Cognitio Dei Experimentalis—Experimentalis et Vera Sapientia Bonaventure on the Experiential Knowledge of God in the Commentary on the Sentences and in De scientia Christi
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. The Experiential Knowledge of God in the Commentary on the Sentences
2.1. Experiential Knowledge
2.2. The Experiential Knowledge of God and the Spiritual Gift of Wisdom—III Sent d. 35
2.2.1. The Context of the Question: Theology as Science and Wisdom
- Intellect in itself—habitus of contemplation—properly speculative science;
- Intellect extended to work—habitus of becoming good—practical/moral science;
- Intellect extended to the affect—intermediate habitus between the purely speculative and the practical—wisdom. (Bonaventura 1882, I Sent Prooem., q. 3)10
2.2.2. The Spiritual Gift of Wisdom and the Experiential Knowledge of God
Quarto modo dicitur sapientia magis proprie, et sic nominat cognitionem Dei experimentalem; et hoc modo est unum de septem donis Spiritus Sancti, cuius actus consistit in degustando divinam suavitatem. Et quoniam ad gustum interiorem, in quo est delectatio, necessario requiritur actus affectionis ad coniugendum et actus cognitionis ad apprehendum, secundum illud Philosophi, qui dicit quod “delectatio est coniunctio convenientis cum convenienti cum sensu eiusdem”, hinc est quod actus doni sapientiae partim est cognitivus et partim est affectivus, ita quod in cognitione inchoatur et in affectione consummatur, secundum quod ipse gustus vel saporatio est experimentalis boni et dulcis cognitio. Et ideo actus praecipuus doni sapientiae propriissime dictae est ex parte affectivae (…).(Bonaventura 1887, III Sent d. 35, a. 1, q. 1)16
2.3. The Experience of the Divine in Christ—III Sent d. 16
Tertia suppositio est, quod Christus simul erat viator et comprehensor, ita quod viatoris cognitio non impediebat comprehensoris cognitionem, nec affectio affectionem; et illud fuit in Christo singulare propter officium mediatoris, quo debebat experiri et divina et humana. Unde sicut simul et semel poterat perfecte converti ad Deum et converti ad nos, ita quod una illarum conversionum alteram non impediebat nec retardabat; sic potuit secundum eandem partem animae simul et semel gaudere in Deo et compati corpori suo, ita quod nec dolor a gaudio, nec gaudium a dolore pateretur aliquam diminutionem sive remissionem.(Bonaventura 1887, III Sent d. 16, a. 2, q. 2, concl.)25
2.4. Respondeo Dicendum—Reflections on the Commentary on the Sentences
2.4.1. The Function of Experiential-Mystical Theology
Common wisdom—philosophical wisdom—wisdom in speculative theology; theological wisdom—wisdom as a gift of the Holy Spirit; experiential knowledge of God; experiential-sapiential theology—wisdom in mystical theology.
2.4.2. Christ’s Experience of God—Hypothetical Conclusion
2.4.3. The Experience of Christ the Mediator
3. Christ’s Experiential Knowledge of God in De Scientia Christi
3.1. Context
3.2. Christ’s Knowledge of the Uncreated Wisdom per Excessum—De Scientia Christi q. 6
Et quoniam anima illa Verbo unita et magis est deiformis effecta et magis inebriata propter gratiam non tantum sufficientem, sed etiam superexcellentem; ideo contuetur divinam sapientiam et contuendo excedit in ipsam, licet non comprehendat eam. Et pro hac causa admiratio non tantum habet locum in via, verum etiam in patria; non tantum in Angelis, verum etiam in anima assumpta a Deo.(Bonaventura 1891b, Scien.Chr. q. 6, concl.)34
3.3. Christ’s Knowledge of the Infinite Things Contained in Uncreated Wisdom per Excessum—De Scientia Christi q. 7
Hic autem modus cognoscendi per excessum est in via et in patria; sed in via ex parte, in patria vero est perfecte in Christo et in aliis comprehensoribus; sed in aliis est coarctate tum ex parte mensurae propriae gratiae, tum ex parte voluntatis divinae, quae non se cuilibet offert in omnimoda familiaritate; sed in anima Christi est liberalissime, tum quia ab ipsa habet gratiam implentem omnimode capacitatem suam, tum quia speculum aeternum praebet se ei manifestabile secundum familiaritatem omnimodam.(Bonaventura 1891b, Scien.Chr. q. 7, concl.)39
Secundum statum viae et secundum statum patriae non solum requiritur lucis aeternae praesentia, sed etiam lucis aeternae influentia, non tantum verbum increatum, sed etiam verbum interius conceptum; quod cum sit finitum, nec anima Christi nec aliqua alia anima potest esse comprehensiva Verbi aeterni nec scibilium infinitorum, licet in ea ferri habeat per excessum; qui quidem excessus est ultimus modus cognoscendi et nobilissimus, quem in omnibus libris suis laudat Dionysius, et maxime in libro de Mystica Theologia. De quo etiam mystice quasi est tota Scriptura divina, et de quo Apocalypsis secundo (Rev 2:17): Dabo ei calculum et in calculo nomen novum scriptum, quod nemo scit, nisi qui accipit; quia istum cognoscendi modum vix aut numquam intelligit nisi expertus, nec expertus, nisi qui est in caritate radicatus et fundatus, ut possit comprehendere cum omnibus Sanctis, quae sit longitudo, latitudo etc.; in quo etiam experimentalis et vera consistit sapientia, quae inchoatur in via et consummatur in patria; ad cuius circumlocutionem magis sunt idoneae negationes quam affirmationes, et superpositiones quam positivae praedicationes; ad cuius experientiam plus valet internum silentium quam exterius verbum. Et ideo hic finis verbi habendus est, et orandus Dominus, ut experiri donet quod loquimur.(Bonaventura 1891b, Scien.Chr. q. 7, concl.)41
3.4. Respondeo Dicendum—Reflections on De scientia Christi
“But here Bonaventure goes beyond his Victorine predecessors. When they encountered the loveless, mostly Christless Mystical Theology, they added love. Bonaventure’s use of The Mystical Theology adds not only love but also Christ, for in his reading the Dionysian darkness equals death and resurrection with Christ: ‘With Christ crucified, let us pass out of the world to the Father’. As he said at the outset, “there is no other path but through the burning love of the Crucified”. In sharing with Bernard and Francis a non-Dionysian devotion to Christ in the flesh, Bonaventure invoked the Areopagite’s authority only where it fit into his own tradition. Nevertheless, his creative work is the culmination of the Victorines’ integration of Dionysian darkness into the Western legacy of love for Christ crucified, and an echo of Paul’s original answer to the Athenians’ unknown God. It may seem incongruous to pair the Areopagite’s apophatic cloud with Francis’s ardent stigmata, but not to someone of Bonaventure’s synthetic genius”.
