Having outlined the problem of thinking the political/transcendence at the end of metaphysics, and identifying two “criteria” for what might open after this closure, we may look at two approaches that directly attempt to address the problem as sketched above. Simon Critchley [
18] has also directly taken up the question raised by Nancy and Lacoue-Labarthe in
The Retreat of the Political [
7] by advocating the thought of Levinas, at the expense of Nancy’s own attempt to engage with the question as a “neutralizing of ethical transcendence”. Thus, the two approaches that will be explicated in a moment may be regarded as entering into a debate between Levinasian and Nancian thought on thinking an alternative sense of transcendence that allows for a politics of alterity. The debate hinges on the interpretation of Heidegger’s notion of being-with (
Mitsein). Also, as a counter to Critchley, a Nancian critique of the Levinasian approach to the problem will be advocated by highlighting Nancy’s relation to Levinas as not escaping the urge of a re-figuration, i.e., leaving the door open for an onto-theology of Love, something Critchley overlooks in his critique on Nancy by fixating only on his Heideggerian link.
3.1. Transcendence as the Trace of the Other
Bearing in mind the way in which the onto-theological figuration of the Subject’s metaphysical identity operates, i.e., synthesizing the other into the subject or the Same, we start off with Levinas’ rejection of Heidegger’s notion of being-with. In Levinas’
Time and the Other ([
19], p. 43), the relationship that is prescribed by the preposition
mit concerns an association of side by side, around a common term, that fails to be the face-to-face relationship from where the ethical command may take place. Moreover,
mit, functioning merely as a juxtaposition, “runs the risk of embodying a violent movement: a crowd walking side by side, the vicious rustling of a march” ([
20], p. 128). In other words, the rejection of Heidegger’s
Mitsein can be understood in relation to Levinas’ mistrust of any notion of community thought in terms of the
with, which will in an onto-theological fashion, lead to a single-minded destiny that leads to the mastery of the individual by a surrender to the Same (the identity of the community). In short, Heidegger from a Levinasian perspective does not ensure the ethical relation to the other with the designation of being-with as a mode of existence of
Dasein and thus does not overcome the constraints of the metaphysical identity as set out in his later work.
Instead, Levinas turns to Martin Buber to formulate in a more ethical fashion the relation of meeting with the other. Most significantly, Levinas finds in Buber the notion of a meeting in which reciprocity is possible that is both mutual and symmetrical. From this notion, Levinas eventually developed his concept of the “asymmetrical” relation with the other, based on the idea that responsibility lies before any experience and not in speaking out to the other in a symmetrical fashion. Responsibility, here, is not triggered by any event nor mediated by language but rests in the original difference as the original ethical relation ([
20], p. 130). Thus, what comes first is not the question of
Being as with Heidegger and the subsequent mode of being-
with, but rather the face-to-face relation, i.e., the question of ethics. Instead of the distance between the Same, or
Dasein in Heidegger’s case, and the Other being reduced where their opposition fades, “now, the Same is called into question by the other (
l ’Autre; to heteron) or, to use Levinas’ word, [called into question by] the ‘alterity’ (
altérité) of that which cannot be reduced to the Same, that which escapes the cognitive powers of the knowing subject” ([
21], pp. 4–5), and therefore transcends the subject. The ethical is then understood as the location of a point of alterity. Levinas calls this “exteriority” that which cannot be reduced to the Same. ([
21], p. 5). This exterior being is named the face (
visage) and defines “the way in which the other (
l’Autre) presents himself, exceeding the idea of the other in me” ([
22], p. 50). Restated, the face of the other is the site of alterity, which initiates the ethical relation that is not synthesizable to the metaphysical identity of the subject. Hence, the relationship between the subject and the other, which was previously asymmetrically skewed towards the subject, is now asymmetrically skewed towards the other because of the alterity of the other that transcends the subject.
