1. Introduction
As a generalization of
-algebras, the notion of
d-algebras was introduced by Neggers and Kim [
1]. They discussed some relations between
d-algebras and
-algebras as well as several other relations between
d-algebras and oriented digraphs. Several properties on
d-algebras, e.g.,
d-ideals, deformations, and companion
d-algebras, were studied [
2,
3,
4]. Recently, some notions of the graph theory were applied to the theory of groupoids [
5].
The notion of an implicativity has a very important role in the study of -algebras. An implicative -algebra has some connections with distributive lattices, Boolean algebras, and semi-Brouwerian algebras.
In this paper, we generalize the notion of the implicativity, which is a useful tool for investigation of -algebras by using the notion of a word in general algebraic structures, the most simple mathematical structure, i.e., in the theory of a groupoid. Moreover, we generalized the notion of the implicativity by using -product “□”, and obtain the notion of a weakly i-implicativity, and obtain several properties in -algebras and other algebraic structures.
2. Preliminaries
A groupoid
is said to be a
left-zero-semigroup if
for all
. Similarly, a groupoid
is said to be a
right-zero-semigroup if
for all
[
6]. A groupoid
with constant 0 is said to be a
d-algebra [
1] if it satisfies the following conditions:
- (I)
,
- (II)
,
- (III)
and imply for all .
For brevity, we call
X a
d-algebra. In a
d-algebra
X, we define a binary relation
by
if and only if
. A
d-algebra
is said to be an
edge if
for all
. Example 1 below is an edge
d-algebra. For general references on
d-algebras we refer to [
2,
3,
4].
A
-
algebra [
7] is a
d-algebra
X satisfying the following additional axioms:
- (IV)
,
- (V)
for all .
Theorem 1 ([
7])
. If is a -algebra, thenfor all . Example 1. Let be a set with the following table:Then, is an edge d-algebra which is not a -algebra, since . For general references on -algebras, we refer to [
7,
8,
9].
Let
be a partially ordered set with minimal element 0, and let
be its associated groupoid, i.e., * is a binary operation on
X defined by
Then, is a -algebra, and we call it a standard -algebra.
A
-algebra
is said to be
implicative if
;
commutative if
;
positive implicative if
for all
[
7]. It is well known that a
-algebra is implicative if and only if it is both commutative and positive implicative. A group
X is said to be
Boolean if every element of
X is its own inverse.
The notion of Smarandache algebras emerged and has been applied to several algebraic structures [
10,
11,
12]. Two algebras
and
are said to be
Smarandache disjoint [
13,
14] if we add some axioms of an algebra
to an algebra
, then the algebra
becomes a trivial algebra, i.e.,
; or if we add some axioms of an algebra
to an algebra
, then the algebra
becomes a trivial algebra, i.e.,
. Note that if we add an axiom
of an algebra
to another algebra
, then we replace the binary operation “∘” in
by the binary operation “*”.
Let
be the collection of all groupoids
defined on
X. For any elements
and
in
, we define a binary operation “□” on
by
where
for any
. Using the notion, Kim and Neggers proved the following theorem.
Theorem 2 ([
6])
. is a semigroup, i.e., the operation “□" as defined in general is associative. Furthermore, the left zero semigroup is an identity for this operation. 3. (Weakly) Implicativity in Groupoids
By using the notion of words, we generalize the notion of an implicativity in groupoids. A groupoid (or a
-algebra)
is said to be
implicative if
for all
.
Proposition 1. If is a left-zero semigroup (respectively, a right-zero semigroup), i.e., (respectively, ) for all , then is implicative.
Proof. If is a left-zero semigroup, then for all . It follows that , which proves that is implicative. Similarly, if is a right-zero semigroup, then it is also implicative. □
Proposition 2. The class of implicative groupoids and the class of groups are Smarandache disjoint.
Proof. Assume is both a group and an implicative groupoid. Then, for all . This shows that . □
Notice that the class of implicative groupoids is equationally defined and thus that it is a variety, i.e., it is closed under subgroups, epimorphic images, and direct products.
A groupoid
is said to be
weakly implicative if there exists a word
such that, for all
,
Note that is an expression of “x”, e.g., , and a zero element “0”, e.g., , if necessary.
Proposition 3. Let be a weakly implicative groupoid with . If is a -algebra, then it is an implicative -algebra.
Proof. Let be a weakly implicative groupoid with . Since is a -algebra, we obtain for all . Hence, is an implicative -algebra. □
Corollary 1. Let be an edge d-algebra. If is a weakly implicative with , then is an implicative edge d-algebra.
Proof. If is an edge d-algebra, then and for all . By Proposition 3, is an implicative edge d-algebra. □
Let
be a groupoid. Define a binary operation “•” on
X by
for all
. We call
an
oppositie groupoid of a groupoid
.
Theorem 3. The opposite groupoid of a -algebra is weakly implicative.
Proof. Let be a -algebra and let for all . Then, . Hence, is weakly implicative. □
Proposition 4. There is no nontrivial implicative opposite groupoid derived from a -algebra.
Proof. Let be a -algebra and let . Assume that is implicative. Then, for all , i.e., , a contradiction. □
Theorem 4. The class of weakly implicative groupoids and the class of groups are Smarandache disjoint.
