How Naive Is Contentful Moral Perception?
Abstract
:1. The Metaphysics of Perceptual Experience
Phenomenological Characteristic: Perceptual experience, at least paradigmatically, exhibits a certain kind of phenomenal character—there is a ‘what it’s like’ to perceive objects and properties (such as the qualia of the various colors on the cover of my notebook).
Epistemological Characteristic: Perceptual experience, at least paradigmatically, plays an essential role in justifying beliefs about our immediate surroundings (such as justifying my belief that my notebook is on the table).
Behavioral Characteristic: Perceptual experience, at least paradigmatically, plays an essential role in facilitating action (such as reaching out and grabbing my notebook).
1.1. Representationalism
1.2. Naive Realism
Acquaintance: For S to have a perceptual experience e of F, e must provide S with direct awareness of F.
Constitution: For a perceptual experience e to be an experience of F, e must be partly constituted by F.
The reason Putnam’s Proof is intuitively so unsatisfactory is that we ordinarily take experience to provide us with knowledge of far more than merely the functional structure of the medium-sized world. We take ourselves to have knowledge of the categorical objects and properties around us. We ordinarily think we know what the world is like. If the world is that way, it is not a bit like a vat.[11], p. 151.
1.3. Kantian and Berkeleyan Properties
A Kantian Property is a property such that the phenomenal character of veridical experiences of them are mostly determined by features of the subject.[1], p. 214.
A Berkeleyan Property is a property “such that the phenomenal character of veridical experiences of it is mostly determined by the fact that the subject perceives an instance of that property (that is, features of the subject play a relatively minimal role in determining phenomenal character)”.[1], pp. 226–227
2. Contentful Moral Perception and Kantian/Berkeleyan Properties
Contentful Moral Perception (CMP): An agent can represent moral properties as part of the content of her perceptual experience (along with shape, color, pitch, etc.)14.[18]
CMP*: Moral properties, in human agents, are (re)presented as a content/constituent of their perceptual experience (along with shape, color, pitch, etc.).
3. In Favor of Moral Perception as Berkeleyan
3.1. Moral Motivation
Humeanism: “Necessarily, whenever an agent engages in some motivated action, ϕ, the complete explanation of her action must cite one or more of her desires as the ultimate source(s) of motivation to ϕ”.[33].
Anti-Humeanism: Sometimes, when an agent engages in some motivated action, ϕ, the complete explanation of her action will not appeal to any of her desires as the ultimate source(s) of motivation to ϕ.
3.2. Grounding Moral Thought
Experience of the object has to explain how it is that we can grasp demonstratives referring to the object as referring to a categorical object, not merely a collection of potentialities. This means that, given any description of the phenomenal character of experiences of objects, we can ask whether experience, so described, would be capable of explaining our grasp of a demonstrative referring to the thing…Merely having sensations could explain how it is that you have the conception of the object as a hypothesized cause of those sensations…but it could not provide you with knowledge of the categorical thing itself…that is exactly what happens when you rely on your experience of the object to interpret a demonstrative referring to that object.[11], p. 145
3.3. Epistemic Access to Normativity
[I]t seems that veridical experience gives us something that trustworthy, reliable, and quickly delivered testimony doesn’t. I propose that the ‘something more’ is something along the lines of the following: the phenomenal character of veridical experience gives its subject insight into what things in one’s environment are like independently of one’s experiences of them.[1], p. 227
IKf > BPf. For any perceptible property F in experience e, if e provides intrinsic knowledge of F, then F is a BP in e.
3.3.1. Normative Authority
3.3.2. Individuating the Authoritatively Normative
3.3.3. Berkeleyan Perception and the Epistemology of Normative Authority
Normative Authority (NA): Moral properties, or the moral principles that ground their instances, are normatively authoritative in the sense of being intrinsically and objectively deliberation-worthy.
