The Freedom of Facticity
Abstract
:1. Introduction
“Here I am—Jew, or Aryan, handsome or ugly, one-armed, etc. I am all of this for the Other with no hope of changing it.”(BN p. 544)
2. Part 1: The Facticity of Freedom
2.1. The Freedom of Choice
“Much more than he appears to ‘make himself’ man seems ‘to be made’ by climate and the earth, race and class, language, the history of collectivity of which he is a part, heredity, the individual circumstances of his childhood, acquired habits, the great and small events of his life.”(BN p. 503)
2.2. The Facticity of Freedom
“Thus we come to catch a glimpse of the paradox of freedom: there is freedom only in a situation, and there is a situation only through freedom.”(BN p. 511)
“Thus our freedom itself creates the obstacles from which we suffer.”(BN p. 516)
“Without facticity freedom would not exist—as a power of nihilation and of choice—and without freedom facticity would not be discovered and would have no meaning.”(BN p. 517)
2.3. Freedom and Identification
“Belonging to the human species is defined by the use of very elementary and very general techniques. To know how to walk, to know how to take hold, to know how to pass judgment on the surface and the relative size of perceived objects, to know how to speak, to know how in general to distinguish the true from the false, etc.”(BN p. 533)
“I am not thrown only face to face with the brute existent. I am thrown into a worker’s world, a French world, a world of Lorraine of the South, which offers me its meanings without my having done anything to disclose them.”(BN p. 535)
“Here I am—Jew, or Aryan, handsome or ugly, one-armed, etc. I am all of this for the Other with no hope of changing it.”(BN p. 544)
“In fact, according to the free possibilities which I choose, I can disobey the prohibition, pay no attention to it, or, on the contrary, confer upon it a coercive value which it can hold only because of the weight which I attach to it.”(BN p. 545)
“The true limit of my freedom lies purely and simply in the very fact that an Other apprehends me as the Other-as-object and in that second corollary fact that my situation ceases for the Other to be a situation and becomes an objective form in which I exist as an objective structure.”(BN p. 546)
“It is only by my recognising the freedom of anti-Semites (whatever use they make of it) and by my assuming this being-a-Jew that I am a Jew for them; it is only thus that being-a-Jew will appear as the external objective of the situation.”(BN p. 547)
“How then shall I experience the objective limits of my being: Jew, Aryan, ugly, handsome, king, servant, untouchable, etc.—when will language have informed me as to which of these are my limits?”(BN p. 548)
3. Part 2: The Freedom of Facticity
3.1. Autonomous and Heteronomous Freedom
3.2. The Freedom of Facticity
“What then is freedom? To be born is both to be born of the world and to be born into the world. The world is already constituted, but also never completely constituted; in the first case we are acted upon, in the second we are open to an infinite number of possibilities. But this analysis is still abstract, for we exist in both ways at once. There is, therefore, never determinism and never absolute choice, I am never a thing and never bare consciousness. In fact, even our own pieces of initiative, even the situations which we have chosen, bear us on, once they have been entered upon by virtue of a state rather than an act. The generality of the ‘rôle’ and of the situation comes to the aid of decision, and in this exchange between the situation and the person who takes it up, it is impossible to determine precisely the ‘share contributed by the situation’ and the ‘share contributed by freedom’.”
3.3. Freedom and Liberation
4. Conclusions
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
References
- Alcoff, Linda Martín. 2006. Visible Identities: Race, Gender, and the Self. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Appiah, Kwame A. 2003. Race, culture, identity. In The African Philosophy Reader. Edited by P. H. Coetzee and A. P. J. Roux. New York: Routledge, pp. 373–91. [Google Scholar]
- Bernasconi, Robert. 2007. How to Read Sartre. London: Granta Books. [Google Scholar]
- Cerbone, David R. 2006. Understanding Phenomenology. Chesham: Acumen. [Google Scholar]
- Du Bois, William Edward Burghardt. 1975. Dusk of Dawn: An Essay toward an Autobiography of a Race Concept. Milwood: Kraus-Thomson Organization Limited. [Google Scholar]
- Fanon, Frantz. 2004. The Wretched of the Earth. New York: Grove Press. [Google Scholar]
- Føllesdal, Dagfinn. 1981. Sartre on Freedom. In The Philosophy of Jean-Paul Sartre. Edited by P. A. Schilpp. La Salle: Open Court, The Library of Living Philosophers. [Google Scholar]
- Freire, Paulo. 2000. Pedagogy of the Oppressed. London: Continuum, New York: Continuum. [Google Scholar]
- Gordon, Lewis R. 1997. Black Existential Philosophy. In Existence in Black: An Anthology of Black Existential Philosophy. Edited by L. Gordon. New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Gordon, Lewis R. 2008. An Introduction to Africana Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Gordon, Lewis R. 2015. Sartre. In The Encyclopedia of Political Thought, 1st ed. Edited by Michael T. Gibbons. Somerset: John Wiley & Sons, Ltd. [Google Scholar]
