, by making everlasting their being [sc. of material things] through continuous generation. In this way their being continues, i.e., [in generation] it always happens that what is generated is a substance of the same species of the one generating it.22
5. Is the Divine Volitional Act That Gives Origin to the Cosmos Necessary?
6. Answer to a Difficulty: God Cannot Move from Not Causing to Causing; Therefore, Aristotle Concludes That the Cosmos Has an Infinite Past Duration: Does This Not Imply Necessity?
From what has been said we can infer that a reason can be assigned to the divine will. (1) The end is the reason for willing the things that are for the sake of the end. But God wills his own goodness as the end, and other things He wills as things that are for the sake of the end. His goodness, therefore, is the reason why He wills the other things which are different from Himself. (2) Again, a particular good is ordered to the good of the whole as to its end, as the imperfect to the perfect. Now, some things fall under the divine will according to their disposition in the order of the good. It remains, then, that the good of the universe is the reason why God wills each particular good in the universe. (3) Again, as was shown above, on the supposition that God wills something, it follows necessarily that He wills the things required for it. But that which imposes necessity on another is the reason why that other exists. Therefore, the reason why God wills the things that are required for each thing is that that thing be for which they are required.
Thus, therefore, can we proceed in assigning the reason of the divine will. God wills man to have a reason in order that man be; He wills man to be so that the universe may be complete;43 and He wills that the good of the universe be because it befits his goodness. However, this threefold reason does not proceed according to the same relationship. For the divine goodness neither depends on the perfection of the universe nor is anything added to it from this perfection. For, although the perfection of the universe necessarily depends on certain particular goods that are its essential parts, yet on some of them it does not depend of necessity, but nevertheless a certain goodness or adornment accrues to the universe from them, as from those things that exist only for the support or adornment of the other parts of the universe. A particular good depends necessarily on the things that are absolutely required for it, even though this too has certain things that are for its embellishment. Hence, at times the reason of the divine will contains only a befittingness; at other times, usefulness; at still other times, a necessity of supposition; but a necessity that is absolute only when it wills itself.44
7. Conclusions and Corollary
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
1 | On Plato see his works Republic 10, 616c-421a (Plato 1900c); and Timaeus 30a-31a (Plato 1900d). On Aristotle’s works, see Nicomachean Ethics 3.5.1113b3-114b25 (Aristotle 1962) and all the texts analyzed in this present paper. |
2 | See, for example, Metaphysics Lambda 10, 1175a16-24 (Aristotle 1895). The more the different levels of being share in intelligence, the more they share in order and are connected to the good of the whole through the tendencies of their respective natures, and the less their doings and sufferings are left to chance. According to Alberto Ross Hernández (2016), Alexander of Aphrodisias identified nature as a cause with fatum and as being opposed to chance, in the sublunary world. |
3 | At the time in which the 20th-century “traditional” interpretation of Aristotle was starting, Franz Brentano identified the influence of Hume’s conception of causality as the main factor in bringing about the belief that there is an incompatibility between the infinite past duration of the cosmos held by Aristotle, on the one hand, and God’s efficient causality of the being of the cosmos, on the other. Brentano clarified that the Humean conception of causality is entirely alien to the Aristotelian conception. See Brentano (1978, p. 62). |