This feeling of obligation appears as independent of preference, as many of the alternatives within our experience do not. Where neither alternative has this character, where our choices are wholly matters of preference or desire, the choice which we face does not appear as a moral choice. However, let either alternative appear not as a preference, but as an “objective” demand, and I feel myself to be confronted by a moral issue, by a categorical imperative, by an injunctive force which issues from one of the alternatives itself.[62], p. 50
Your moral experience is not simply that of being required to do something by objective features of the circumstances you face given a certain set of standards to which you happen to be committed. A crucial part of the phenomenology is the powerful sense that the standards you are employing are themselves imposed upon you independently of your choices or contingent commitments or causal psychological shaping by your society. Not only are the wrong-making features of walking away from the child objective, along with their relation to a given set of standards, but their wrong-makingness itself seems to be objective, which is to say that the associated standards themselves have an objective status. The moral experience is that of being confronted by a moral demand that is backed up by categorically authoritative standards to which you are committed because they objectively merit that commitment—not because you have simply been raised to be so committed or made the choice to be.[63], p. 26
If we start with normative concepts, it seems apt to characterize their normativity in terms of a special mode of presentation in cognition—that of inherent, authoritative guidance. Though there might be more to it than a distinctive phenomenology, the phenomenology seems really important.[64], p. 123
4. Two Worries from Moral Disagreement: Illusions and Cognitive Penetration
5. Taking Stock
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | See https://survey2020.philpeople.org/survey/results/4894, accessed on 22 May 2023. |
2 | This is a simplified statement of Logue’s view—for the details, see Section 1.3. |
3 | |
4 | Strictly speaking, this is a matter of a degree, rather than a hard-and-fast distinction. See Section 1.3. |
5 | And in fact, it isn’t even clear that full-blown representation is incompatible with Berkeleyan Property perception. See Section 1.3, especially footnote 20. |
6 | See Fish (2021 Ch.1) [8]. |
7 | For ease of reading, I’ll leave this qualification about context implicit in the remainder of what follows. |
8 | Fish (2021), Ch.3 [8]. |
9 | Representationalism, or intentionalism, comes in many different forms and strengths, which I will not be delving into here. For details, see Lycan (2019), Section 2 [9]. |
10 | I have in mind here primarily the detailed articulation and development of various forms of disjunctivism. See the variety of perspectives in Byrne & Logue (2009) [12]. |
11 | |
12 | |
13 | One difference between BK-perception and edenic perception is that Chalmers appears to allow for the possibility that edenic perception is representational. While Logue allows for such a view (see Logue 2012, 225–226), she thinks such a view will fail to have the epistemological advantages that a naive realist conception of BK-perception will have. |
14 | Werner (2020), p.6. Bergqvist & Cowan (2018) call this “canonical moral perception” [18]. |
15 | |
16 | |
17 | |
18 | Notice that this is distinct from an argument to the effect that appealing to a background desire would be generally a more complex explanation of action, and so this is not a general argument against Humeanism about belief/desire explanations. This is because the complexity here is not about how many states are involved in any given action explanation, but about the cognitive mechanisms—and their realisticness—in a given subset of action explanations. |
19 | Two anonymous reviewers worry that this kind of story can’t explain why illusory/hallucinatory (purported) perceptions of normative properties would be motivating in the same way, since they by definition do not provide Acquaintance. I return to this important issue in Section 4 since an analogous concern arises with respect to knowledge of normative authority. |
20 | For an overview, see Björnsson et al. (2015) [34]. |
21 | Thanks to an anonymous referee for pressing me on this. |
22 | |
23 | In fact, there might be a positive reason to think that we obviously don’t have Quiddistic Knowledge of moral properties, because if we did, questions about the metaphysics of moral properties would have been settled long ago merely by introspection. If a version of this argument succeeds, it would indirectly tell in favor of moral properties in perception as KPs. I’m not sure that the argument can work, however. After all, those who endorse Quiddistic Knowledge for, say, qualia, do not take their views to be refuted by the fact that there remains a dispute about the metaphysics of qualia. See Majeed (2017) and Liu (2020, forthcoming) for discussion of some of these issues [42,43,44]. |
24 | There may be further conditions on acting rightly or on acting with moral worth, but I know of no account of such things that requires anything resembling Quiddistic Knowledge. |
25 | |
26 | This is not to say that the knowledge needs to be even in principle stateable. Knowledge-which may be ineffable. See Dasgupta (2015) [49]. |