4. Conclusions
Funding
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Here we are thinking in particular of the reflections of Balthasar and LaNave, which show that, for Bonaventure, the primary object of spiritual perception is Christ himself and the various aspects of the mystery of Christ (verbum increatum, incarnatum, inspiratum). For more detail, see (Puskás 2024). Shelby also analyses in depth the Christological and soteriological foundations of Bonaventure’s doctrine of grace, when he emphasizes the role of Christ (hierarcha) in the hierarchization of the soul. |
2 | The theme of the 14th distinction of the third book of the Commentary on the Sentences is the analysis of the knowledge of Christ. Although in some respects the Seraphic Doctor draws parallels here between the knowledge of the human soul of Christ and the knowledge of other saints concerning God—for example, knowledge is created by wisdom as the effect of the Word (Bonaventura 1887, III Sent d. 14, a. 1, q. 1), the soul comes to know the eternal Word by non-comprehensive knowledge (Bonaventura 1887, III Sent d. 14, a. 1, q. 2)—he does not employ the vocabulary characteristic of experiential knowledge. The “excessus” (excedit in infinitum) of which he speaks here (Bonaventura 1887, III Sent d. 14, a. 1, q. 3, ad 4) refers only to the fact that the knowledge of the human soul of Christ infinitely exceeds the knowledge of others. |
3 | 3. In his monograph, Karl-Heinz Hoefs merely refers to the 7th question of De scientia Christi, without any explanation or analysis. (Hoefs 1989, pp. 89–90). Katherine Wrisley Shelby takes a position on De scientia Christi only in relation to quaestio 4, citing Joshua Benson (Shelby 203, p. 205). Interestingly, Ilia Delio also does not address the work De scientia Christi in his study on Christ-cantered theology and spirituality (Delio 2014). Robert Glenn Davis quotes and describes some of the basic ideas of question 7 of De scientia Christi. (Davis 2017, pp. 42–44). The guiding aspect of his interpretation is a general illumination of the nature of affectus/amor in its relation to cognition. To this end, he offers the example of the “excessivus modus cognoscendi” in the soul of Christ, which he reads as describing the characteristic movement of affectus/amor as opposed to the movement characteristic of cognition of the intellect (cognitio intellectus). In contrast, our interpretive concern is with the relationship between the experiential knowledge of God in Christ and in the saints. A further difference is that our analysis includes quaestio 6 of De scientia Christi. |
4 | Some examples: per sensibile experimentum (Bonaventura 1885, II Sent d. 13, a. 3, q. 1, ad 2); experimento, per experientiam (Bonaventura 1885, II Sent d. 14, p. 1, a. 1, q. 1, concl.); experientia sensus (Bonaventura 1885, II Sent d. 14, p. 1, a. 2, q. 1); per sensus experientiam (Bonaventura 1885, II Sent d. 14, p. 2, a. 2, q. 2, arg. 2). |
5 | Bonaventure adds, however, that the divine acceptance of man’s faith and love cannot be experienced and known with full certainty, but only with probable certainty. (Bonaventura 1887, III Sent d. 23, a. 1, dub. 4). |
6 | Bonaventure says that the knowledge of angels may be innate in them, but may also come from revelation, from their own effort and experience. From the latter, they may also have some knowledge of future events. |
7 | The author emphasizes that the formula is used literally only once by Bonaventure (Bonaventura 1887, III Sent d. 35, a. unicus, q. 1, concl.), so we are not dealing with a fixed expression. There is one more passage in his Commentary on the Sentences (Bonaventura 1887, III Sent d. 24, dub. 4, sol.), where the term “experiential knowledge” is employed in reference to God, but the formula itself is not used. (Hoefs 1989, pp. 16, 35–41). We note that the notion of an affective “experiential knowledge of God” will be taken up by Hugh of Balma and then later by Gerson in their definitions of mystical theology. The recovering of Bonaventure at the College of Navarre in the beginning of the fifteenth century comes to fruition in Gerson, and then more fully in the 1495 Strassburg Opuscala. The definition of the mystical theology as “experiential knowledge of God” later appears in Johannes Altenstaig’s Vocabularius theologiae (1517). Cf. (Dubbelman and Zoutendam 2024, pp. 53–94; Dubbelman 2024, pp. 281–303). |
8 | Both passages are in the third book of the Commentary on the Sentences. See Bonaventura 1887, III Sent d. 35, a. unicus, q. 1, concl.: “cognitio Dei experimentalis” and (Bonaventura 1887, III Sent d. 24, dub. 4, sol). |
9 | Bonaventure, in interpreting the agostonic phrase—“Quid est Deum scire, nisi eum mente conspicere firmiterque percipere?” (Trin. VIII, 4, 6)—also takes into account the negative theology of Dionysius Areopagite. It is in reconciling the positions of the two authorities that he formulates his idea of the experiential knowledge of God, which is union with God imperfectly realized in the wayfaring state and perfectly realized in the state of the vision. (Bonaventura 1887, III Sent d. 24, dub. 4). |
