The Multiverse and Divine Creation
Abstract
:1. Introduction
There are infinitely many universes in the theistic multiverse. Multiverse theory further ensures that the plenitude of creation is consistent with being the best possible world. Indeed, the theistic multiverse is the uniquely best world.…the extent and the abundance of the creation must be as great as the possibility of existence and commensurate with the productive capacity of a ‘perfect’ and inexhaustible Source.
2. Creating the Theistic Multiverse
Bruno’s ontology reverses the order of worlds and universes, or at least seems to. Universes include an infinity of worlds rather than worlds including an infinity of universes. But he insists on an infinite creation from an infinite divine power. Similar views on divine creation are expressed in Kant’s Universal Natural History and Theory of the Heavens:I hold the universe to be infinite as a result of the infinite divine power; for I think it unworthy of divine goodness and power to have produced merely one finite world when it was able to bring into being an infinity of worlds. Wherefore I have expounded that there is an endless number of individual worlds like our earth. I regard it, with Pythagoras, as a star, and the moon, the planets, and the stars are similar to it, the latter being of endless number. All these bodies make an infinity of worlds; they constitute the infinite whole, in infinite space, an infinite universe, that is to say, containing innumerable worlds. So that there is an infinite measure in the universe and an infinite multitude of worlds. But this may be indirectly opposed to truth according to the faith.2
A creation that is in proportion to the power of an infinite being, according to Kant, must itself be infinitely or limitlessly large. More recently, Paul Draper has expressed similar thoughts concerning what a perfectly good God of limitless resources would create:But what is at last the end of these systematic arrangements? Where shall creation itself cease? It is evident that in order to think of it as in proportion to the power of the Infinite being, it must have no limits at all…the field of the revelation of the Divine attributes is as infinite as these attributes themselves.
These views all seem to express some logical or metaphysical relationship between maximal greatness and the principle of plenitude. We noted above that the principle of plenitude is most closely associated with Arthur Lovejoy. The principle of plenitude, according to Lovejoy, states that no genuine potentiality can remain unfulfilled:…a perfectly good God of limitless creative resources would be likely to create vastly many worlds, including magnificent worlds of great perfection as well as good but essentially flawed worlds that are more in need of special providence…. For by creating valuable worlds, God adds to the excellence of reality and also provides for the expression of divine benevolence, divine justice, and other virtues.
…the extent and the abundance of the creation must be as great as the possibility of existence and commensurate with the productive capacity of a ‘perfect’ and inexhaustible Source…the world is the better the more things it contains.
But why would God be committed to the Principle of Plenitude? In fact, why should God create anything at all?….God is a loving God, and while he does not need anyone to show his love to, nonetheless, his love leads him to create beings to show his love to..…So God creates a cosmos full of beings. But why stop there? The same considerations that lead him to create this cosmos would lead him to create any valuable cosmos.
According to Turner’s account of creation, God surveys all possible worlds—perhaps all of the simple possible worlds—and selects for creation the cosmoi of all of those possible worlds that are on balance good. The theistic multiverse therefore includes all and only those cosmoi that are on balance good. It is easy to see that the theistic multiverse, on Turner’s account, is the best possible world. It is God’s perfect goodness, omnipotence, and love that explain why God actualizes the best possible world—the theistic multiverse.…Thus I claim that God ought to actualize that complex possible world which contains cosmoi corresponding to every simple possible world above some cut-off line—for example, every simple possible world with a favorable balance of good over evil.3
Since it also true that God cannot create a universe that is unworthy of creation, God must create all and only the universes worth creating. The universes that God selects from are instantiations or concretizations of possible worlds.5 So, just as God can survey possible worlds and evaluate them according to their good-making and bad-making properties, God can survey the universes and evaluate them according to their good-making and bad-making properties.Pushed to their logical limit, these considerations suggest that an unsurpassably powerful, knowledgeable, and good deity will create every universe that is worth creating. I suspect that this way of thinking is motivated by a principle of plenitude…4