4 | See (Judson 1994). See also Judson (2019, pp. 179, 202, 205–8). One presupposition of Judson’s views is that any efficient cause that transmits movement must “expend power” (see Judson 2019, pp. 206, 235). But, actually, this is not the case of an efficient cause that is completely spiritual or dispossessed of magnitude. Judson acknowledges that it might be the case that an efficient cause without magnitude does not “expend power” (see Judson 2019, p. 235), but then he returns to his belief that the Prime Mover moves only as final cause and is perplexed about why, then, according to Physics 8.10, a magnitude could not move eternally as final cause since in that way it does not need to “expend power”. A serious omission in Judson’s understanding is that he thinks that the natural movement of the heavens does not need an efficient or moving cause, precisely because it is natural. Consequently, he is perplexed about why a Prime Mover or kinetikón would be at all needed in Physics and conjectures that Aristotle must have suffered an important change of mind in between De Coelo and Physics (see Judson 2019, p. 178). But Aristotle is very clear that all that is moved is moved by another: the living being by an intrinsic unmoved mover (which cannot be the Prime Mover) and what is light or heavy is moved (even in its natural movements) by the cause that brings them into being and by the cause that removes the obstacle to their movement. See Aristotle (1879, Physics 8.4, 256a1-3). |
5 | Of course, here, “to remember” is alluding to the theory of anamnesis, which is an explanation about how we first acquired the experience of those realities that we contemplate in philosophy and other sciences. |
6 | See, for instance, the works by Jedan (2000), Mesch (2013) or Rapp (2017). Of course, I believe that Aristotle holds a sufficient notion of freedom, but I can only outline my position. However, the reasons I give below will prove the existence of freedom in God and a fortiori of freedom in Aristotle’s thought. |
7 | The reader should see the said paper by Irwin, where he succeeds in defending a very similar view. |
8 | Compare 1111b10-19 with Republic 4, 439a-441 d. |
9 | It is not appropriate to translate orektiké with the word “desire” because this English word does not cover all the wealth of meaning of that Greek word. It would be better to translate it as “inclination” or “tendency”, but really the Latin translation is best: appetitus, which in English can be expressed as “appetitive power”, as I have chosen to do. |
10 | Only among beings with intellect can there be philía. See Nicomachean Ethics 8.2, 1155b26-32; 11, 1161b1-8; 1162a4-5; 1163b15-19. |
11 | This is the reason why “justice” exists only among beings that have noûs (Nicomachean Ethics 5.9, 1137a26-30). Slaves can have friendship (Nicomachean Ethics 8.11, 1161b1-8) and virtue because they have lógos (Aristotle 1894, Politics 1.13, 1259b22-28 and 1260a14-24), and virtue can exist only among those who can choose (Nicomachean Ethics 2). The appetitive power of boúlesis is in the rational part of the soul. |
12 | |
13 | “[…] actio agentis per intellectum, non proportionatur naturae ipsius, sed formae apprehensae; non enim aedificator tantum aedificat quantum potest, sed quantum exigit ratio formae conceptae” (Aquinas 2000b, In octos libros Physicorum, lib. 8, l. 21, n. 10). |
14 | Lindsay Judson points out another reason why a finite magnitude cannot have infinite power in Aristotle. Metaphysics Book Λ (1919), pp. 193–94, namely: “his idea seems to be that, if the cause had magnitude, determinate amounts of power would be located in distinct spacial parts of the cause, and used up successively, like a series of batteries used one at a time”. This is not incompatible with what I hold in the text, but I am focusing on a particular argument of Physics 8.10. |
15 | Aristotle gives other reasons for postulating an incorporeal power: “that which exists without magnitude cannot be in motion” (267a22–3), and this is how the first mover can be motionless and the beginning of the chain of movers and moved. Moreover, “we have a mover that has no need to change along with that which it moves but will be able to always cause motion (because causing motion under these conditions requires no effort)” (267b22-3; see also Aristotle 1879, Physics 8.10, 266a10–267b26). What the first mover does is not to transmit physical energy, which cannot be done without undergoing change; what the first mover is doing is “touching without being touched”, as Aristotle (Physics 8.5, 258a18–22) states. And that is precisely what the intellectual substance, entirely incorporeal, does, and (analogously) so does the human will, in moving the body. |