27 | Compare understanding the definition of a word vs. understanding that some particular word is a noun, and so only suited to play certain grammatical roles. |
28 | This is not to say that Kantian perception could not provide any knowledge of second-order properties, or that Kantian perception could not (re)present second-order properties. Rather, there is a certain kind of second-order property that KP cannot provide us, according to IKf > BPf, and that is knowledge of something like the intrinsic nature of some property—a sort of partial Quiddistic Knowledge. Of course, one could deny IKf > BPf, but I am taking it for granted in what follows. I thank an anonymous referee for pressing me to think more carefully about this issue. |
29 | |
30 | Howard & Laskowski (forthcoming), 8. It should be noted that Howard & Laskowski are ultimately skeptical of authoritative normativity [50]. |
31 | See Paakkunainen (2018), Section 6 [54]. |
32 | The Inescapable Game has three rules. 1. Everyone must play the game, and 2. Everyone must harshly criticize anyone who is losing the game, and 3. The only ways to lose the game are (a) to claim that you aren’t playing it or (b) to fail to criticize anyone who is losing the game. I refuse to play the Inescapable Game. But its reasons nonetheless apply to me. Claiming that I don’t care about the game or its rules only results in further obligations that I will be harshly criticized. |
33 | One core source of this thought, though not expressed in these terms, is Parfit (2011), Volume 2, Part Six [55]. |
34 | |
35 | Eklund (2017) is the most detailed exploration of these issues [58]. |
36 | |
37 | It’s worth flagging that similar such questions will plausibly arise with respect to some other metaethical claims, such as the supervenience of the moral on the natural. |
38 | I thank an anonymous referee for pressing me to address the first issue, and a different anonymous referee for pressing me to address the second issue. |
39 | Both terms are used for the same phenomenon. I will use “cognitive permeation” in what follows. |
40 | For discussion, see Soteriou (2020), Section 2.4 [65]. |
41 | |
42 | |
43 | Cavedon-Taylor (2018) has suggested that cognitive permeation supports representationalism generally, but even if the argument does not work at complete generality, it could provide a test for whether a given perception of a property was Kantian [72]. |
44 | One issue here has to do with whether cognitive permeation genuinely is incompatible with the Berkeleyan perception of some property. It’s known, for example, that gray bananas appear more yellow than they in fact are (Macpherson 2012). Suppose I see a banana in a dark room, and it appears somewhat yellow to me. Furthermore, suppose that the banana is in fact yellow, and the cognitive influence is merely correcting for error predictably produced by the darkness of the room. Does this undermine my perception of the yellowness as Berkelyan? It seems initially like the answer is yes; however, my perception of the banana as yellow could be based on prior Berkeleyan perceptions of yellowness in bananas, so the ultimate explanation of my experience is given in terms of the worldly facts and not the subject [67]. |
45 | I think what this brings out is that the distinction between Kantian and Berkeleyan property perception is more complicated than Logue suggests, because it isn’t clear what range of facts count as part of the explanation of the phenomenology in the relevant sense. |
46 |
References
- Logue, H. Why Naive Realism? Proc. Aristot. Soc. 2012, 112 Pt 2, 211–237. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Logue, H. Are Perceptual Experiences Just Representations? In Current Controversies in Philosophy of Perception; Nanay, B., Ed.; Routledge: London, UK, 2016. [Google Scholar]
- Audi, R. Moral Perception; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Cowan, R. Perceptual Intuitionism. Philos. Phenomenol. Res. 2015, 90, 164–193. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Matey, J. The Perception of Virtue. In The Epistemology of Non-Visual Perception; Brogaard, B., Gratzia, D., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, forthcoming.
- McBrayer, J. Moral perception and the causal objection. Ratio 2010, 23, 291–307. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Väyrynen, P. Doubts about Moral Perception. In Evaluative Perception; Bergqvist, A., Cowan, R., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Fish, W. Philosophy of Perception: A Contemporary Introduction; Routledge: London, UK, 2021; Volume 2. [Google Scholar]
- Lycan, W. Representational Theories of Consciousness. In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy; Stanford University: Stanford, CA, USA, 2019; Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/consciousness-representational/ (accessed on 22 May 2023).
- Kennedy, M. Heirs of nothing: The implications of transparency. Philos. Phenomenol. Res. 2009, 79, 574–604. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Campbell, J. Reference and Consciousness; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2002. [Google Scholar]
- Byrne, A.; Logue, H. Disjunctivism: Contemporary Readings; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Hatfield, G. Sense Data. In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy; Stanford University: Stanford, CA, USA, 2021; Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/sense-data/ (accessed on 22 May 2023).
