Reframing Catholic Theological Ethics from a Scotistic Perspective
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Why Scotus?
3. Scotus’ Meta-Ethics in a Nutshell
4. Marriage and Bigamy
Further Issues
Even the sort of dispensations Scotus sees God making […] are always in accord with right reason, and are something the human mind did figure out, or might have if emotions did not blind one’s reason. For they concern such things as are good for man [sic] in relation to his fellowman, where there is a hierarchy of values involved, and where to obtain the principal value, certain aspects of lesser value may have to be sacrificed, in view of a less than ideal environmental situation.
5. Conclusions
5.1. The Notion of Premoral and Moral Good and Evil
5.2. The Primary Importance of the End in the Specification and Evaluation of Moral Acts
5.3. The (Ir)Relevancy of the Concept of Intrinsic Evil
5.4. Scotus’ Contemporary Significance
Conflicts of Interest
References
- Alluntis, Felix, and Allan B. Wolter. 1975. John Duns Scotus: God and Creatures: The Quodlibetal Questions. Washington: The Catholic University of America Press. [Google Scholar]
- Aquinas, Thomas. 1955–1957. Summa contra gentiles. Available online: http://dhspriory.org/thomas/ContraGentiles.htm (accessed on 26 April 2017).
- Cross, Richard. 1997. Duns Scotus on Goodness, Justice, and what God Can Do. Journal of Theological Studies 48: 48–76. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Finnis, John. 2011. Natural Law and Natural Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ingham, Mary B., and Mechthild Dreyer. 2004. The Philosophical Vision of John Duns Scotus: An Introduction. Washington: Catholic University of America Press. [Google Scholar]
- Jaczn, Antoon V., Henri Veldhuis, Aline H. Looman-Graaskamp, Eef Dekker, and Nico W. den Bok. 1994. John Duns Scotus: Contingency and Freedom: Lectura I 39. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. [Google Scholar]
- Leo, XIII. 1879. Aeterni Patris. Available online: http://w2.vatican.va/content/leo-xiii/en/encyclicals/documents/ hf_l-xiii_enc_04081879_aeterni-patris.html (accessed on 26 April 2017).
- McCormick, Richard A. 1981. Notes on Moral Theology 1965–1980. Washington: University Press of America. [Google Scholar]
- Möhle, Hannes. 2003. Scotus’s Theory of Natural Law. In The Cambridge Companion to Duns Scotus. Edited by Thomas Williams. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 312–31. [Google Scholar]
- Osborne, Thomas M. 2014. Human Action in Thomas Aquinas, John Duns Scotus & William of Ockham. Washington: Catholic University of America Press. [Google Scholar]
- Pickstock, Catherine. 2005. Duns Scotus: His Historical and Contemporary Significance. Modern Theology 21: 543–74. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Salzman, Todd. 1995. Deontology and Teleology: An Investigation of the Normative Debate in Roman Catholic Moral Theology. Leuven: Leuven University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Santogrossi, Ansgar. 1994. Scotus’s Method in Ethics: Not to Play God—A Reply to Thomas Shannon. Theological Studies 55: 314–29. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Selling, Joseph A. 2016. Reframing Catholic Theological Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Shannon, Thomas A. 1995. The Ethical Theory of John Duns Scotus. Quincy: Franciscan Press. [Google Scholar]
- Wolter, Allan B., and William A. Frank. 1997. Duns Scotus on the Will and Morality. Washington: The Catholic University of America Press. [Google Scholar]
1 | Scotus’ decline was, in my opinion, more a result of this general impression than respective differences between him and Aquinas, which is not to deny that there were differences between them. This general impression was that Scotus was a proponent of voluntarism, while Aquinas was a proponent of intellectualism and the latter was more in line with the Catholic understanding of morality. Although this observation rests on how Scotus was treated by theologians of the Second Scholasticism and the manual tradition within the Catholic Church, the Radical Orthodoxy movement has further fueled this skepticism towards Scotus in the recent decades. Cf. (Pickstock 2005, pp. 563–69). |
2 | The subtitle of the encyclical letter, On the Restoration of Christian Philosophy in Catholic Schools in the Spirit of the Angelic Doctor, St. Thomas Aquinas, is very suggestive in terms of its aim. |
3 | References to Aquinas’ translated works in the main text are specified by the modern edition, followed by details of the original work (title, book (b.), distinction (dist.), question (q.), or chapter (chp.)). |
4 | References to Scotus’ translated works in the main text are specified by the modern edition, followed by details of the original work (title, book (b.), distinction (dist.), question (q.), and article (a.)). |