On Kraay’s picture of divine creation, God surveys all of the possible universes we find in possible worlds. God evaluates the universes according to their good-making and bad-making properties. Finally, God creates all and only the universes that are worthy of creation in the theistic multiverse. Indeed, God necessarily creates all and only the universes that are worthy of creation.The axiological framework for possible worlds discussed [above] can now be applied, mutatis mutandis, to universes…. As we earlier restricted our attention to possible worlds actualizable by God, let’s now restrict our attention to universes creatable by God. Finally, just as there are three candidate hierarchies of possible worlds…so too there are three candidate hierarchies of universes: either there is exactly one unsurpassable universe, or else there are none, or else there are infinitely many.6
If there is a unique unsurpassable world…there is good reason to think that it would be morally unacceptable for God to allow any other world to be actual. But if it is morally unacceptable for God to permit any world other than the unique best to be actual, it seems that this is the only world that could be actual—which is just to say that it is the only possible world…
According to O’Connor, the superuniverse that results would be infinitely valuable. Indeed, God would have a choice among such infinitely valuable superuniverses. And, again, for O’Connor, the principle of plenitude explains the creation of the superuniverse.More likely…is that God would elect to create that super-universe containing every single universe at or above [some goodness threshold] τ…7
According to O’Connor, God surveys all of the universes existing in all possible worlds and creates all and only those universes whose value exceeds some value τ.…So God has reason not to settle for creating a superuniverse that has only one universe as a member. Nor will it help for God to create two or three-membered superuniverse, or in fact an n-membered superuniverse, for any finite value n. But it would appear to help if God were to create an infinitely membered superuniverse, provided there is no finite upper limit on the value of its members.8
3. Incoherent Creation: Turner and Kraay
But if both Turner and Kraay are right that God necessarily actualizes the best possible world—the theistic multiverse—then both of their accounts of divine creation are flatly incoherent.theists should maintain that the actual world is a multiverse featuring all and only universes worthy of being created and sustained by God, and—more controversially—it recommends that theists embrace modal collapse: the claim that this multiverse is the only possible world.9
4. Incoherent Creation: O’Connor
But even the infinitely membered superuniverses are not sufficiently good for God to actualize any one of them.…it is plausible that God, intending to create, would not wish to settle for a universe than which there are an infinity of better universes, whose increase in value over our universe stretches without limit as we go up the series…. So God has reason not to settle for creating a superuniverse that has only one universe as a member. Nor will it help for God to create a two or three-membered superuniverse, or in fact an n-membered superuniverse, for any finite value n. But it would appear to help if God were to create an infinitely membered superuniverse, provided there is no finite upper limit on the value of its members.11
But, again, O’Connor refines God’s principle of selection from among the infinitely valuable worlds.More likely…is that God would elect to create that super-universe containing every single universe at or above [some goodness threshold] τ…12
The additional criteria are measured along three qualitative dimensions of value. First, for each universe, we can assess the intensive value of each of the basic objects. Using criteria for the perfection of each kind of object, this measure concerns the perfection of each object in the universe. Secondly, there is the aggregate value of objects taken collectively. Finally, there is the organic value of each universe, and perhaps the organic value of its subregions.…notice that [as] we go up the scale of superuniverses (unlike universes), eventually the values become infinite, in such a way that the hierarchy seems to ‘flatten out’. The superuniverse God creates is one of these equally top-valued members, the choice between them to be decided on grounds in addition to objective value.13
According to O’Connor, then, a perfect being will actualize some rich and infinitely value superuniverse.The total value of a universe appears then to be a point in three-space. Given that none of a universe’s objects may have infinite intensive value, its value in this regard…will typically not be infinite…And crucially a universe’s organic value will always be less than maximal. Even allowing for infinite aggregative value, then, no single universe will be of maximal value…Hence, there is a natural impetus for a perfect being to create an infinitely membered superuniverse whose members are ordered by value without an upper bound.14
No highly particular sort of universe is necessary, according to O’Connor, but it is necessary that God actualize a possible world that satisfies the criteria he has set forth. Necessarily, God actualizes an infinitely membered, partial ordered superuniverse for which there is no finite upper bound on the intensive value on the objects in each universe and no finite upper bound on the organic value of its universes, all of which exceed the threshold τ.I have argued that all the possibilities deemed creation-worthy by a perfect Creator would conform to a rich structure. Even so, an infinity of options satisfies these constraints, and there is no reason yet uncovered to suppose that any highly particular sort of universe will be deemed necessary.15