10 | “For if we consider the intellect in itself, thus it is properly called speculative and is perfected by a habit which is the grace of contemplation [contemplationis gratia], and is called speculative science. But if we consider it as having originated to be extended to work, thus it is perfected by a habit that exists so that we might become good [ut boni fiamus], and this is practical or moral science. But if we consider it from a middle point of view, as having originated to be extended to the affect [extendi ad affectum], so it is perfected by a middle habit between the purely speculative and the purely practical [habitu medio inter pure speculativum et practicum], and which is encircled by both [complectitur utrumque]. And this habit is called wisdom [sapientia], which simultaneously designates the cognition and affection (…). Whence, it is for the sake of contemplation, and so that we might become good; but principally, it is so that we might become good [ut boni fiamus]”. I Sent Prooemii, q. 3, resp. The Latin text is translated by Shelby (Shelby 2023, p. 359). |
11 | “Scientia theologica est habitus affectivus et medius inter speculativum et practicum, et pro fine habet tum contemplationem, tum ut boni fiamus, et quidem principalius, ut boni fiamus” (Bonaventura 1882, I Sent Prooemii, q. 3, concl.). In my own translation: “Theological science is an affective habitus and as an intermediate mediates between the speculative and the practical habitus. Its aim is contemplation as well as becoming good, but the primary aim is to become good”. |
12 | Bonaventure writes about this in relation to the question of “scientia” as a spiritual gift from the Holy Spirit. (Bonaventura 1887, III Sent d. 35, a. un. q. 2, resp.). |
13 | “Faced with the possibility of defining theology as a speculative or as a practical science, Bonaventure opts for a third way: theology perfects the intellect as it is extended ad affectum (…). If, on the other hand, the final cause is understood as that end which perfects the formal cause—thus, not the end of the one who undertakes the activity, but the proper end of the activity itself—then theology must be governed in an intrinsic way by this extension ad affectum” (LaNave 2014, p. 100). |
14 | “Modus procedendi perscrutatorius sive ratiocinativus convenit huic doctrinae, cum valeat ad confutandum adversarios fidei, ad fovendum infirmos in fide, ad delectandum perfectos” (Bonaventura 1882, I Sent Prooemii, q. 2, concl.). |
15 | In other places, the full identification is not made, but the close connection between the two concepts is regularly formulated in such a way that experiential knowledge is an integral part of the broader meaning of wisdom. See Bonaventura 1887, III Sent. d. 34, p. I, a. 2, q. 2, ad 2; Bonaventura 1887, III Sent. d. 35, a. 1, q. 3 ad 3. |
16 | In my own translation: “The fourth way is to use the concept of wisdom in a more proper sense; it then means the experiential knowledge of God. In this case, it is one of the seven gifts of the Holy Spirit, the act of which consists in tasting divine sweetness. And since for the inward savouring in which there is delight, the act of affection is absolutely necessary for the conjunction and the act of cognition for the apprehension, as the Philosopher says—“delight is the conjunction of the proper with the proper, with the perception of conjunction”, therefore the act of the gift of wisdom belongs partly to the cognitive and partly to the affective, in such a way that it begins in cognition and is completed in affection, so that the act of tasting is itself an experiential cognition of the good and the sweet. And therefore the particular act of the gift of wisdom belongs in the most proper sense to the affective side (…)”. |
17 | Our reading at this point coincides with Marianne Schlosser’s interpretation. (Schlosser 1990, pp. 186–217). |
18 | “in amore Dei ipsi gustui coniuncta est cognitio. Optimus enim modus cognoscendi Deum est per experimentum dulcedinis; multo etiam excellentior et nobilior et delectabilior est quam per argumentum inquisitionis” (Bonaventura 1887, III Sent d. 35, a. unicus, q. 1, ad 5). In my own translation: “In God’s love, cognition is connected with the act of tasting itself. The most excellent way to know God is through the experience of sweetness. Far more excellent and noble and delightful than knowledge by reasoning inquiry”. |
19 | “donum sapientiae est ad cognitionem aeternorum secundum aeternas rationes, secundum tamen quod ille rationes sunt via ad gustum et experimentalem cognitionem divinae suavitatis, ita quod cognitio illa gustui annexa” (Bonaventura 1887, III Sent, d. 35, a. unicus, q. 3, ad 1). In my own translation: “the gift of wisdom relates to the cognition of eternal things by eternal causes, but in such a way that these causes are the ways to tasting and experiencing divine sweetness, so that this cognition is connected with the tasting”. |
20 | “Nihilominus tamen in ipso actu intellectus est quaedam delectatio, sed longe inferior quam in dono sapientiae. Delectatur enim quis in cognitione veritatis, sed non sic in gustu summae suavitatis” (Bonaventura 1887, III Sent d. 35, a. unicus, q. 3, ad 3). In my own translation: “There is, however, some pleasure in the act of intellect itself, far inferior, however, to the gift of wisdom. For in the case of the former, we delight in the knowledge of truth, and not in the taste of the supreme sweetness”. |