5 | Hence, one could say that Aquinas tried to justify the doctrine of creation within the frame of ancient Greek necessitarianism by introducing into it the act of creation, while Scotus found the view entirely incompatible with the doctrine of creation and developed an alternative ontology. |
6 | In other words, Scotus does not follow the Thomistic understanding that links the eternal law with creation (including “nature” and natural inclinations) through the notion of natural law as a rational participation in the eternal law. In fact, the whole notion of eternal law has no role in his ethical system. Instead, what belongs to the natural law (in the strict sense) is determined on the basis of the content of a given commandment, i.e., if it is conceptually necessary that the commandment be valid. The “conceptually necessary”, in this context, means necessary for the attainment of the ultimate end (the beatific vision) and this can be said only of those commandments that express self-evident principles (such as the first and the second commandment). Only such commandments prescribe goodness that cannot be repudiated without also repudiating the ultimate end. Cf. (Möhle 2003, pp. 314–16). |
7 | Since the issue of marriage and bigamy is related to the sixth commandment (the second tablet), it is obvious that it does not concern the natural law in the strict sense or goodness that is necessarily linked to the attainment of the ultimate end. |
8 | One of the anonymous reviewers of this article has argued that Scotus’ way of reasoning through the problem of the relationship between marriage and bigamy does not seem to provide a convincing solution, since it seems to suggest that the only way of achieving one purpose of marriage is to go directly against the other, which would then make the natural law seem arbitrary. I believe that this critique stands only if the natural teloi of marriage are understood as principles that need to be followed or accommodated in any morally acceptable solution. As far as I understood Scotus, the two purposes of marriage should rather be understood as inconclusive indications of what would be a rational thing to do in this area of life (and this is because there is no necessary relation between natural teloi and the ultimate end of human life for Scotus). They are inconclusive indications because the most Scotus can say is that there are rationally sound reasons to pursue only the primary purpose of marriage, as well as to pursue both primary and secondary purpose (although the latter solution already militates against the primary end to an extent, since one is not going to have as many children as one could by pursuing only the primary purpose of marriage). In order to turn these inconclusive indications into a rationally compelling argument (in the sense of recta ratio), circumstances need to be considered (and the argument needs to be sanctioned by the divine will). Nevertheless, since these inconclusive indications are both rationally sound, none of the possible solutions would make natural laws related to them internally incoherent (in the sense of irrational or incomprehensible). |
9 | This is exactly opposite of the claim made by Ansgar Santogrossi who tried to summarise Scotus’ position on dispensations by formulating a contemporary Scotistic gloss: “A contemporary Scotistic gloss on the pope’s [John Paul II] words might run: given the categorical, universal character of St. Paul’s condemnation of certain acts falling under the second table of the Decalogue, the closure of revelation with the death of the last apostle, and the obvious thrust of the Veritatis splendor, it can be stated that it will never be licit to act against the divine precept ‘till heaven and earth pass away’, regardless of how the Old Testament loci for dispensations from those precepts should be interpreted; nevertheless in the last analysis this is because God has graciously and contingently willed it so” (Santogrossi 1994, p. 326). Although I can agree with Santogrossi that, according to Scotus, God’s gracious and contingent decision of the will is certainly responsible for the OT dispensations, Scotus is quite clear that such dispensations both occurred and can still occur. Hence, Santogrossi’s limitation of the scope of the divine contingent will, introduced in order to bring it in line with Veritatis splendor, is clearly misplaced. Apart from that, if the possibility of dispensing from precepts of natural law in the extended sense is a prerogative of God’s gracious and contingent will, then denying this prerogative is an expression of hubris that reserves for itself another prerogative of knowing better how God’s graciousness should be exercised and, naturally, it should never be exercised in opposition to what is expected of it. |