5. On Creating All Metaphysical Reality
Peter Forrest, too, suggests that God would create every possible world meeting some standard of goodness.…I am suggesting…that the many independent regions of a plenitudinous hyperspace provide [the hyperspace] theorist with the resources to affirm a perfectly good sense in which God creates the best world and our own world is not the best. The sense in question amounts to the double claim that at least one of the independent three-dimensional subregions of hyperspace is as valuable as any three-dimensional subregion could be, and that the particular three-space in which we find ourselves is not the fortunate one…[P]lenitudinous hyperspace…also provides the resources to maintain a…sense in which God creates absolutely every world worth creating, even if their number is indenumerable.16
The theistic multiverse, by any of these accounts, is not plenitudinous. The theistic multiverse does not include possible worlds or universes that correspond to every way things (non-skeptically) might have been. The multiverse includes only those possible worlds that meet or exceed some standard of goodness.In the absence of arguments to the contrary, it is reasonable to assume the Principle of Compatibility and that God can create one version of every possible good world. It follows that God never chooses between one possible world and another; rather, God examines all possible worlds and, for each possible world, decides whether to create it or not.17
In the theistic multiverse, every possible object, event, etc. exists at some time or other where the existence of these possible objects, events, etc. does not differ ontologically from the existence of actual objects, events, etc. There is no ontological difference between possible objects and actual objects, since the possible objects just are the actual objects. The theistic multiverse does not make the distinction between actual worlds, objects, events, states of affairs and possible worlds, objects, events, and states of affairs. The theistic multiverse is the only existing possible world, so God actualizes every possible world.The most general form of the principle of plenitude does not distinguish among possibilia. If there are possible objects, kinds of objects, events, kinds of events, states of affairs and so on, then the general principle entails that every possible object, kind of object, event, kind of event, state of affairs and so on exists at some time or other where the existence of merely possible objects, kinds of object, events, kinds of event, states of affairs and so on do not differ ontologically from the existence of actual objects, kinds of object, events, and so on.18
One big world, spatiotemporally interrelated, might have many different world-like parts. Ex hypothesi these are not complete worlds, but they could seem to be. They might be four-dimensional; they might have no boundaries; there might be little or no causal interaction between them. Indeed, each of these world-like parts of one big world might be a duplicate of some genuinely complete [Lewis] world.19
However the one big world is structured, it would include infinitely many world-like objects. Those world-like objects are parts of the vast, temporally infinite, universe. The defender of the theistic multiverse might argue that—contrary to what we might have thought—the one big world comprises all of metaphysical reality, and the totality of the world-like objects in the theistic multiverse represent every way things non-skeptically might have been.21Time might have the metric structure not of the real line, but rather of many copies of the real line laid end to end. We would have many different epochs, one after another. Yet each epoch would have infinite duration, no beginning, and no end. Inhabitants of different epochs would be spatiotemporally related, but their separation would be infinite…20
The multiverse theorist might argue analogously that if you thought there was a possible world for every way things non-skeptically might have been, how do you know you are not thinking of world-like objects? How do you know that you are not thinking that there is a world-like object for every way things non-skeptically might have been? If the theistic multiverse includes an infinity of world-like objects, and if the theistic multiverse—the one big world—is all there is to metaphysical reality, then we might be moved to conclude that metaphysical reality is in fact plenitudinous or close enough.If you thought, as I did too, that a single world might consist of many more or less isolated world-like parts, how sure can you be that you really had in mind the supposed possibility that I reject? Are you sure that it was an essential part of your thought that the world-like parts were in no way spatiotemporally related? Or might you not have had in mind, rather, one of these substitutes I offer? Or might your thought have been sufficiently lacking in specificity that the substitutes would do it justice?
6. Conclusions
Conflicts of Interest
References
- Almeida, Michael J. Forthcoming. Theism and Modal Realism, Unpublished manuscript, under review.