21 | “amplius ascendit affectio quam ratio et unio quam cognitio, secundum quod vult Dionysius” (Bonaventura 1887, III Sent d. 35, a. unicus, q. 3, ad 5). Contrary to his usual practice, Bonaventure here refers to Dionysius only in general terms, without naming any of his writings. Also unusual is the way the reference is made with the verb ‘vult’ instead of the usual ‘dicit’ or ‘docet’. Perhaps this is a way of showing that he is not quoting the author directly but is joining an interpretative tradition. |
22 | While St. Albert the Great and others interpreted Areopagite’s Mystical Theology in a speculative way, the representative of the St. Victorian school, Thomas Gallus, offered an affective reading of Dionysius’ writing. According to his fundamental thesis (Comm. super Isaam 6), God draws love (affectus) to himself inestimably more deeply and subtly than intellect (intellectus), because angels and men love more than they can examine and understand. (McGinn 1998, p. 80). |
23 | The roots of the affective reading of the mystical union in Dionysius’ Mystical Theology go back to the oeuvre of Dionysius himself, who in De divinis nominibus, in chapter VII, which is mainly a meditation on the name ‘wisdom’ applied to God, describes union with God as an event of union that transcends the nature of reason (VII, 1) and reason itself (VII, 3). (Areopagite 1920, pp. 104–106, 147, 152). Thomas Gallus and the authors who followed the affective interpretation, including Bonaventure, read Dionysius’ Mystical Theology in light of the Dionysian work De divinis nominibus, and consequently interpreted the union described in the former as an ecstatic unifying movement of love. |
24 | It is in this text that Bonaventure develops his idea of the particularities of Christ’s sensual experience. In this sense, Jesus, through his sensual senses (sensualitas), comes to know things that are perceptible by the senses according to their own mode of being (in proprio genere), which corresponds to the experiential cognition (cognitio experientiae) of the fallen state (status naturae lapsae), which the Seraphic Doctor also calls cognitio poenalis experientiae. He argues that Christ did not acquire new knowledge through his sensory experience but merely learned in a new way the same things that he had already known in other ways. The perfection of Jesus’ soul is the reason why it is necessary to posit all three modes of cognition in Christ’s soul, even though neither the simple knowledge (notitia/intelligentia simplex, cognitio gratis datae a Verbo), which is graciously given by the Word to the soul of Jesus, nor sensual experience add anything new to the glorious knowledge in the Word (cognitio in Verbo secundum statum gloriae). |
25 | In my own translation: “The third preliminary assumption is that Christ was both wayfarer and arriver at the goal (comprehensor). Therefore, the cognition proper to being wayfarer did not hinder the cognition proper to arriver at the goal, nor did the affection proper to one state hinder the affection proper to the other state. In Christ, this was singular because of the office of mediation, by virtue of which he had to experience both the divine and the human. Consequently, just as he could turn perfectly to God and turn to us at the same time, so that the one turning did not hinder or delay the other, so he could, with the same part of the soul, rejoice in God and suffer with his body at the same time. Therefore, joy neither diminished nor removed pain, nor pain joy”. |
26 | Bonaventure quotes the same biblical passage in both texts on the meaning of the term “sapientia”—Ecclesiastes 6:23—and interprets it in the same way. |
27 | In the Commentary on the Sentences, Bonaventura uses the term “mystica theologia” in connection with the question of whether or not we use all our designations (nomina) of God in a purely translative sense. Following Dionysius Areopagites, the Seraphic Doctor explains in his reply that there are three ways of knowing God: per effectum, per excellentiam and per ablationem/abnegationem. Mystical theology includes the ways of knowing and speaking per excellentiam and per ablationem. The mystical way of speaking of the most excellent attributes (proprietates excellentiae) of God is figurative, but the designations made by denials in mystical theology are not figurative but are used in proper sense. (Bonaventura 1882, I Sent d. 22, a. un. q. 3, ad 3). |
28 | Dubbelman states in his recent work that Bonaventure was probably the first Latin writer to use the term mystica theologia as a concept and a way of doing theology. See (Dubbelman 2024, pp. 281–303). |
29 | Referring to the text of Is 11:2, Bonaventura states: “omnia dona perfecte fuerunt in Christo” (Bonaventura 1887, III Sent d. 34, p. 1, a. 2, q. 1 arg. 1). Cf. (Bonaventura 1887, III Sent d. 34, p. 1, a. 2, q. 1 concl.; Bonaventura 1887, III Sent d. 34, p. 1, a. 2, q. 3 concl.; Bonaventura 1887, III Sent d. 13, a. 1, q. 3). |
30 | The majority of scholars (Weber, Quinn, Bougeroe, Mauro, Houser) are of the opinion that De scientia Christi was written in 1254, when Bonaventure became magister at the University of Paris. Presumably, the work was part of the inception as Master process itself (Hayes 1992, pp. 41–42). |