16 | See Aristotle (1896), De anima 3.9 432b3–7; 10, 433a22–30; 11, 433b3–13; and Aristotle (1895), Metaphysics Lambda 7, 1072a26–30 and 1072a34–b5. Regarding the action that conforms to the conception of the intellect, see the general description of téchne by Aristotle (1962), Nicomachean Ethics 6.4, 1140a6-14, and its application to theology here, Metaphysics Lambda 10, 1075b8-10. |
17 | As I will show below, there are texts that allow us to attribute “will” to Aristotle’s God. This interpretation has been defended by Brentano (1977, pp. 175–77), Berti (1977, pp. 435–36; 2005, p. 747), De Koninck (2008, p. 130), George (2010, pp. 4–5) and Torrijos-Castrillejo (2013). |
18 | That the vegetative soul is the source of nourishment, growth and reproduction can be seen in De anima 2.4, 416a6-9. That the sensitive soul is the origin of the animals’ movements can be seen in De anima 3.9-10. That the soul is an unmoved mover can be seen in Physics 8.5, 258a1-4. |
19 | On the way in which these substances know, see Aristotle (1896), De anima 3.6, 430b20ff. It is presupposed here that there cannot be causes separate from matter, and moreover, there cannot be intelligibles that are not intelligences (or acts of intelligences). On the fact that their contemplating another substance implies that they are not the highest substance and that their substance is not their operation, see Metaphysics Lambda 9, 1074b18-21. Lindsay Judson interprets this passage differently in 2019, pp. 306–307. Instead, Aryeh Kosman interprets it in the same way as I do. See Kosman (2000), p. 314. |
20 | |
21 | Aristotle (1922), my translation. Note how Plato (1900a, Symposium 206c) resonates here. A similar idea is repeated in De anima 2.4, 415a26-b7: living beings participate as much as they can in eternity and divinity through the generation of other beings similar to them. In Aristotle (1962), Nicomachean Ethics 10.7, 1177b31–34, this subject is dealt with once more, and again closely following Plato’s Symposium (212a): man may imitate God not only through generation but also through contemplation, and in this latter way, he “immortalizes” himself as much as possible. |
22 | Aquinas (2000a), In De generatione et corruptione, lib. 2, l. 10, n. 7. My translation. Actually, in inanimate things, the substance generated by other non-living substance might be of a different species, but it belongs always to the same genus. According to Aristotle (1922), there is a cycle in the generation and corruption of inanimate things (De generatione et corruptione 2.11, 338a2–11). |
23 | |
24 | See Aquinas (2000b), In octos libros Physicorum, lib. 2, l. 12, n. 1; and Aquinas (2000d), Summa theologiae I q. 2, a. 3, c. St. Thomas states in his commentary on Physics: “Ea enim quae non cognoscunt finem, non tendunt in finem nisi ut directa ab aliquo cognoscente, sicut sagitta a sagittante: unde si natura operetur propter finem, necesse est quod ab aliquo intelligente ordinetur; quod est providentiae opus”. Aristotle explicitly states that there is divine providence: see Aristotle (1962), Nicomachean Ethics 10.8, 1179a22–32. I have proved that, actually, this is Aristotle’s mature thesis, that there is providence: see Casanova (2016). Brentano (1978, pp. 58–60) and contemporary interpreters such as George (2010), Torrijos-Castrillejo (2012, p. 13) and Pelletier (2020) agree with my interpretation. |
25 | In Aristotle (1895), Metaphysics Lambda 10, 1075a11–15 Aristotle has stated that God is the highest good. Lindsay Judson comments on this passage (Judson 2019, pp. 356–57), but he seems to overlook that it poses a problem for his general interpretation of Lambda. Indeed, if the highest Intellect as an efficient cause acts for the sake of the highest good, then it seems that the Intellect would not be the highest cause. Anaxagoras, when stating that the Intellect alone was the highest cause, touched on this problem but did not understand it in all its depth. Aristotle solves the problem because he knows how to reduce the good for which the craftsman acts to the craft that is the principle of action in the craftsman. Thus, the poietikón (not mere kinetikón) conceives precisely the good that He wants to produce, and in His act of understanding, the form understood and that good are one. Judson (2019) seems to criticize Aristotle because he does not mention Plato’s Timaeus, where “the Demiurge is portrayed as a divine and rational moving cause”. But the reason for that is simple: Plato’s demiurge acts for the sake of the highest good, which in Plato’s understanding is a different entity. |