- Russell, B. The Problems of Philosophy; Barnes & Noble: New York, NY, USA, 1912. [Google Scholar]
- Fish, W. Perception, Hallucination, and Illusion; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Langsam, H. The intuitive case for naive realism. Philos. Explor. 2017, 20, 106–122. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Chalmers, D. Perception and the fall from Eden. In Perceptual Experience; Gendler, T.S., Hawthorne, J., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2006. [Google Scholar]
- Bergqvist, A.; Cowan, R. Evaluative Perception: Introduction. In Evaluative Perception; Bergqvist, A., Cowan, R., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Reiland, I. On experiencing moral properties. Synthese 2021, 198, 315–325. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Werner, P.J. Moral Perception. Philos. Compass 2020, 15, e12640. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hamilton, R.P. Virtuous Perception: A Gibsonian Approach. In Virtue, Narrative, and Self: Explorations of Character in Philosophy of Mind and Action; Ulatowski, J., van Zyl, L., Eds.; Routledge: London, UK, 2020. [Google Scholar]
- Van Grunsven, J. Enactivism and the Paradox of Moral Perception. Topoi 2021, 41, 287–298. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wisnewski, J.J. The case for moral perception. Phenomenol. Cogn. Sci. 2015, 14, 129–148. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wisnewski, J. Affordances, Embodiment, and Moral Perception: A Sketch of a Moral Theory. Philos. Contemp. World 2019, 25, 35–48. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Blum, L.A. Moral Perception and Particularity; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 1994. [Google Scholar]
- Cowan, R. Cognitive Penetrability and Ethical Perception. Rev. Philos. Psychol. 2014, 6, 665–682. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Murdoch, I. The Sovereignty of Good; Schocken Books: New York, NY, USA, 1970. [Google Scholar]
- Vance, J.; Werner, P.J. Attentional Moral Perception. J. Moral Philos. 2022, 19, 501–525. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Werner, P.J. Moral Perception and the Contents of Experience. J. Moral Philos. 2016, 13, 294–317. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Werner, P.J. Moral Perception without (Prior) Moral Knowledge. J. Moral Philos. 2018, 15, 164–181. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Harman, G. The Nature of Morality: An Introduction to Ethics; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 1977. [Google Scholar]
- Müller, J.M. Perceptualism and the epistemology of normative reasons. Synthese 2020, 199, 3557–3586. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Swartzer, S. A challenge for Humean externalism. Philos. Stud. 2018, 175, 23–44. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Björnsson, G.; Strandberg, C.; Olinder, R.F.; Eriksson, J. Motivational Internalism: Contemporary Debates. In Motivational Internalism; Björnsson, G., Strandberg, C., Olinder, R.F., Eriksson, J., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Barlassina, L.; Hayward, M.K. More of me! Less of me!: Reflexive Imperativism about Affective Phenomenal Character. Mind 2019, 128, 1013–1044. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Jacobson, H. The Role of Valence in Perception: An ARTistic Treatment. Philos. Rev. 2021, 130, 481–531. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Schaffer, J. Quiddistic Knowledge. Philos. Stud. 2005, 123, 1–32. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Slutsky, D. Causally Inefficacious Moral Properties. South. J. Philos. 2001, 39, 595–610. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sturgeon, N. Moral Explanations. In Ethical Theory 1: The Question of Objectivity; Rachels, J., Ed.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 1985. [Google Scholar]
- Sturgeon, N. Evil and Explanation. Can. J. Philos. 1995, 25, 155–185. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lewis, D. Ramseyan humility. In Conceptual Analysis and Philosophical Naturalism; Braddon-Mitchell, D., Nola, R., Eds.; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Liu, M. Explaining the Intuition of Revelation. J. Conscious. Stud. 2020, 27, 99–107. [Google Scholar]
- Liu, M. Revelation and the Appearance/Reality Distinction. In Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Mind; forthcoming.