31 | Hayes thus praises Bonaventure’s work: “The Disputed Questions offer the most extensive discussion of Christ’s knowledge in the Bonaventurean corpus and provide an excellent example of the intricate relations that existed between philosophy and theology in the medieval period” (Hayes 1992, p. 45). |
32 | “sapientia increata comprehendi non potest ab anima sibi unita nec ab alia quaecumque creatura, secundum quod comprehendi dicitur aliquid, quod comprehendens totum et totaliter secundum omnem modum capit in se ipso” (Bonaventura 1891b, Scien.Chr. q. 6, concl.). “It must be admitted that uncreated wisdom can be comprehended neither by a soul united with it, nor by any other creature as long as “to be comprehended” means that there is a subject who, in the act of comprehending, grasps the object fully and completely within itself, from every perspective” (Hayes 1992, p. 169). Bonaventure uses the term “apprehensio” instead of “comprehensio” to describe the insight of Christ’s human soul into the divine Wisdom united with Him. “Fatemur autem, animam Christi esse deiformem, non tamen esse Deo aequalem; et ideo concedimus et tenemus, quod ipsam sapientiam sibi unitam, licet clare et perspicue apprehendat, non tamen totaliter comprehendit” (Bonaventura 1891b, Scien.Chr. q. 6, ad 19.20). “Now we admit that, while the soul of Christ is conformed to God, yet it is not equal to God. And therefore we concede and we hold that, even though it apprehends clearly and plainly that very wisdom which is united with itself, yet it does not comprehend this wisdom totally” (Hayes 1992, p. 177). |
33 | “In via enim possumus divinam immensitatem contemplari ratiocinando et admirando; in patria vero contuendo, quando erimus deiformes effecti, et excedendo, quando erimus omnino inebriati; propter quam ebrietatem dicit Anselmus in fine Proslogii, quod ‘magis intrabimus in gaudium divinum, quam divinum gaudium intret in cor nostrum’” (Bonaventura 1891b, Scien.Chr. q. 6, concl.). |
34 | “And since that soul which is united with the Word is made more God-like and is more intoxicated because of a grace that is not only sufficient but superexcellent, therefore it beholds the divine wisdom, and in this beholding it is drawn to that wisdom in ecstasy even though it does not comprehend that wisdom. For this reason, wonder has a place not only in historical existence but in heaven as well, and not only in the case of the angels but in that soul which was assumed by God” (Hayes 1992, pp. 171–72). |
35 | Bonaventure, in his Commentary on the Sentences, takes the position that the soul of Christ knows all that the Word knows by habitual knowledge, but not by actual knowledge. While the Word comprehends infinite things in a comprehensive and complete way (comprehendendo), the human soul of Christ has no such knowledge of them. |
36 | The use of the term “inebriata” recalls the text of Pro 9:2–6, where the personified Wisdom invites men to feast and to drink the wine she has mixed: “venite comedite panem meum et bibite vinum quod miscui vobis” (Vulgata). |
37 | “Et ideo anima Christi, cum sit creatura ac per hoc finita, quantumcumque sit unita Verbo, infinita non comprehendit, quia nec illis aequatur nec illa excedit; et ideo illa non omnimode capit, sed potius capitur, ac per hoc in illa non fertur per modum comprehensionis, sed potius per modum excessus. Excessivum autem modum cognoscendi dico non quo cognoscens excedat cognitum, sed quo cognoscens fertur in obiectum excedens excessivo quodam modo, erigendo se supra se ipsum” (Bonaventura 1891b, Scien.Chr. q 7, concl.). “And therefore, despite the fact that it is united with the Word, the soul of Christ does not comprehend an infinite number of things since it is a creature and is therefore limited; for it is neither equal to nor greater than the Word. And therefore, the soul does not grasp these things in their totality. Rather, the soul is taken captive by them, and thus it is drawn not by comprehensive knowledge but rather by an ecstatic knowledge. I call this an ecstatic mode of knowledge, not because the subject exceeds the object, but because the subject is drawn toward an object that exceeds it in a certain ecstatic mode that draws the soul beyond itself” (Hayes 1992, p. 187). We note that Bonaventure here explicitly departs from the position he took in the Commentary on the Sentences, where he understood the cognition of Christ’s soul of the infinite things contained in eternal Wisdom as still habitual cognition, and not as cognition in the mode of excess. In the Breviloquium (1256/1257), the Seraphic Doctor retained both terms, saying that Christ cognizes infinite things “cognitione habituali, vel excessiva” (Bonaventura 1891a, Brev. p. IV. c. 6). |
38 | Bonaventure refers to Dionysius Areopagite’s Mystical Theology in connection with cognition in the mode of excessus, and to the 7th chapter of his book De divinis nominibus. “Oportet agnoscere, nostrum intellectum quandam habere potentiam ad intelligendum, per quam videt intelligibilia, unionem vero excedentem intellectus naturam, per quam coniungitur ad ea quae sunt ultra se. Secundum hanc igitur divina intelligendo, non secundum nos, sed nos totos a nobis totis extra factos et totos deificatos; melius est enim Dei esse et non esse sui; sic enim erunt omnia credibilia iis qui sunt cum Deo” (Bonaventura 1891b, Scien.Chr. q. 7, concl.). “We ought to acknowledge that our intellect has a certain power to understand through which it contemplates the intelligible realities, and we ought to acknowledge a union that surpasses the nature of the intellect, through which it is united to those things which are beyond it. Knowing divine things in this way, not according to our own capacity but in as far as we are drawn entirely beyond ourselves, we are totally deified; for it is better to belong to God than to belong to oneself. Thus, all the objects of faith will be available to those who are with God” (Hayes 1992, p. 187). |