- Draper, Paul. 2004. Cosmic Fine-tuning and Terrestrial Suffering: Parallel problems for Naturalism and Theism. American Philosophical Quarterly 41: 311–21. [Google Scholar]
- Forrest, Peter. 1981. The Problem of Evil: Two Neglected Defenses. Sophia 20: 49–54. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hudson, Hud. 2005. The Metaphysics of Hyperspace. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kant, Immanuel. 1969. Universal Natural History and Theory of the Heavens. Translated by W. Hastie. Ann Arbour: University of Michigan Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kraay, Klaas. 2010. Theism, Possible Worlds, and the Multiverse. Philosophical Studies 147: 355–68. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kraay, Klaas. 2011. Theism and Modal Collapse. American Philosophical Quarterly 48: 361–72. [Google Scholar]
- Lewis, David. 1986. On the Plurality of Worlds. Oxford: Blackwell. [Google Scholar]
- Lovejoy, Arthur O. 1932. The Great Chain of Being. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Munitz, Milton K. 1951. One Universe or Many? Journal of the History of Ideas 12: 231–55. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- O’Connor, Timothy. 2008. Theism and Ultimate Explanation: The Necessary Shape of Contingency. Hoboken: Wiley-Blackwell. [Google Scholar]
- Turner, Donald. 2014. Revising the Many-Universes Solution to the Problem of Evil. In God and the Multiverse: Scientific, Philosophical, and Theological Perspectives. Edited by Klaas Kraay. New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- White, Michael. 2002. The Pope and the Heretic: The True Story of Giordano Bruno, the Man Who Dared to Defy the Roman Inquisition. New York: HarperCollins. [Google Scholar]
1 | I will argue in what follows that God should actualize every possible universe. This perhaps follows trivially on the account of multiverse creation under discussion. |
2 | See (White 2002). See also (Munitz 1951). |
3 | Ibid., p. 11. |
4 | See (Kraay 2010, p. 361). |
5 | Kraay’s terminology is that universes ‘comprise’ worlds. In Kraay’s metaphysics, possible worlds are maximal states of affairs. So it is perhaps better to see universes as actualized or concretized maximal states of affairs. |
6 | Ibid., p. 360. |
7 | Ibid., p. 117. |
8 | See op. cit. (O’Connor 2008, p. 117). |
9 | |
10 | Turner updates his views in (Turner 2014). His revised view, which he assimilates to Leibniz’s views, is that there are possible worlds that God cannot actualize. To make the revised view work it would have to be true that God actualizes some worlds as a matter of metaphysical necessity and nonetheless there are possible worlds that he cannot actualize. But there could be no possible worlds that it is metaphysically impossible for God to actualize. Alternatively, Turner could hold, with Leibniz, that it is not metaphysically impossible for God to actualize a less-than-ideal world. If that is true then it is hard to see why we need the theistic multiverse. |
11 | See (O’Connor 2008, p. 117). |
12 | Ibid., p. 117. |
13 | Ibid., p. 117. |
14 | Ibid., p. 118. |
15 | Ibid., p. 120. |
16 | See (Hudson 2005, p. 166 ff). The plenitudinous hyperspace Hudson describes is similar to a possible big world that Lewis proposes. See (Lewis 1986, p. 72). |
17 | (Forrest 1981). On Forrest’s ontology, possible worlds are collections of individual objects.
|
18 | |
19 | See (Lewis 1986, p. 70 ff). All of the bracketed material is my own. |
20 | Ibid., p. 72. |
21 | Certainly multiverse theorists run into the problem of such worlds being a part of metaphysical reality. But we do have some evidence from modal imagination that there is a rich variety of possible worlds in the pluriverse. |
© 2017 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Almeida, M. The Multiverse and Divine Creation. Religions 2017, 8, 258. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel8120258
Almeida M. The Multiverse and Divine Creation. Religions. 2017; 8(12):258. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel8120258
Chicago/Turabian StyleAlmeida, Michael. 2017. "The Multiverse and Divine Creation" Religions 8, no. 12: 258. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel8120258
APA StyleAlmeida, M. (2017). The Multiverse and Divine Creation. Religions, 8(12), 258. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel8120258