- Majeed, R. Ramseyan humility: The response from revelation and panpsychism. Can. J. Philos. 2017, 47, 75–96. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dunaway, B. Reality and Morality; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2020. [Google Scholar]
- Enoch, D. Taking Morality Seriously: A Defense of Robust Realism; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Suikkanen, J. Non-Naturalism and Reference. J. Ethics Soc. Philos. 2017, 11, 1–24. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wedgwood, R. The Nature of Normativity; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2007. [Google Scholar]
- Dasgupta, S. Inexpressible Ignorance. Philos. Rev. 2015, 124, 441–480. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Howard, N.R.; Laskowski, N.G. Robust vs. Formal Normativity II, Or: No Gods, No Masters, No Authoritative Normativity. In The Oxford Handbook of Metaethics; Copp, D., Rosati, C., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, forthcoming.
- McPherson, T. Against quietist normative realism. Philos. Stud. 2011, 154, 223–240. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- McPherson, T. Authoritatively Normative Concepts. In Oxford Studies in Metaethics, Vol 13; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2018. [Google Scholar]
- Wodak, D. Mere formalities: Fictional normativity and normative authority. Can. J. Philos. 2019, 49, 828–850. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Paakkunainen, H. The “Just Too Different” Objection to Normative Naturalism. Philos. Compass 2018, 13, e12473. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Parfit, D. On What Matters: Two-Volume Set; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Luco, A.C. Non-negotiable: Why moral naturalism cannot do away with categorical reasons. Philos. Stud. 2016, 173, 2511–2528. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Shafer-Landau, R. A defence of categorical reasons. Proc. Aristot. Soc. 2009, 109 Pt 2, 189–206. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Eklund, M. Choosing Normative Concepts; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Leary, S. Choosing normative properties: A reply to Eklund’s Choosing Normative Concepts. Inq. Interdiscip. J. Philos. 2020, 63, 455–474. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- McPherson, T. Ardent realism without referential normativity. Inq. Interdiscip. J. Philos. 2020, 63, 489–508. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Werner, P.J. Normative concepts and the return to Eden. Philos. Stud. 2022, 179, 2259–2283. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mandelbaum, M. The Phenomenology of Moral Experience; Johns Hopkins University Press: Baltimore, MD, USA, 1955. [Google Scholar]
- FitzPatrick, W.J. Moral Phenomenology and the Value-Laden World. Ethical Theory Moral Pract. 2021, 25, 21–36. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bedke, M. Choosing Normative Concepts. Philos. Rev. 2019, 128, 121–126. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Soteriou, M. The disjunctive theory of perception. In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy; Stanford University: Stanford, CA, USA, 2020. [Google Scholar]
- McDowell, J. Criteria, defeasibility, and knowledge. Proc. Br. Acad. Lond. 1982, 68, 455–479. [Google Scholar]
- Macpherson, F. Cognitive penetration of colour experience: Rethinking the issue in light of an indirect mechanism. Philos. Phenomenol. Res. 2012, 84, 24–62. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Vetter, P.; Newen, A. Varieties of cognitive penetration in visual perception. Conscious. Cogn. 2014, 27, 62–75. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Newen, A.; Vetter, P. Why cognitive penetration of our perceptual experience is still the most plausible account. Conscious. Cogn. 2017, 47, 26–37. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Werner, P.J. A posteriori ethical intuitionism and the problem of cognitive penetrability. Eur. J. Philos. 2017, 25, 1791–1809. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Elliott, A. Can we see what’s wrong with Non-naturalism. In Oxford Studies in Metaethics Vol. 19; Shafer-Landau, R., Ed.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, forthcoming.
- Cavedon-Taylor, D. Naïve realism and the cognitive penetrability of perception. Anal. Philos. 2018, 59, 391–412. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Samuel, J. Thin as a Needle, Quick as a Flash: Murdoch on Agency and Moral Progress. Rev. Metaphys. 2021, 75, 345–373. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Werner, P.J. Toward a Perceptual Solution to Epistemological Objections to Nonnaturalism. J. Ethics Soc. Philos. 2023, 24, 466–487. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2023 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Werner, P.J. How Naive Is Contentful Moral Perception? Philosophies 2023, 8, 49. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies8030049
Werner PJ. How Naive Is Contentful Moral Perception? Philosophies. 2023; 8(3):49. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies8030049
Chicago/Turabian StyleWerner, Preston J. 2023. "How Naive Is Contentful Moral Perception?" Philosophies 8, no. 3: 49. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies8030049
APA StyleWerner, P. J. (2023). How Naive Is Contentful Moral Perception? Philosophies, 8(3), 49. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies8030049