Next Article in Journal
Sensitive and Selective Ammonia Gas Sensor Based on Molecularly Modified SnO2
Previous Article in Journal
Label-Free Immunodetection in High Ionic Strength Solutions Using Carbon Nanotube Transistors with Nanobody Receptors
 
 
Font Type:
Arial Georgia Verdana
Font Size:
Aa Aa Aa
Line Spacing:
Column Width:
Background:
Abstract

The Social Obligations of the Cued Self in the Age of Advertising †

by
Yogi Hale Hendlin
Department of Medicine, University of California, San Francisco, CA 94143-1390, USA
Presented at the IS4SI 2017 Summit DIGITALISATION FOR A SUSTAINABLE SOCIETY, Gothenburg, Sweden, 12–16 June 2017.
Proceedings 2017, 1(3), 234; https://doi.org/10.3390/IS4SI-2017-03970
Published: 8 June 2017

1. Extended Abstract

The information age presents us with a gambit: present information transparency to level the asymmetries of information, “democratizing” the opportunities for people to act according to more informed, autonomous decisions; or to control and manipulate our inherent human vulnerabilities to further skew power towards increasing asymmetrical positive feedback loops benefitting the few. This paper examines contrasting notions of the self vis-à-vis (un)consciously curated environments as humans increasingly live in advertising-saturated environments [1].
Advertising per se can influence actors towards virtuous action (e.g., neighborhood watch anti-crime campaigns) or towards behaving according to the wills of private interests (e.g., a Christian pathos-infused anti-abortion billboard) [2]. While certainly no advertising will ever be neutral, and one can always question the good or the interests behind such efforts to influence, we can differentiate between public versus private advertising, those without a product to sell intending to sway a population towards profiting a certain business, subculture, or belief system versus those aimed to help a population for their own sake (such as a public service announcement about proper nutrition). Society is never monolith, but should advertising really be the battlefield through which discourse is achieved?
Evolutionarily, we are maladapted to deal with advertising [3]. Until the last century or so, information was power, and the natural environment tended not to deceive us [4,5]. More recently, our desires and emotions have been hijacked through public relations, propaganda, and advertising [6]. Mass media has enabled the conformity of opinion unlike that previously imagined, and in the last decade, the internet has moved from primarily a portal of knowledge and understanding to a dizzying maze of corporate interests and click bait one must navigate in order to actually get or do the thing one turned to it to do in the first place. The moneylenders have captured the akashic records.
The monetization of human consciousness raises interesting epistemological and ethical questions [7]. What we make of the effects of advertising, and more importantly, the decisions we collectively make regarding how we wish to curate our mental environment, are fundamental to our present condition. These determinations rest, in turn on our view of human nature.
The recent work of situationist philosophy emphasizes that the bulk of our actions are cued, rather than based on an unshakable non-socially-contingent self [8,9]. Unlike the myth of the autonomous individual, almost ignoring the distractions society presents, increasingly social psychology and philosophy is acknowledging the inextricably relational composition of the self [10].
Debates currently rage in philosophy between virtue ethics and situationism. Situationism, most provocatively formulated by Kwame Anthony Appiah, states that instead of some inner essence of character determining our behavior in the world, that for the most part, various external stimuli and pressures impinge on us, significantly altering the course of our actions [11]. The same person in different situations, can perform drastically different behaviors, based on the challenges and opportunities they come into the situation with, and are presented with. In one famous experiment, seminarians on their way to an important meeting were observed whether or not they gave money or help to someone in need. Those seminarians running late to the meeting in the experiment almost systematically did not lend help, while those who were early helped the planted subject to a much higher degree [12]. This experiment by design suggests that the same population engages in widely divergent socially-cohesive behaviors depending on the situation they are in—in this case, whether they were late or not to an important meeting.
Pragmatism has since its origins denied the notions of an autochthonous self, instead avering that the self is always socially constituted through and through. G.H. Mead, for example, appraises the communicatively rationalized society as forming the bulwark of how we understand ourselves. Mead writes, “we are what we are, through our relationship with others” [13]. If this interdependency is so strong that it has lead Alasdair MacIntyre to write his book Dependent Rational Animals to characterize both humans and nonhumans as ontologically social [14], then what does it mean when a primary mode of interacting with our environment through advertising becomes instrumental rather than communicative?
By returning to the original Aristotelean meaning of character qua habitus [15], situationism and virtue ethics are much more compatible than otherwise judged. Our habitus, however, emerges from a specific spatiotemporal milieu [16], a habituation to a particular habitat [17]. Take Aristotle’s phronimos out of Athens in the 4th century B.C.E., and that same person may be very maladapted indeed to the strictures of the modern world. Attentive habituation is not a universal quality, but one keenly geared towards the history of situations and stimuli encountered. Thus, reinscribing virtue ethics in the constraints of context highlights the molding of individual to environment and vice-versa [18].
What this suggests, is that advertising robs of knowing and developing certain parts of ourselves, through its calculated intention to use us qua consumers to achieve the ends of some anonymous other profiting entity. Rethinking the ethics of advertising in a world with increasingly ubiquitous modes of manipulating us through automatic means—algorithms, Big Data, predictive purchases, one-click-buy, etc.—benefits from understanding our vulnerable and porous selves, dismantling the claims that we can fortify ourselves against systematically exploitative elements in our environment.