We find here the “model” of how Levinas aims to meet the criteria for thinking after metaphysics, namely avoiding onto-theology by rethinking the question of the political/transcendence. For Levinas, this “model” of the one-to-one relation holds for a sense of community as well, which does not reduce difference. In
Totality and Infinity [
22], Levinas states that the ethical relation itself already constitutes the relation to a third,
le tier, which is the ethical relation to other forms and thus the “model” according to which the relation to all others is formed. Restated, “the third party looks at me in the eyes of the Other—language is justice” ([
22], p. 213), and hence my ethical obligation to the Other does not stay with the face to face relation but opens up to the question of justice for humanity as a whole ([
21], p. 226). Also, the passage from the ethical (face-to-face) to the political is not a chronological matter, but rather the ethical for Levinas is already the political. Restated: “The ethical relation does not take place in an a-political space outside the public realm; rather, ethics is always already political, the relation to the face is always already a relation to humanity as a whole” ([
21], p. 226).
Moreover, the relation to a third brings in the notion of equality and symmetry. Whereas I am in an asymmetrical ethical relation to the Other, this relation at the same time opens up to a symmetrical relation to humanity as a whole and the double structure of community in Levinas’ terms. It is the relation to the third, which is the communal bond we share among equals, i.e., in Critchley’s ([
21], p. 227) words, “a commonality among equals which is at the same time based on the inegalitarian moment of the ethical relation”. Levinas names this “human fraternity” and it is an attempt to decenter the metaphysical identity of the modern subject and community. The asymmetry skewed toward the Same is reverted to the Other; “subjectivity is ultimately described as a ‘hostage’ (
ôtage) to the Other” ([
23], p. 112). The subject is now preoccupied with the responsibility to the Other, before being preoccupied with itself.
How does the notion of transcendence relate to Levinas’ ethical, which is at the same time political, relation to the Other and/or a third? The answer, as we shall also see with Nancy, is the alternative sense of transcendence that enables the decentring of the subject or avoids onto-theology and the rethought relation to the other. Levinas does often refer directly to God, but this should not be understood as a reference to the traditional sense of transcendence that is the God of onto-theology. Instead, as Critchley points out, “after the death of that god, the ethical subject is able to discover the sense (
sens: both direction and signification) of transcendence that was lost or reified in metaphysics: the transcendence of the Other” ([
21], p. 113). Thus, God is the transcendence of the Other, which is located as a trace in the face of the other, as the movement of infinity. God or the Other, for Levinas, is an enigma that escapes comprehension or any form of thematisation, i.e., “the otherwise than Being” ([
21], p. 114). The question of community or the political is also directly intertwined with Levinas’ notion of transcendence. Its through
mono-theism, for Levinas, which the human fraternity that refers back to the approach of the Other (God) through the face of the other, is possible: “‘thanks to God’ that I am an Other for the others” ([
23], p. 158). It is due to the trace of the Other (God), Critchley outlines in arguing the case for Levinasian thought, that the community is prevented from becoming wholly immanent and therefore totalitarian. How does the Levinasian perspective answer the questions set out at the beginning of this article? In brief, on the question of what to anticipate in the end times, the response will entail more of a preoccupation than an anticipation; that is, the preoccupation with the responsibility of the Other. It is through this preoccupation that addresses one as the trace of the Other in the face of the other, that the movement of transcendence as infinity escapes comprehension, which also answers the second question by rethinking a notion of the political/transcendence after metaphysics that keeps open alterity. Thereby, through the notion of the relation to the third as common bond, a totalitarian sense of community is avoided.
3.2. Transcendence as Transimmanence
In contrast to Levinas, Nancy argues for the re-appropriation of Heidegger’s notion of
Mitsein: “Philosophy is, in sum, the thinking of being-with; because of this, it is also thinking-with as such” ([
17], p. 31). In other words, to think the question of relation that becomes imperative at the closure of metaphysics starts by retreating the analysis of
Dasein as always already existing
with-others; that is, an existence
with others, which needs no justification or comprehension from an already constituted subject. In this move, Nancy already indicates the program of decentering the Subject as the onto-theological figuration of modernity that comes to an end in the political form of totalitarianism. But, in placing being-with at the heart of his thinking, Nancy does not uncritically follow Heidegger’s analysis in
Sein und Zeit. For Nancy, the analytic of
Mitsein remains nothing more than a sketch, and, although
Mitsein is coessential with
Dasein, it remains in a subordinate position ([
17], p. 93).
