1. Introduction
A preferential arrangement on
is a ranking of the elements of
where ties are allowed. We denote
as the set of all preferential arrangements on
. For example,
The number of
is denoted by
. These numbers
are also called the Fubini numbers [
1], the ordered Bell numbers [
2] (Section 5.2), or surjection number [
3] (p. 109). They count the number of weak orderings on a set of
n elements. The term “preferential arrangement” was first introduced by Gross [
4]. The explicit expression of
is usually given by [
5] (Equation (13))
where
is the Stirling numbers of the second kind. The recursive relation and the generating function
were first given by Cayley [
6] in 1859. As a preferential arrangement is nothing else than a sequence of non-empty sets, this directly gives the generating function SEQ(SET
(
))
, and this also explains the recurrence and the link with Stirling numbers (see e.g., [
3] (p. 109)). Accordingly, this number
has been given various interpretations and has also been connected to a number of well-known combinatorial sequences [
5,
7,
8,
9].
The Delannoy number
is defined for nonnegative integers
m and
n by [
1] (p. 81):
The explicit expression of
and the generating function [
1] are given by:
The significances of these numbers are explained in [
10,
11]. Recently, Sun [
12] and Liu, Li, & Wang [
13] investigated some congruences relations on them. Qi, Čerňanová, Shi, & Guo [
14] established several explicit expressions, including determinantal expressions. Moreover, Delannoy numbers are related to some adic dynamical systems [
15].
Based on some algebraic identities in Hoffman’s harmonic algebra, we obtained an interesting identity which connects the numbers and :
Main Theorem. For a pair of nonnegative integers n and m, we have:where and are the Stirling numbers of the first kind and the second kind, respectively. Our paper is organized as follows. In
Section 2, we present some algebraic preliminaries on Hoffman’s harmonic algebras and provide the basic identity which we will use. In
Section 3, we prove the Main Theorem and also establish some more formulas. We introduce combinatorial viewpoints to approach the Main Theorem in the last section.
2. Some Preliminaries on Harmonic Algebras
We summarize the algebraic setup introduced by Hoffman [
16,
17] as follows. Let us consider the coding of multi-indices
, where
are positive integers and
, by words (that is, by monomials in non-commutative variables) over the alphabet
by the rule
The weight (or the degree) coincides with the total degree of the monomial , whereas the length (or the depth) is the degree with respect to the variable x.
Let
be the
-algebra of polynomials in two non-commutative variables, which is graded by the degree (where each of the variables
x and
y is assumed to be of degree 1); we identify the algebra
with the graded
-vector space
spanned by the monomials in the variables
x and
y ([
16]).
We also introduce the graded -vector spaces and , where denotes the unit (the empty word of weight 0 and length 0) of the algebra . Then, the space can be regarded as the subalgebra of generated by the words .
Let us define a bilinear product ∗ (the stuffle product or harmonic product) on
by the rules
for any word
w, and
for any words
u,
v, any letters
or
y (
), and any generators
,
of the subalgebra
, and then extend the above rules to the whole subalgebra
by linearity. It is known that each of the above products is commutative and associative. We denote the algebra
by
, and we call it a harmonic algebra (or Hoffman’s harmonic algebra). For our convenience, we let
Lemma 1. Let be positive integers. Then:where is a r-tuple of positive integers. Proof. We use an induction on
k to prove Equation (
5).
The above identity follows from the induction hypothesis. Since
we have:
The former summand has
instances of
and the latter summand has
r instances of
in each summation. We rewrite the summation such that each summand has the same instances of
.
We simplify the summation in the above identity as follows.
Combining the first term and the last term , we get our conclusion. ☐
We define a rational linear map:
by
and
where
is the multiple zeta value (MZV) [
18,
19,
20]. Since
, we have
. Thus, this guarantees that
is well-defined. Then, this map is an algebra homomorphism [
21]:
. If we apply this map to the result of the above lemma, then we have the following identity:
where
are positive integers and
. This result was recently proved in [
22] (Theorem 1.3) by another method. In fact, this result can be also obtained from [
21] (Proposition 3) and [
23] (Proposition 4), and it is also true for
, provided one uses stuffle-regularized MZVs.
It is worth noting that
is isomorphic to the algebra QSym of quasi-symmetric functions, and QSym has the algebra Sym of symmetric functions as a subalgebra [
24]. The well-known identity
of symmetric functions (which follows from the multinomial theorem), where
is the monomial symmetric function corresponding to the partition
. We define a monomorphism Sym
sending
to
. We could use this map to send the above identity to Equation (
5).