26 | A post-Jaegerian reader may ask whether Aristotle’s mind did not change during his long philosophical career. To this concern, I reply that it did, and considerably. In his youth, as a Platonist, he believed in separate forms. When he realized that they could not exist, his theology went through a crisis. One can feel that in some passages of Posterior Analytics where he talks about the science that he later will call “wisdom”, “first philosophy”, or “theology” as if that science were a hypothesis (see Aristotle 1964, Posterior Analytics 1.11, 77a25–35, for example). Moreover, in some passages of the Metaphysics, he uses the expression “the sought for science” (see Aristotle 1895, Metaphysics Alpha 1–2, 981b27–982a6; 982b5–10). The reason is that he needed to discover that there were formalities that, being metacategorial (being, good, one, intelligible), can be predicated of both suprasensible and sensible realities in order to establish the new science of first philosophy in place of Plato’s dialectics. Once he made this discovery, he established his theology, which did not suffer drastic changes or revisions afterwards. |
27 | |
28 | The statement in the text depends on the following reasoning: if one thing is directed to an end by a natural desire, such desire does not depend on the knowledge that such a thing might have, since it is previous to such knowledge. But the direction of all desires depends on knowledge. For this reason, natural desires must depend on the knowledge of the Author of nature. Aristotle does not state this, but he comes very close in Physics 2.8, 199b26-32. Regarding the dependence of secondary separate substance from the first, see Aristotle (1895), Metaphysics Lambda 8, 1073a23–24 (God is called here “the principle and the first of beings”), 1073a30 (here God is called “the first substance”) and 1073b1–3 (here Aristotle states that among the separate substances there is one that is first, another one is second, and so on. He states, moreover, that the order of the substances may be known through the order of the moving spheres); and 9, 1074b29–30. Note that in Lambda 8, 1074a31-37, after stating that there are many separate substances, Aristotle adds that the first is only one, both in species and in number. In Metaphysics alfa élatton 1, 993b19-31, Aristotle argues explicitly that the community of the name “truth” [intelligibility], which is not mere equivocation, must come from what is Truest. He concludes the passage thus: “as each thing is in respect of being, so it is in respect of truth”. But it is clear that the First Substance is the Highest Being. Therefore, it must be the Truest reality. Actually, without the community of name coming through efficient causality from the Truest, the Aristotelian cosmos would be much more episodic than the Platonic. In the Platonic, there was at least an explanation (through Ideas and participation) of the community of name. But I cannot in this context go further in this direction. For further development on this point, I suggest that the reader look at my previous work. See Casanova 2007, pp. 95-155. |
29 | See Aristotle (1962), Nicomachean Ethics 10.7, especially 1177a27–1178a8, where Aristotle deals both with the self-sufficiency that is proper for the highest happiness and with how it assimilates us to God. God is the happiest and most self-sufficient being because He needs nothing outside of Himself. He just contemplates Himself and in Himself he knows everything else. |
30 | See Aristotle (1962), Nicomachean Ethics 8.8, 1059a27–b1; 9.4, 1166a2–6. For instance, Flannery (1999, pp. 134–35) acknowledges that Aristotle’s God loves men with a love of friendship, although He does not need them. |
31 | Lindsay Judson states that a mover without magnitude could be unmoved. However, he seems to suppose that as long as it transfers power, it cannot be really unmoved like the object of desire (see Judson 2019, pp. 206, 235). He is taking “movement” in De anima 3.10 in the strict sense that has an intermediate state between the initial one and the final one (see Judson 2019, p. 179), which Aristotle denies of sense perception and of intellectual grasping (see De anima 3.7, 433a27-b10). But Aristotle states as well that intellectual grasping has a greater degree of immobility (see De anima 4, 429a29-b5 and 429b22-430a9). Thus, perceiving is a “movement” of a species different from