10 | The reason why Scotus rejects the “exception” explanation of divine dispensation, as Möhle explains, consists in the fact that he holds the principles of non-contradiction and coherence as valid, even when it comes to what God can do, due to his absolute power. From these two, Scotus argues that God cannot order the world in such a way that the precepts of that ordering would contradict each other. Even more, these precepts have to constitute a coherent whole. Hence, if the “exception” explanation of divine dispensations were to be valid, then God could simply disregard these two principles, while decisions of his will would have an arbitrary character. Cf. (Möhle 2003, p. 321). |
11 | In these issues related to the example of bigamy, I followed Scotus’ distinction between primary and secondary purpose of marriage in order to see where his reasoning would take us when it comes to various situations and to demonstrate that there is an underlying method to his reasoning. Of course, if we were to apply his method to contemporary Catholic teaching on marriage (that does not distinguish between primary and secondary ends of marriage, although it claims that the ends of marriage are inseparable), the results would be different. |
12 | In formulating these three points of convergence I am indebted to Thomas Shannon. Cf. (Shannon 1995, pp. 87–113). |
13 | By premoral evil Selling refers to those realities, specified descriptively, that are harmful to human beings (hence, –moral), but are not immediately morally determinative (hence, pre-), such as death, sickness, ignorance, etc. Similarly, premoral goods are those realities that are beneficial to human beings, but are not immediately morally determinative, such as health, nutrition, knowledge, etc. The notion of moral good/evil, on the other hand, always implies a reference to the human will intending how to bring about a certain end and choosing means to it. In this sense, Selling would argue that sometimes one can choose a premoral evil as a means of attaining a good end (for instance, punishing a criminal to attain justice in a society) and this kind of premoral evil does not make the whole act morally evil. However, he warns, “the manner or extent to which some evil may be attached to the moral event […] is not always straightforward”. (Selling 2016, p. 181). |
14 | The end as a circumstance is the end of an agent, which could be any of the two goods associated (for Scotus) with marriage or both. His point (and mine in presenting and developing his point) is that one cannot exclude a priori any of these two (or three) possibilities as being always immoral, since circumstances might demand giving priority to one of the goods associated with marriage (provided a divine dispensation has also been given). Since these goods are both relative in relation to the ultimate end, they do not always have to be pursued by the will when one intends marriage (such as in the case of underpopulation (Scotus) or overpopulation (my deduction)). |
15 | By using a case study of lying Richard Cross has argued that Scotus is in fact a proponent of the concept of intrinsically evil acts as those acts that are morally wrong on the basis of their object. According to Cross, Scotus’ list of such acts would not include only hatred of God, but also lying, murder, theft, and adultery. It is impossible to evaluate Cross’ carefully argued claims within the frame of this article, since one would first have to discuss how Scotus and then Cross understand objects of the abovementioned acts and only then proceed to engage with the claims Cross has made. Another problem with the case study of lying is that Scotus seemed to have stopped somewhere in the middle between, on the one hand, what he encountered in the tradition (especially Augustinian tradition) and other medieval theologians when it comes to lying and, on the other hand, bringing his reflection on lying more in line with the more general direction of his own thought that goes beyond the natural teleology approach. This is what makes Cross’ claim debatable and Scotus’ treatment of lying as, perhaps, not the most representative of his thought. Cf. (Cross 1997, pp. 48–76). |
© 2017 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Polgar, N. Reframing Catholic Theological Ethics from a Scotistic Perspective. Religions 2017, 8, 200. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel8100200
Polgar N. Reframing Catholic Theological Ethics from a Scotistic Perspective. Religions. 2017; 8(10):200. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel8100200
Chicago/Turabian StylePolgar, Nenad. 2017. "Reframing Catholic Theological Ethics from a Scotistic Perspective" Religions 8, no. 10: 200. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel8100200
APA StylePolgar, N. (2017). Reframing Catholic Theological Ethics from a Scotistic Perspective. Religions, 8(10), 200. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel8100200