39 | “But this mode of knowing by means of ecstasy exists both in the wayfaring state and in heaven. For those in the wayfaring state, it is only partial, while in heaven it is realized perfectly in Christ and in some of the saints. But in others it is limited, both because of the measure of grace proper to each and because of the divine will which does not offer itself to all with the same degree of familiarity. But in the soul of Christ it is realized most generously, both because that soul possesses a grace which fills its capacity in every way and because the eternal mirror offers itself to that soul, manifesting itself with total familiarity” (Hayes 1992, pp. 187–88). |
40 | In his reply to objections 19, 20 and 21, Bonaventure explains in detail the nature of this fullness in the soul of Christ, which cannot be increased. “quia, cum anima Christi cognitionem comprehensivam, respectu omnium, quaecumque in universo fiunt, et excessivam respectu omnium, quae in divina arte continentur, et excessus ille sit in totalitate virtutis cognoscentis, et in summa familiaritate respectu speculi repraesentantis; oportet, quod anima Christi etsi non omnia comprehendat, quae divina sapientia comprehendit, quia tamen in omnia illa excedit, ideo totus eius appetitus est terminatus; ut, sicut nihil ultra adiici possit eius gratiae, sic nihil ultra addiici possit eius sapientiae, quia tantum datum est ei, quantum concedi potest alicui creaturae” (Bonaventura 1891b, Scien. Chr. q. 7, ad 19.20.21). “And since the soul of Christ has comprehensive knowledge of all things that happen in the universe and ecstatic knowledge of all things contained in the divine art, and since that ecstatic knowledge is rooted in the total power of the knowing subject and in the most intimate familiarity with that mirror which represents all things—even though Christ’s soul does not have comprehensive knowledge of all that the divine wisdom comprehends but is nonetheless drawn to all those things in ecstatic knowledge—its entire desire for knowledge finds satisfaction. Consequently, as nothing further can be added to his grace, so nothing can be added to his wisdom because he has been given as much as can be granted to any creature” (Hayes 1992, p. 194). |
41 | “In our present life as well as in heaven it is not only the presence of the eternal light that is required, but the influence of the eternal light as well; and not only the uncreated Word, but the word conceived within us as well. And since the latter is finite, neither the soul of Christ nor any other soul can have comprehensive knowledge of the eternal Word or of the infinite number of knowable objects, even though the soul may be drawn to them in ecstasy. And, indeed, this ecstasy is that ultimate and most exalted form of knowledge which is praised by Dionysius in all his books, but especially in his book on mystical theology. Practically the whole of sacred Scripture speaks symbolically of this type of knowledge. And in reference to it, the second chapter of the Apocalypsel says: “I shall give him a white stone, and on the stone will be written a new name which no one knows except the one who receives it”. This type of knowledge can be understood only with great difficulty, and it cannot be understood at all except by one who has experienced it. And no one will experience it except one who is “rooted and grounded in love so as to comprehend with all the saints what is the length, and the breadth”, etc. It is in this that true, experiential wisdom consists. It begins on earth and is consummated in heaven. In trying to explain this, negations are more appropriate than affirmations, and superlatives are more appropriate than positive predications. And if it is to be experienced, interior silence is more helpful than external speech. Therefore, let us stop speaking, and let us pray to the Lord that we may be granted the experience of that about which we have spoken” (Hayes 1992, pp. 195–96). |
42 | Bonaventure, in quaestio 6, discusses the ecstatic knowledge of uncreated divine Wisdom only in relation to the soul of Christ. |
43 | The term “excessus” occurs most often, about fifteen times, in De divinis nominibus. (Areopagite 1920). |
44 | The first chapter of Mystical Theology contains the main ideas and key expressions that Bonaventure recalls in the passage quoted: the transcendence of affirmations, the application of the higher degree, silence, prayer to the Lord. |