the physical movement because in the former there is no intermediate state as there is in the latter: perceiving is act of the being in act not of the being in potency. The same thing is said of “desiring” in De anima 3.7, 17-18: it is a “movement” of that which is in act. This is why even animals’ souls, qua agents, are unmoved movers. But a greater degree of immobility belongs to the appetite belonging to reason, boúlesis. What Aristotle is arguing in Metaphysics Lambda 7, 1072b14 is precisely that the First Substance (not just “Prime Mover”) moves as an agent with the same immobility as the object of love. That is, among the agents, the first one has the greatest degree of immobility. |
32 | The necessity is probably stronger: if matter is a necessary being by itself, not created, then God must have caused necessarily, although He did not cause necessarily this concrete cosmos. Here Brentano’s view (explained in the next note) can come into place, since he thought that God created the separate substances, the human intellects and matter and in that way he presents the Aristotelian as a complete, coherent view of the cosmos in which God’s autarchía would really be totally independent from matter. However, it seems to me that Aristotle had the true insight that matter is a necessary [principle of] being and could not come to conceive that its necessity could be dependent on an original divine act of creation out of nothing. |
33 | Even in the foundational discussion between David Ross and Franz Brentano, we see this subject emerge. Indeed, against Brentano, who held that according to Aristotle God created the world from eternity, Ross argues that “the spheres in so far as they have hýle cannot have been thought of as created by God, for hýle is what making presupposes and what therefore cannot be made” (1914, p. 291). The truth is that Brentano’s position is very strong. It is clear that human intellects come to be (as he argued and Ross and Zeller contested) and that, since they are incorporeal, they do not come to be through natural change and generation. Moreover, if, as Brentano plausibly holds, the being of the secondary separate substances depends on the first substance (since their operations do depend on the first substance, as most interpreters accept, including Lindsay Judson: see Judson 2019, pp. 330–31, 341), this dependence seems to suggest an eternal creation. Certainly, since the being of the spiritual substances, including the human intellect, is much more solid than the being of material realities, and if it is plausible to hold that incorporeal substances were caused by God, according to Aristotle, then it seems plausible to argue, as Brentano did, that matter was also produced by God, although not through natural change. But this is what I deny in the body of the article because I do not see that Aristotle draws the necessary consequences that would follow from holding this position. |
34 | |
35 | See Aristotle (1961), De partibus animalium 1.1, 639b19–21. Here, Aristotle calls this final cause the lógos (the reason, ratio) of things, and he states that art or craft is a lógos without matter (see 640a33–34). In all this, it is easy to perceive the connection between divine Art of Craft, on the one hand, and nature, on the other. How could there be lógos in nature without an intellectual cause? In De partibus animalium 1.5, 644b23–645b, Aristotle states that when contemplating the works of the art of painting or of sculpture, which are mere imitations of nature, we experience a great pleasure because in them we co-contemplate the art itself that devised them. He adds that a similar pleasure exists when we contemplate the works of nature, since in them, we can contemplate [kathorân] the causes. This passage of De partibus animalium is relevant for an additional reason. Werner Jaeger took it to belong to the last intellectual period of Aristotle which is the less Platonic period. See Jaeger (1934, pp. 337–41). Despite this, the doctrine of the passage is extremely close to that of Plato (1900c, Republic 3, 401a–2a). |