Mitsein becomes subordinate because the focus falls on
Dasein’s choice of being authentic or inauthentic, resulting in the dissimulation of
Mitsein under the notion of
Das Man. Hence, “as such, the whole existential analytic still harbors some principle by which what it opens up is immediately closed off” ([
17], p. 93). Nancy calls for a reopening of the analysis of
Mitsein, which would neither lead to a completion thereof nor sets up
Mitsein as a principle. For, in principle, being-with escapes completion and the taking up of the place of a principle.
What is necessary, then, according to Nancy “is that we retrace the outline of its analysis and push it to the point where it becomes apparent that the coessentiality of being-with is nothing less than a matter of the co-originarity of meaning and that the ‘meaning of Being’ is only what it is (either ‘meaning’ or, primarily, its own ‘precomprehension’ as the constitution of existence) when it is given as with” ([
17], p. 93). Hence, differing from Levinas, Nancy does not place the emphasis in a reversal of the position of preoccupation from the Subject to the Other. Rather, the decentering of the subject lies in the move to co-originality of the subject and the other in being-
with. The essence of
Being, re-appropriating Heidegger ([
10], p. 42), which is not a substance but “to exist” (
Zu-sein), for Nancy is being-with;
being singular plural. And it marks an absolute equivalence: “Being does not preexist its singular plural. To be more precise, Being absolutely does not preexist; nothing preexists; only what exists exists” ([
17], p. 29). With this re-appropriation of Heidegger into his own terminology, Nancy aims to avoid onto-theology “because none of these three terms precedes or grounds the other, each designates the co-essence of the others” ([
17], p. 37). Correspondingly, every other is seen as an origin, from where the world is co-created; the world occurs at each moment of the world, as each time of Being in the realm of being-with of each time with every other time ([
17], p. 20). There is thus no set example, origin, or identity according to which to model others. Each time of Being constitutes a singularly unique origin of the world, making up the plurality of origins.
Moreover, Nancy, similar to Levinas, argues it was Heidegger’s analysis of the everydayness of being-with that lead him to base the notion of
Das Man on the domination of common as average or mediocre ([
17], p. 82). This analytic of
Mitsein, Nancy holds, does not do the measure of the
with justice because it conceals the essential common-with. It is rather from the everyday being-
with where the other is encountered as a unique origin with whom the world is co-created, differentiated as a singularity in the plurality of origins. Therefore, “Heidegger confuses the everyday with the undifferentiated, the anonymous, and the statistical” ([
17], p. 9). The ordinary is now re-defined as always exceptional, even though we may understand little of its character as origin: “What we receive most communally as ‘strange’ is that the ordinary itself is originary. With existence laid open in this way and the meaning of the world being what it is, the exception is the rule” ([
17], p. 20). Furthermore, the
with of being-
with, which lies between the I (subject) and the other, belongs to neither. The
with, instead, exposes one to an-other. The
with or
cum in Latin is nothing as in no-thing, not a substance, identity, history, value, and so on that may be made into a figuration. Nor is it a category of the subject. It is rather the exposure to our ontological mode of existence as
Mitsein.
It is this experience of the ontological co-originality of the subject and the other, through the
with, which transcends us, cutting across, as Nancy puts it, the I and the other, exposing one to the immanence of the other, that composes Nancy’s notion of transcendence as transimmanence. In typical Nancian fashion, the prefix
trans from transcendence is rethought/”retreated” to bring about a word play with an alternative sense of the notion: “within the discourse about alterity, a general mode of trans- (transport, trans-action, transcription, transfer, transmission, transformation, transparency, transubstantiation, transcendence) continually runs along-side the mode of
cum, but it will never be able to eclipse it or replace it” ([
17], p. 78). Most notable,
trans as designating a movement is used in relation to transcendence as the movement of
with, the cutting across. The movement that is transcendence, however, goes nowhere outside of the world, but rather stays in the immanent world, not as a substance, but by going (moving) to an-other, as circulating, i.e., movement as
transimmanence. Rephrased, this is the “outside within” that Anné Verhoef ([
24], p. 10) writes about in his contribution to this special issue of
Religions, or better still the “outside-within-between”; meaning “that cannot be divorced from the plurality of singular bodies” ([
25], p. 97). The movement comes and goes and is not fixed (inside or outside the world) nor is it infinite. It is finite but occurs infinitely. In sum, transimmanence refers to the occurrence of sense that happens each time between a subject and an-other; sense occurs coextensively as the experience of being-
with, cut across, exposed to one an-other. “Roughly speaking, sense passes along being without issuing from within it or from outside it; it slides through social relations without substantializing them. It makes them meaningful without giving them a (reducible) meaning” ([
25], p. 167).