45 | Robert Glenn Davis, in his analysis of the text of Scien.Chr. q. 7, remarks: “This passage suggests that the transformation that occurs in the soul’s exceeding of itself is, most fundamentally, a transformation of the soul’s mode of moving. To know God ecstatically means to be drawn out of oneself and into God. Another name for the soul’s motion toward its object is amor. Thus, one could say that to love God is to know God in an ecstatic way or, conversely, that to know God ecstatically is love. The crucial distinction is that union with God is a state in which the soul is seized, taken captive, and transformed into its object. This is why ordinary knowledge in which the soul takes hold of its object-can have no place in the soul’s intimacy with God, according to Bonaventure. In this way, amor names an even closer intimacy with God than sapientia, which Bonaventure characterizes as a movement of a thing toward the soul” (Davis 2017, p. 43). In support of this latter statement, Glenn quotes the following passage from the Commentary on the Sentences: “Certain acts refer to a motion from a thing to the soul, such as wisdom, while others refer to the motion from the soul to the thing, such as loving [amare]” (Bonaventura 1882, 1 Sent d. 32, a. 2, q. 1, ad 1, 2, 3). Finally he adds: “In his much later Collationes in Hexaemeron, Bonaventure discusses ecstasy as a sapientia nulliformis, but this passage from the Sentences indicates that sapientia is not necessarily an ecstatic movement any more than cognitio is” (Davis 2017, p. 150, endnote 52). We agree with the author’s assertion that ordinary cognition of reason plays no part in cognition of God per excessum, as well as with his claim that sapientia is not necessarily an ecstatic movement towards God. However, we find it necessary to supplement and nuance these statements in so far as Bonaventure in De scientia Christi q. 7 does not speak of wisdom (sapientia) in general, but of a particular form of wisdom when he uses the term experimentalis et vera sapientia. This form of sapientia implies, by definition, the ecstatic movement of affectus/amor, so it makes no sense to contrast affectus with sapientia. On the contrary, in the text of the Commentary on the Sentences cited by Glenn (1Sent d. 32, a. 2, q. 1, ad 1,2,3), the Seraphic Doctor uses the term sapientia in a general sense (“ratio communis, quae sumta est a creaturis”). |
46 | The text of Eph 3:17–19 in the Vulgata translation reads: “in caritate radicati et fundati ut possitis comprehendere cum omnibus sanctis quae sit latitudo et sublimitas et profundum, scire etiam supereminentem scientiae caritatem Christi ut impleamini in omnem plenitudinem Dei”. |
47 | Such principles are, e.g., the soul of Christ comes to know the uncreated Wisdom (Word) through the created wisdom (word); it comes to know the eternal Wisdom in a non-comprehensive way; it comes to know all actual beings (past, present, future) in Wisdom in an actual way; the knowledge of Christ surpasses the knowledge of other creatures. |
48 | See (Bonaventura 1887, III Sent d. 34, p. I, a. 1, q. 3, ad 1); (Bonaventura 1887, III Sent d. 34, p. I, a. 2, q. 1). |
References
- Areopagite, Dionysius. 1920. On the Divine Names and the Mystical Theology. Translated by Clarence Edwin Rolt. London and Grand Rapids: Christian Classics Ethereal Library. [Google Scholar]
- Boeckl, Karl. 1931. Die sieben Gaben des Heiligen Geistes in ihrer Bedeutung für die Mystik nach der Theologie des 13. und 14. Jahrhunderts. Freiburg and Breisgau: Herder. [Google Scholar]
- Bonaventura. 1882. Commentaria in quatuor libros Sententiarum magistri Petri Lombardi. In primum librum sententiarum (I Sent). In Doctoris Seraphici S. Bonaventurae Episcopi Cardinalis Opera Omnia. Quaracchi: Tomus I. Florentia. [Google Scholar]
- Bonaventura. 1885. Commentaria in quatuor libros Sententiarum magistri Petri Lombardi. In secundum librum sententiarum (II Sent). In Doctoris Seraphici S. Bonaventurae Episcopi Cardinalis Opera Omnia. Quaracchi: Tomus II. Florentia. [Google Scholar]
- Bonaventura. 1887. Commentaria in quatuor libros Sententiarum magistri Petri Lombardi. In tertium librum sententiarum (III Sent). In Doctoris Seraphici S. Bonaventurae Episcopi Cardinalis Opera Omnia. Quaracchi: Tomus III. Florentia. [Google Scholar]
- Bonaventura. 1891a. Breviloquium (Brev). In Doctoris Seraphici S. Bonaventurae Episcopi Cardinalis Opera Omnia. Tomus V. Opuscula varia theologica. Quaracchi: Florentia, pp. 199–292. [Google Scholar]
- Bonaventura. 1891b. Quaestiones disputatae de scientia Christi (Scien.Chr). In Doctoris Seraphici S. Bonaventurae Episcopi Cardinalis Opera Omnia. Tomus V. Opuscula varia theologica. Quaracchi: Florentia, pp. 3–43. [Google Scholar]
- Carpenter, Charles. 1999. Theology as the Road to Holiness in St. Bonaventure. Mahwah: Paulist Press. [Google Scholar]
- Coolman, Boyd Taylor. 2004. Knowing God by Experience: The Spiritual Senses in the Theology of William of Auxerre. Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press. [Google Scholar]
- Coolman, Boyd Taylor. 2017. Knowledge, Love, and Ecstasy in the Theology of Thomas Gallus. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Daniel, Randolph. 1974. St. Bonaventure a Faithful Disciple of St. Francis? A Reexamination of the Question. In S. Bonaventura 1274–1974. Edited by Jacques Guy Bougerol. Grottaferrata: Collegio S. Bonaventura, vol. 2, pp. 171–87. [Google Scholar]