- Hacking, Ian. 1992. Making up People. In Forms of Desire: Sexual Orientation and the Social Constructionist Controversy. Edited by Edward Stein. New York: Routledge, pp. 69–88. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, Martin. 1962. Being and Time. Translated by J. Macquarrie, and E. Robinson. Oxford: Blackwell. [Google Scholar]
- Heidegger, Martin. 1971. Poetry, Language, Thought. Translated by A. Hofstadter. New York: Harper and Row. [Google Scholar]
- Malpas, Jeff. 2006. Heidegger’s Topology. Cambridge: The MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
- Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. 1962. Phenomenology of Perception. Translated by C. Smith. London and New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Moran, Dermot. 2000. Introduction to Phenomenology. London and New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Olivier, Abraham. 2015. Heidegger in the Township. South African Journal of Philosophy 34: 240–54. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sartre, Jean-Paul. 1957. Transcendence of the Ego. Translated by F. Williams, and R. Kirkpatrick. New York: Noonday Press. [Google Scholar]
- Sartre, Jean-Paul. 1964. Words. Translated by B. Frechtman. New York: Braziller. [Google Scholar]
- Sartre, Jean-Paul. 1965. Essays in Existentialism. Edited by W. Baskin. Secaucus: Citadel Press. [Google Scholar]
- Sartre, Jean-Paul. 1982. Critique of Dialectical Reason. Translated by A. Sheridan-Smith. London: Verso. [Google Scholar]
- Sartre, Jean-Paul. 1986. Troubled Sleep. Translated by E. Sutton. London: Penguin. [Google Scholar]
- Sartre, Jean-Paul. 2003. Being and Nothingness. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Taylor, Charles. 1994. Multiculturalism and ‘The Politics of Recognition’. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Webber, Jonathan. 2011. Freedom. In The Routledge Companion to Phenomenology. Edited by S. Luft and S. Overgaard. New York: Routledge, pp. 327–35. [Google Scholar]
1 | Henceforth Sartre’s Being and Nothingness (Sartre 2003) is referred to as BN. |
2 | See also Appiah’s more recent 2016 BBC Reith Lectures, entitled Mistaken Identities. |
3 | Du Bois (1975, pp. 116–17) as referred to by Appiah. |
4 | Quote taken from Appiah (2003, p. 438). |
5 | Appiah accuses Sartre for not taking the theoretical commitments of collective identification seriously enough—I discuss his critique in Section 2.3. |
6 | See Webber (2011, 327ff). |
7 | |
8 | To be sure, I shall give a relatively lengthy discussion of Sartre’s position first in order to make my use of and difference from his position clear. This discussion is also meant to help introduce the non-specialist to Sartre, while the specialist might prefer to glance at the first part of my paper and advance to the second part. |
9 | Webber refers, among others, to Føllesdal’s (1981) charge against Sartre. |
10 | See, for instance, BN pp. 457 and 475. See also the key to special terminology in Being and Nothingness. |
11 | |
12 | BN pp. 40ff, 46ff, 99ff. |
13 | |
14 | Sartre maintains that facticity and contingency are really one (BN p. 508). Mostly he speaks of facticity, thereby including contingency. I shall follow his practice and use facticity in its extended sense including contingency. |
15 | In this sense, the typical accusation that Sartre’s early work is overwhelmingly modernist and individualist, not allowing constitutive connections with others, as made by Alcoff (2006, p. 69), is not quite justified. |
16 | This goes back to Sartre’s famous analysis of the “Other-as-a-look” (BN pp. 276ff.) which I confine to my discussion of collective identification. |
17 | See Gordon (2015, p. 1). |
18 | This alludes to Merleau-Ponty’s statement that the world chooses us and we choose the world, in his critical discussion of Sartre’s concept of freedom in The phenomenology of perception. I come back to Merleau-Ponty’s view in Section 3.2. |
19 | See also the discussion of Malpas (2006, p. 254). |
20 | Lewis Gordon helpfully points out this distinction (Gordon 2008, p. 83). |
21 | Fanon explicitly refers to liberation in terms of the transformation of the situation, particularly, the decolonisation of the situation (Fanon 2004, p. 2) versus the liberties taken by the colonisers (pp. 33, 50). |
© 2018 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Olivier, A. The Freedom of Facticity. Religions 2018, 9, 110. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel9040110
Olivier A. The Freedom of Facticity. Religions. 2018; 9(4):110. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel9040110
Chicago/Turabian StyleOlivier, Abraham. 2018. "The Freedom of Facticity" Religions 9, no. 4: 110. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel9040110
APA StyleOlivier, A. (2018). The Freedom of Facticity. Religions, 9(4), 110. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel9040110