36 | Aristotle (1961), De partibus animalium 1.1, 641b16–18. See up to line 642a2. Aquinas corrects Aristotle regarding the explanation of the non-generability of heaven. He argues that it is not due to being composed of a matter different from the sub-lunar sphere, but to a disposition of the celestial matter to a different kind of form (a heavenly one), a kind of form that can entirely actualize the potentiality of matter (Aquinas 2000e, In libros de coelo et mundo, lib. 1, l. 6, n. 6). This is interesting because, contrary to what many Thomists hold, Aquinas teaches that “potencies are diversified according to their order to a diversity of acts”. Besides this, he follows Aristotle in holding that heaven is non-generable, and thinks that Aristotle and other philosophers came to know the creation of heaven itself (an emanation [effluvium] from the first principle), although they understood it to be coeternal with God, while “we state that the heaven was caused by God according to the whole of its substance [sc. the heaven’s] from a particular initial instant in time” (n. 7). |
37 | |
38 | Brentano (1977, p. 134) sustained this opinion. |
39 | In Metaphysics Lambda 10, Aristotle points out that the cosmos has been ordered by God, but the lowest parts in it were left more to chance than the upper parts. I agree that there is chance in the universe, but if Aristotle had known that God created matter, he would know, as Aquinas did, that even chance is subject to God’s providence. In Physics 2.6, 198a1 ff. Aristotle divides, like Plato, the most general (efficient) causes into three: nature, art and chance. In the commentary on this passage, St. Thomas makes an observation beyond what the text states (introduced by the typical expression “considerandum est autem”) to point out that chance is subject to a superior cause that orders it. In comparison with it, it is not “chance”, even if it is chance in comparison with its effects. Aristotle, as far as my knowledge goes, never made such a remark, but, on the contrary, he seems to speak of chance as something that originates at one of the two poles of the cosmos and is not subject to the other pole. |
40 | |
41 | |
42 | See Aquinas (2000c), Suma contra gentiles 1, chapter 84: “Secundum hoc […] quod aliquid repugnat rationi entis inquantum huiusmodi, non potest in eo salvari similitudo primi esse, scilicet divini, quod est fons essendi. Non potest igitur Deus velle aliquid quod repugnat rationi entis inquantum huiusmodi”. For more on this question, see Brock (1993). |
43 | Note the closeness of Aquinas’ choice of words here to that of Aristotle in De generatione et corruptione 2.10. |
44 | |
45 | See Aristotle (1895), Metaphysics Lambda 7, 1072b18–30. Joy or pleasure presupposes love. Aristotle explicitly attributes to God the activity of loving in other passages, as when he states that there are men who are loved by the gods: see, for example, Aristotle (1962), Nicomachean Ethics 10.8,1179a22–32 and Aristotle (1935), Eudemian Ethics 7.14,1247a27–1248b6. But, besides this, although Aristotle rejects the Delphian separation of the most beautiful, the best and the most pleasant, he agrees that “the most pleasant is that somebody achieves what he loves” (Nicomachean Ethics 1.8, 1099a28). His agreement is clear in Nicomachean Ethics 10.4, 1175a10–16, where he holds that pleasure makes perfect the activities or operations and, in that context, states: “each one exercises the faculties [that he most loves] and concerning the things that he most loves”. |
References
- Aquinas, Thomas. 1958–1962. Commentary on Aristotle’s Physics. Translated by Pierre H. Conway. Columbus: College of St. Mary of the Springs. Available online: https://isidore.co/aquinas/Physics.htm (accessed on 23 December 2024).
- Aquinas, Thomas. 1975. Summa Contra Gentiles. Translated by Anton Pegis. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press. Available online: https://isidore.co/aquinas/ContraGentiles1.htm (accessed on 23 December 2024).
- Aquinas, Thomas. 2000a. In De Generatione et Corruptione. Edited by Enrique Alarcón. Pamplona: Universidad de Navarra. Available online: https://www.corpusthomisticum.org/xgc.html (accessed on 23 December 2024).
- Aquinas, Thomas. 2000b. In Octos Libros Physicorum. Edited by Enrique Alarcón. Pamplona: Universidad de Navarra. Available online: https://www.corpusthomisticum.org/cpy012.html (accessed on 23 December 2024).
- Aquinas, Thomas. 2000c. Summa Contra Gentiles. Edited by Enrique Alarcón. Pamplona: Universidad de Navarra. Available online: https://www.corpusthomisticum.org/scg1072.html (accessed on 23 December 2024).
- Aquinas, Thomas. 2000d. Summa Theologiae. Edited by Enrique Alarcón. Pamplona: Universidad de Navarra. Available online: https://www.corpusthomisticum.org/sth1002.html (accessed on 23 December 2024).