Along these lines, Nancy’s notion of community can also be unpacked. Community, for Nancy, is inoperative. A sense of community, therefore, never becomes fixed. There is a constant construction and destruction (autoproduction) of the meaning of community. Thus, the place of power in totalitarianism that becomes the empty space Lefort refers to in democracy either constantly becomes filled with a new figuration of community that replaces the previous one or emptied. From another perspective: community is not a group of people who have some-thing in common, that share a common-being. It is rather a place where people are (being) in common Being-in common as being-
with. But, since this being-
with transcends both the subject and other, this “‘in-common’ cannot be controlled by them and so eludes them” ([
26], p. 37). This implies that anything can happen, peace or violence, order or disorder, and so on, depending on the figuration of community. Hence, a community is possible where the “forgetting” of human value takes place by a figuration that fills the place of power rather than keeping the space open as Lefort writes on democracy. The co-creation of the world does not ensure a positive (or negative) outcome. Anything may transpire, because “the being-in-common is a condition and not a value (nor counter-value)” ([
26], p. 38).
3.4. A Nancian Reply, Critique, and Rethinking of Levinas
Nancy, in addition to his explicit relation to Heidegger’s thinking, may also be considered in connection with his critique and re-appropriation of Levinas’ thought. This most notable in the text
Shattered Love, something Critchley overlooks in his critique. Nancy himself, writing on love, acknowledges his debt to Levinas: “Every philosophical inquiry on love today carries an obvious debt toward Levinas, as well as points of proximity, such as are easily detected here. For Levinas cleared the path toward what one can call, in the language of
Totality and Infinity, a metaphysics of love, to the point that this metaphysics commands, at bottom, his entire oeuvre” ([
28], pp. 104–5). But Nancy, in a Derridean ethical manner, does not merely return the gift through eulogy, but rather disseminates Levinas’ ethics through a critique and elaboration ([
29], p. 452). Nancy’s critique begins with explicating how, for Levinas, love remains equivocal and thereby reduces it to self-love, i.e., egotism. To love in this way is to love oneself within love, which means a return to the self (the Same). Correspondingly, love’s transcendence lifts the equivocation only by transcending itself into fecundity, filiation, and fraternity ([
28], p. 105). In other words, this perplexity leads Levinas to distinguish between two types of love;
Agape, the love of the ethical face-to-face relation that preserves the love for the other, and
Eros, or erotic love which comprises egotism. This distinction, additionally, contains an implied hierarchy, namely
Agape above
Eros. Moreover, there is a movement in the hierarchy enabled by the trace of the Other that decenters the subject (self-love) toward the discovery of the ethical responsibility, which to recall the earlier discussion, is at the same time the passage to politics. This movement, Nancy holds, is teleologically determined: “This teleology proceeds from the first given of his thought, ‘the epiphany of the face’: love is the movement stressed by this epiphany, a movement that transcends it in order to reach, beyond the face, beyond vision and the ‘you,’ the ‘hidden-never hidden enough-absolutely’” ([
28], p. 105). More importantly, the moment of hierarchizing teleology leads to another moment where Levinas overcomes, briefly, the ontic dialectic of the face-to-face, he holds to be primordial. This moment is when the erotic self-loving relation to the other is sublated in paternal and fraternal love, after which the face returns once more. The ontic has to be overcome, although briefly, in the moment of Love. Finitude is overcome to reach infinity, beyond the subject as the trace of the Other. Thus, the primordiality of the ontic is challenged. In contrast, for Nancy, what is primordial is the ontological being-with as love. Love deconstitutes the subject; or again, the relation to the ontic face that constitutes a subject comes second for Nancy and is perhaps also why Levinas requires to overcome it, briefly, to reach what is more primordial, i.e., love.