Proof. Assume is both a group and a weakly groupoid. Then, there exists a word such that for all . It follows that for all . Since , we obtain , a constant. Hence, , i.e., , a contradiction. □
4. Levels of Implicativities
Let be a groupoid and let . We define binary operations “” on X by and for all , where . Let be a word of x. We define the following levels of implicativities as follows:
- Level 0:
(i) (weakly 0-implicative); (ii) (implicative).
- Level 1:
(i) (weakly 1-implicative); (ii) (1-implicative).
- Level i:
(i) (weakly i-implicative); (ii) (i-implicative).
Theorem 5. Let be a group with . Then, X is weakly 1-implicative if and only if X is a Boolean group.
Proof. Let be a weakly 1-implicative groupoid. Then, for all . It follows that . If we let , then , and hence for all . If we let , then . Hence for all . Hence, is a Boolean group.
Assume
is a Boolean group. Then,
for all
. It follows that, for any
,
Hence,
is a weakly 1-implicative groupoid. □
Theorem 6. Let be a group. If is a weakly i-implicative groupoid, then it is i-implicative.
Proof. Given , we have , , , and . Similarly, we obtain . Since X is a group and is a word on x, we have . This shows that for all . Hence, for all , proving that is i-implicative. □
Proposition 5. Let be a group. If for any , then X is i-implicative.
Proof. Given , we have . Hence, X is i-implicative. □
Theorem 7. Let be a -algebra. If it is weakly i-implicative, then it is i-implicative.
Proof. Suppose that is weakly i-implicative. Then, there exists a mapping such that, for any , . Since is a -algebra, we obtain . In this fashion, we obtain . Thus, , which proves that . Hence, is i-implicative. □
Theorem 8. Let be both a weakly 0-implicative groupoid and an 1-implicative groupoid. If , then is weakly 0-implicative.
Proof. Since
, we have
for any
. It follows from
is 1-implicative that
for all
. Let
. Since
is weakly 0-implicative, we have
for some word
. It follows that
which proves that
is weakly 0-implicative. □
Corollary 2. Let be both an implicative groupoid and a 1-implicative groupoid. If , then is implicative.
Proof. Let in Theorem 8. □
Let be a groupoid and let . If we assume that for any , then and hence . In this fashion, we obtain for all .
Theorem 9. Every implicative -algebra is an i-implicative -algebra where .
Proof. Let
be an implicative
-algebra. Then,
for any
. It follows from Theorem 1 that
i.e.,
. This shows that
for any
. Hence,
is an
i-implicative
-algebra. □
5. Weakly Implicative Groupoids with P
A groupoid
is said to have a
condition if it satisfies the following condition, for any
,
and a groupoid
is said to have a
condition if it satisfies the following condition, for any
,
i.e.,
. Assume that a groupoid
has the condition
. Then,
for any
. Similarly,
. In this fashion, we have
for any
. Hence,
satisfies the condition
.
Proposition 6. If a groupoid is a weakly i-implicative groupoid with , then it is a weakly -implicative groupoid.
Proof. Let be a weakly i-implicative groupoid with . Then, and for any , where . It follows that for any . This proves that is a weakly -implicative groupoid. □
Theorem 10. Any standard -algebra has the condition .
Proof. Let be a standard -algebra. Given , we have 3 cases: (i) ; (ii) ; (iii) . Case (i). If , then . Case (ii). If , then . Case (iii). If , then and . It follows that . Hence, . □
Note that nonstandard -algebras need not have the condition . Consider the following example.
Example 2. Let be a set with the following table:Then, is a -algebra ([7], p. 245). Since and , we have , i.e., does not satisfy the condition . A groupoid
is said to have a
condition if
, where
Theorem 11. Let be a groupoid with a condition . If satisfies the following conditions: (i) ; (ii) ; (iii) ; (iv) implies , then for all .
Proof. Case (i). If , then . By (iv), we have . If , then . If , then . Case (ii). If , then and hence . Case (iii). If , then and . It follows that . □
Theorem 12. Let be a groupoid with a condition . If satisfies the following conditions: (i) ; (ii) for all , then satisfies the condition .
Proof. Given , if , then and hence . If , then and hence . If , then and hence , proving the theorem. □
Theorem 13. Let K be a field and let . Define a binary operation “*" on K by for all . If is an implicative groupoid, then is one of the following:
- (i)
,
- (ii)
,
- (iii)
.
Proof. Since
is an implicative groupoid, we have
for any
. It follows that
, and
. Case 1. Assume
. Since
, we obtain
, i.e.,
. If
, then
, since
. Hence,
. If
, then
A is arbitrary, since
. Hence,
. Case 2. Assume
. Since
, we obtain
, i.e.,
. □
Theorem 14. Let K be a field and let . Define a binary operation “*" on K by for all . If satisfies the condition , then is one of the following:
- (i)
,
- (ii)
,
- (iii)
,
- (iv)
.
Proof. Since
and
, we have
for any
. It follows that
and
. This shows that
or
. Case 1.
. Since
, we obtain that either
or
. If
, then
. If
, then
, i.e.,
. Hence,
. Case 2.
. Since
, we obtain
. If
, then
, i.e.,
. Hence,
. If
, then
, and hence
A is arbitrary. Hence,
. □