- Aquinas, Thomas. 2000e. In Libros de Coelo et Mundo. Edited by Enrique Alarcón. Pamplona: Universidad de Navarra. Available online: https://www.corpusthomisticum.org/ccm1.html (accessed on 23 December 2024).
- Aristotle. 1879. Physics. Leipzig: Teubner. [Google Scholar]
- Aristotle. 1881. De coelo. In De Coelo et De Generatione et Corruptione. Leipzig: Teubner. [Google Scholar]
- Aristotle. 1894. Politica. Leipzig: Teubner. [Google Scholar]
- Aristotle. 1895. Metaphysics. Leipzig: Teubner. [Google Scholar]
- Aristotle. 1896. De Anima. Leipzig: Teubner. [Google Scholar]
- Aristotle. 1922. De Generatione et Corruptione. Edited by Harold Joachim. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Aristotle. 1935. Eudemian Ethics. In The Athenian Constitution, The Eudemian Ethics, On Virtues and Vices. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Aristotle. 1960. Topika. In Posterior Analytics and Topica. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Aristotle. 1961. De partibus animalium. In Parts of Animals, Movement of Animals, Progression of Animals. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Aristotle. 1962. Nicomachean Ethics. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Aristotle. 1964. Analytica posteriora. In Analytica Priora et Posteriora. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Berti, Enrico. 1977. Aristotele: Dalla Dialettica alla Filosofia Prima. Padova: CEDAM. [Google Scholar]
- Berti, Enrico. 2000. Metaphysics Lambda 6. In Aristotle’s Metaphysics Lambda. Edited by Michael Frede and David Charles. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Berti, Enrico. 2005. Il dio di Aristotele. Humanitas 60: 732–50. [Google Scholar]
- Bradshaw, David. 2001. A New Look at the Prime Mover. Journal of he History of Philosophy 39: 1–22. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Brentano, Franz. 1977. The Psychology of Aristoteles. In Particular His Doctrine of the Active Intellect. With an Appendix Concerning the Activity of Aristotle’s God. Translated by Rolf George. Berkeley: University of California Press. [Google Scholar]
- Brentano, Franz. 1978. Aristotle and His World View. Translated by Rolf George, and Roderick M. Chisholm. Berkeley: University of California Press. [Google Scholar]
- Broadie, Sarah. 2009. Heavenly Bodies and First Causes. In A Companion to Aristotle. Edited by Georgios Anagnostopoulos. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell, pp. 230–41. [Google Scholar]
- Brock, Stephen L. 1993. The ratio omnipotentiae in Aquinas. Acta Philosophica 2: 17–42. [Google Scholar]
- Casanova, Carlos A. 2007. El Ser, Dios y la Ciencia, Según Aristóteles. Santiago: Ediciones UC. [Google Scholar]
- Casanova, Carlos A. 2013. Dios como causa eficiente del ser del cosmos, según Aristóteles (y desde Aristóteles). Acta Philosophica 22: 279–301. [Google Scholar]
- Casanova, Carlos A. 2016. Is There Providence According to Aristotle? Nova et Vetera 14: 199–226. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- De Koninck, Thomas. 2008. Aristote, l’intelligence et Dieu. Paris: PUF. [Google Scholar]
- Flannery, Kevin. 1999. Un aristotelico può considerarsi amico di Dio? In Domanda sul Bene e Domanda su Dio. Edited by Livio Melina and José Noriega. Mursia: Pontificia Università Lateranense, pp. 131–37. [Google Scholar]
- George, Marie. 2010. Would Aristotle Agree with St. John that “God is Love”? The Aquinas Review 17: 1–43. [Google Scholar]
- Gilson, Etienne. 1944. La philosophie au Moyen Age. Paris: Payot. [Google Scholar]
- Irwin, Terence. 1992. Who Discovered the Will? In Philosophical Perspectives 6: Ethics. Edited by James E. Tomberlin. Atascadero: Ridgeview, pp. 453–73. [Google Scholar]
- Jaeger, Werner. 1934. Aristotle. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Jedan, Christoph. 2000. Willensfreiheit bei Aristoteles? Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht. [Google Scholar]