- Davis, Robert Glenn. 2017. The Weight of Love Affect, Ecstasy, and Union in the Theology of Bonaventure. New York: Fordham University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Delio, Ilia. 2014. Theology, Spirituality and Christ the Center: Bonaventure’s Synthesis. In A Companion to Bonaventure. Edited by Jay M. Hammond, J. A. Wayne Hellmann and Jared Goff. Leiden and Boston: Brill, pp. 361–402. [Google Scholar]
- Dubbelman, Samuel J. 2024. Mystica Theologia and Imageless Prayer in Hugh of Balma and Blosius. Sixteenth Century Journal 55: 281–303. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dubbelman, Samuel J., and Erin Risch Zoutendam. 2024. Mystical Terms in Johannes Altenstaig’s Vocabularius theologiae (1517). Renaissance and Reformation 47: 53–94. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gavrilyk, Paul L., and Sarah Coakley, eds. 2011. The Spiritual Senses: Perceiving God in Western Christianity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hayes, Zachary. 1992. Introduction. In Saint Bonaventure’s Disputed Questions on the Knowledge of Christ. Works of Saint Bonaventure. Edited by George Marcil. New York: The Francescan Institute Saint Bonaventure University Saint Bonaventure, pp. 21–67. [Google Scholar]
- Hoefs, Karl-Heinz. 1989. Erfahrung Gottes bei Bonaventura. In Erfurter Theologische Studien. Bd. 57. Leipzig: St. Benno-Verlag. [Google Scholar]
- LaNave, Gregory F. 2012. Bonaventure. In The Spiritual Senses. Perceiving God in Western Christianity. Edited by Paul L. Gavrilyuk and Sarah Coakley. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 159–73. [Google Scholar]
- LaNave, Gregory F. 2014. Bonaventure’s Theological Method. In A Companion to Bonaventure. Edited by Jay M. Hammond, Wayne Hellmann and Jared Goff. Leiden and Boston: Brill, pp. 81–120. [Google Scholar]
- Leinsle, Ulrich G. 1995. Einführung in die schlolastische Theologie. Padernborn, München, Wien and Zürich: Ferdinand Schöning Verlag. [Google Scholar]
- McGinn, Bernard. 1998. The Flowering of Mysticism: Men and Women in the New Mysticism: 1200–1350. The Presence of God. New York: Crossroad, vol. 3. [Google Scholar]
- Porwoll, Robert J., and David Allison Orsbon, eds. 2021. Victorine Restoration. Essays on Hugh of St Victor, Richard of St Victor, and Thomas Gallus. Turnhout: Brepols Publishers. [Google Scholar]
- Puskás, Attila. 2024. Perceiving God: The Spiritual Senses in Bonaventure’s Mystical Theology. Religions 15: 902. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rahner, Karl. 1975. Die Lehre von den ‘geistlichen Sinnen’ im Mittelalter. Der Beitrag Bonaventuras. In Schriften zur Theologie. Edited by Karl Heinz Neufeld. Zürich, Einsiedeln and Köln: Benziger Verlag, vol. 12, pp. 137–72. [Google Scholar]
- Rorem, Paul. 1993. Pseudo-Dionysius. A Commentary on the Texts and an Introduction to Their Influence. New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Rorem, Paul. 2009. Hugh of Saint Victor. In Great Medieval Thinkers. Edited by Brian Davies. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Rorem, Paul. 2015. The Dionysian Mystical Theology. Minneapolis: Fortress Press. [Google Scholar]
- Schlosser, Marianne. 1990. Cognitio et amor. Zur kognitiven und voluntativen Grund der Gotteserfahrung nach Bonaventura. Paderborn, München, Wien and Zürich: Ferdinand Schöning. [Google Scholar]
- Schlosser, Marianne. 2014. Bonaventure: Life and Works. In A Companion to Bonaventure. Edited by Jay M. Hammond, Wayne Hellmann and Jared Goff. Leiden and Boston: Brill, pp. 9–60. [Google Scholar]
- Shelby, Katherine Wrisley. 2023. Spiraling into God. Bonaventure on Grace, Hierarchy, and Holiness. Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press. [Google Scholar]
- Tedoldi, Fabio Massimo. 1999. La dottrina dei cinque sensi spirituali in San Bonaventura. Roma: Antonianum. [Google Scholar]
- Tobon, Monica. 2022. Bonaventure and Dionysius. In Dionysius the Areopagite. Edited by Mark Edwards, Dimitrios Pallis and Georgios Steiris. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 350–66. [Google Scholar]
- von Balthasar, Hans Urs. 1982. The Glory of the Lord. Vol. I: Seeing the Form. Translated by Erasmo Leivà-Merikakis. Edinburgh: T&T. Clark. San Francisco: Ignatius Press. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2025 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Puskás, A. Cognitio Dei Experimentalis—Experimentalis et Vera Sapientia Bonaventure on the Experiential Knowledge of God in the Commentary on the Sentences and in De scientia Christi. Religions 2025, 16, 394. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16030394
Puskás A. Cognitio Dei Experimentalis—Experimentalis et Vera Sapientia Bonaventure on the Experiential Knowledge of God in the Commentary on the Sentences and in De scientia Christi. Religions. 2025; 16(3):394. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16030394
Chicago/Turabian StylePuskás, Attila. 2025. "Cognitio Dei Experimentalis—Experimentalis et Vera Sapientia Bonaventure on the Experiential Knowledge of God in the Commentary on the Sentences and in De scientia Christi" Religions 16, no. 3: 394. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16030394
APA StylePuskás, A. (2025). Cognitio Dei Experimentalis—Experimentalis et Vera Sapientia Bonaventure on the Experiential Knowledge of God in the Commentary on the Sentences and in De scientia Christi. Religions, 16(3), 394. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16030394