We use the result in Lemma 1 to get some relations between Delannoy numbers and preferential arrangements in the next section.
3. Preferential Arrangements and Delannoy Numbers
The definition of the stuffle product ∗ indicates that the stuffle product of two multiple zeta values of depth
m and
n will produce
numbers of multiple zeta values ([
25]). We will give another proof using a combinatorial approach in the next section.
The Delannoy number can be viewed as the number of lattice paths from to in which only east , north , and northeast steps are allowed. The lattice paths described here are called Delannoy paths which give an alternative characterization of the stuffle product.
By counting the number of multiple zeta values in Equation (
5) produced from the stuffle product, we obtain the following interesting identity which connects
and
.
Proposition 1. For a pair of nonnegative integers n and k, we havewhere are the Stirling numbers of the second kind. Proof. There are
terms in the right-hand side of Equation (
5). Since
, we have
by the inclusion–exclusion principle. By [
26] (Equation (6.19)),
we can write the above number as
Since the stuffle product of two MZVs of depth
p and
q produces
numbers of MZVs, we count the numbers of MZVs in the above identity, and then we have:
Combining Equations (
1) and (
7) and the special values of the Stirling numbers of the second kind at zeros, i.e.,
whenever
, we conclude the following result:
This completes our proof. ☐
Our Main Theorem is just the Stirling inversion applied to Equation (
6).
Main Theorem. For a pair of nonnegative integers n and m, we have:where and are the Stirling numbers of the first kind and the second kind, respectively. Proof. For any pair of sequences,
and
, if they are related by
then, they have an inversion formula given by [
26]
We apply this inversion formula to Equation (
6) with
,
. Then, we have:
This completes our proof. ☐
Applying the inversion formula Equation (
8) again to the above identity, we have
If we set
in Equation (
6), we get the original formula, Equation (
1). Moreover, if we set
in Equation (
6) and use the fact
, then we have the following identity (see [
5] (Equation (29))):
where the number
is defined by:
called “barred preferential arrangements of
n elements”, introduced by Pippenger [
5].
is the number of ways of ranking
, with ties allowed, and with a “bar” that may be placed above all the elements of
, between two equivalence classes of tied members, or below all the members. Some relations between
and
were derived in [
5] [Equations (24), (28), and (29)].
4. Combinatorial Approach
In this section, we give a combinatorial approach to prove Proposition 1. First, we connect monomials in to a preferential arrangement.
Proposition 2. For positive integers , the product is a sum of monomials, including monomials of length p for .
Proof. We associate any monomials in the product to a preferential arrangement on as follows. If the factor appears before the factor in a monomial, then it means that . If the factor appears in a monomial, then it means that . For example, the monomial means that the preferential arrangement is .
From the stuffle product rule in Equation (
4) we know that if
u,
v are any possible words,
The corresponding result gives us all situations of Candidate j and Candidate ℓ if we rank j and ℓ: the term means , the term means , and the term means . By mathematical induction, one can assert the following result: The product of produces a sum of monomials, with each monomial corresponding to a possible preferential arrangement in . That is to say, we can regard as ranking the elements where ties are allowed.
Therefore, the product
is a sum of
monomials, including
monomials of length
p for
(see Equation (
1)). ☐
Secondly, we connect a monomial in a stuffle product to a Delannoy path.
Proposition 3. If u, v are monomials in of lengths n and m respectively, then is a sum of monomials.
Proof. We write the monomials
u and
v in
as:
We associate any monomial in the product to a Delannoy path from to as follows. If , then we move from the standing point to the next point by the direction . If , then we move from the standing point to the next point by the direction . If , then we move from the standing point to the next point by the direction . The path begins at the point , then it follows the directions corresponding to , , …, .
From the stuffle product rule in Equation (
4), we know that
This indicates that there are three possible directions beginning from the point to the next point. The first term begins with , i.e., we move to the next point ; the second term begins with , i.e., we move to the next point ; or the third term begins with , i.e., we move to the next point . Since the number of the remaining points are less than , we use the induction hypothesis to conclude the following result.
The product of produces a sum of monomials, where each monomial corresponds to a possible Delannoy path from to . Hence, the number of the monomials is . ☐
Now we give another proof of the Proposition 1. Consider the following product
By Proposition 2 there are monomials in this product. Also, the factor has monomials of length p for , and the factor has monomials of length q for .
By Proposition 3 the product
is a sum of
monomials, where the monomial
u is from the product
with length
p, and the monomial
v is from the product
with length
q. Thus, we have
monomials. By combining these two results, we have the desired identity.