- Judson, Lindsay. 1994. Heavenly Motion and the Unmoved Mover. In Self Motion from Aristotle to Newton. Edited by M.L. Gill and J. Lenox. Princeton: Princeton University Press, pp. 115–71. [Google Scholar]
- Judson, Lindsay. 2019. Aristotle. Metaphysics Lambda. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kosman, Aryeh. 2000. Metaphysics Lambda 9: Divine Thought. In Aristotle’s Metaphysics Lambda. Edited by Michael Frede and David Charles. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Mesch, Walter. 2013. War Aristoteles ein Determinist? Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 67: 113–31. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pelletier, Yvan. 2020. Le Dieu d’Aristote: Omniscient, créateur et providence. Περιπατετικός = Peripatetikos: The Journal of the Society for Aristotelian-Thomistic Studies 15: 103–73. [Google Scholar]
- Plato. 1900a. Symposium. In Platonis Opera. Oxford: Clarendon Press, tomus 2. [Google Scholar]
- Plato. 1900b. Phaedrus. In Platonis Opera. Oxford: Clarendon Press, tomus 2. [Google Scholar]
- Plato. 1900c. Republic. In Platonis Opera. Oxford: Clarendon Press, tomus 4. [Google Scholar]
- Plato. 1900d. Timaeus. In Platonis Opera. Oxford: Clarendon Press, tomus 4. [Google Scholar]
- Plato. 1900e. Laws. In Platonis Opera. Oxford: Clarendon Press, tomus 5-1. [Google Scholar]
- Rapp, Christof. 2017. Tackling Aristotle’s Notion of the Will. Philosophical Inquiry 41: 67–79. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ross, David. 1914. Review of Franz Brentano, Aristoteles Lehre vom Ursprung des Menschlichen Geistes (Leipzig: Veit & Co., 1911) in Mind. A Quarterly Review on Psychology and Philosophy XXIII: 289–91. [Google Scholar]
- Ross Hernández, Alberto. 2007. La causalidad del Primer Motor en Metafísica XII, Dianoia 52/59. Available online: https://www.scielo.org.mx/scielo.php?script=sci_arttext&pid=S0185-24502007000200001 (accessed on 23 December 2024).
- Ross Hernández, Alberto. 2016. Causality, Nature and Fate in Alexander of Aphrodisias. Acta Philosophica 2: 319–32. Available online: https://www.actaphilosophica.it/article/view/3791/1902 (accessed on 23 December 2024).
- Scholem, Gershom. 1995. Major Trends in Jewish Mysticism. New York: Schocken Books. [Google Scholar]
- Spinoza, Baruch. 2006. Ethics. In The Essential Spinoza. Ethics and Related Writings. Edited by Michael L. Morgan. Translated by Samuel Shirley. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, pp. 1–161. [Google Scholar]
- Taylor, Michael. 2007. The Philosophy of Herbert Spencer. London: Continuum. [Google Scholar]
- Torrijos-Castrillejo, David. 2012. Dios en la ética de Aristóteles. Pensamiento 68: 5–23. [Google Scholar]
- Torrijos-Castrillejo, David. 2013. La causalidad del motor inmóvil. Hypnos 31: 234–66. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2025 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Casanova, C.A. Did God Cause the World by an Act of Free Will, According to Aristotle? A Reading Based on Thomistic Insights. Religions 2025, 16, 52. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16010052
Casanova CA. Did God Cause the World by an Act of Free Will, According to Aristotle? A Reading Based on Thomistic Insights. Religions. 2025; 16(1):52. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16010052
Chicago/Turabian StyleCasanova, Carlos A. 2025. "Did God Cause the World by an Act of Free Will, According to Aristotle? A Reading Based on Thomistic Insights" Religions 16, no. 1: 52. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16010052
APA StyleCasanova, C. A. (2025). Did God Cause the World by an Act of Free Will, According to Aristotle? A Reading Based on Thomistic Insights. Religions, 16(1), 52. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16010052