Restated, love, for Nancy is the movement of transimmanence: “Transcendence will thus be better named the crossing of love. What love cuts across, and what it reveals by its crossing, is what is exposed to the crossing, to its coming-and-going-and this is nothing other than finitude” ([
28], p. 98). Finitude, as being-with, is the site of co-originarity and the co-creation of meaning. Hence, for Nancy, there cannot be a hierarchy of love, but only the infinite plurality of singular loves, which Nancy calls the shatters of love: “There are no parts, moments, types, or stages of love. There is only an infinity of shatters: love is wholly complete in one sole embrace or in the history of a life, in jealous passion or in tireless devotion. It consists as much in taking as in giving, as much in requiring as in renouncing, as much in protecting as in exposing. It is in the jolt and in appeasement, in the fever and in serenity, in the exception and in the rule” ([
28], p. 105).
Nor can love be reduced to only erotic egotism: “It is sexual, and it is not: it cuts across the sexes with another difference (Derrida, in
Geschlecht, initiated the analysis of this) that does not abolish them but displaces their identities. Whatever my love is, it cuts across my identity, any sexual property, that objectification by which I am a masculine or feminine subject” ([
28], p. 105). In the cutting-across the subject is also broken into, returned to itself, fractured, decentered. To think love, then, would “demand a boundless generosity toward all these possibilities, and it is this generosity that would command reticence: the generosity not to choose between loves, not to privilege, not to hierarchize, not to exclude” ([
28], p. 83).
Finally, we can ask what one may anticipate in these end times in Nancy’s terms. One might, as Critchley ([
18], p. 65) claims, expect a positive over-determination of with, in the sense of community, but to merely equate the critique from Levinas against Heidegger, is not convincing. In contrast, Nancy’s insistence on a “boundless generosity” of what might happen in the mutual exposure of one to an-other, in the attitude of reticence, of holding open the question, in keeping the tension of the dialectic, and in avoiding the path down the road to an onto-theology by setting up a hierarchy of love with
Agape as the highest and grounding principle and figuration; the analytic of being-with is effectively redirected in evading a figuration of community. The crossing of love exposes finitude and not something infinite (the Other): “Because the singular being is finite, the other cuts across it (and never does the other ‘penetrate’ the singular being or ‘unite itself’ with it or ‘commune’). Love unveils finitude. Finitude is the being of that which is infinitely inappropriable, not having the consistency of its essence either in itself or in a dialectical sublation of the self. Neither the other nor love nor I can appropriate itself nor be appropriated (‘Infinity of one and of the other, in the other and in the one’—Valery)” ([
28], p. 98).
The attitude of reticence also reveals the ethical imperative with which one is confronted in every exposure to the other, better described by what Nancy calls the “promise of love”. Take the formulation “I love you” in Nancy’s terms. Love, of course, serves here as the with of being-with, the movement of love as transimmanence, which mutually exposes the I and the you—one to an-other. The exposure of love does not predetermine the outcome; rather the exposure of love is the promise of love, a risk. The risk lies in that the other does not love me back or that I do not keep the promise of my love. The exposure of love reveals the promise of love, which is a risk because the promise has to be kept: the I have to go on and love the you, and the you the I. And perhaps one of them fails in keeping the promise.
From another position, because the movement of love does not become fixed, it comes and goes; the “I love you”, names nothing and does nothing. It is finite. It only reveals the promise of love, the law which is the ethical imperative that love must arrive, and that nothing can suspend the rigor of this law ([
28], p. 100). However, here again we see the counter to over-determination; the promise cannot assure the completion of this ethical imperative because it does not “anticipate or assure the future is possible that one day I will no longer love you, and this possibility cannot be taken away from love—it belongs to it. It is against this possibility, but also with it, that the promise is made, the word given” ([
28], p. 100). Moreover, the imperative is that the promise must be kept, but if it is not kept, this does not mean that there was no love or that there was not love. Love is only faithful to itself, meaning that love is not the promise (which must be kept) plus the keeping of that promise; not the revealing of the ethical imperative plus providing the ethical act
par excellence. Hence, with the risk of the promise of love anything can happen — as with the inoperativeness of the community. The co-creation may lead to peace or war, to the ethical act or the forgetting of human value, but once more, this does not mean that love was not there touching, cutting across, and exposing the one to an-other. “What” to anticipate, accordingly, becomes a “how” to anticipate; an attitude, which is an attitude, on the one side, of reticence in terms of constructing absolute re-figurations. And on the other, that we may only allude to here, of
adoration [
30].