Conflicts of Interest

The author declares no conflict of interest.

References

  1. Tarasti, E. Existential Semiotics; Indiana University Press: Bloomington, IN, USA, 2000. [Google Scholar]
  2. Hastings, G. The Marketing Matrix: How the Corporation Gets Its Power and How We Can Reclaim It; Routledge: New York, NY, USA, 2012. [Google Scholar]
  3. Barrett, D. Supernormal Stimuli: How Primal Urges Overran Their Evolutionary Purpose, 1st ed.; W. W. Norton & Company: New York, NY, USA, 2010. [Google Scholar]
  4. Donald, M. Origins of the Modern Mind: Three Stages in the Evolution of Culture and Cog-Nition; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1991. [Google Scholar]
  5. Guthrie, S.E. Faces in the Clouds: A New Theory of Religion; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 1993. [Google Scholar]
  6. Stiegler, B. Symbolic Misery—Volume 1: The Hyperindustrial Epoch, 1st ed.; Polity: Columbia, MD, USA; London, UK, 2014. [Google Scholar]
  7. Mander, J. Four Arguments for the Elimination of Television, reprint ed.; William Morrow Paperbacks: New York, NY, USA, 1978. [Google Scholar]
  8. Bargh, J.; Chartrand, T. The unbearable automaticity of being. Am. Psychol. 1999, 54, 462–479. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  9. Spaulding, S. Embodied Social Cognition. Philos. Top. 2011, 39, 141–162. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  10. Bryne, R.W. From Parsing Actions to Understanding Intentions. In The Symbolic Species Evolved; Schilhab, T., Stjernfelt, F., Deacon, T.W., Eds.; Springer: Dordrecht, The Netherlands; New York, NY, USA, 2012. [Google Scholar]
  11. Appiah, K.A. Experiments in Ethics; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2010. [Google Scholar]
  12. Latané, B.; Rodin, J. A lady in distress: Inhibiting effects of friends and strangers on bystander intervention. J. Exp. Soc. Psychol. 1969, 5, 189–202. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  13. Mead, G.H. Mind, Self & Society from the Standpoint of a Social Behaviorist; University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 1934. [Google Scholar]
  14. MacIntyre, A. Dependent Rational Animals; Open Court: Chicago, IL, USA, 1999. [Google Scholar]
  15. Aristotle. Politics; Penguin Classics; Harmondsworth: London, UK, 1962. [Google Scholar]
  16. Bourdieu, P. The Logic of Practice; Stanford University Press: Stanford, CA, USA, 1990. [Google Scholar]
  17. Escobar, A. Territories of Difference: Place, Movements, Life, Redes; Duke University Press: Durham, NC, USA, 2008. [Google Scholar]
  18. Wright, R. A Short History of Progress; Carroll & Graf Publishers: New York, NY, USA, 2005. [Google Scholar]

Share and Cite

MDPI and ACS Style

Hendlin, Y.H. The Social Obligations of the Cued Self in the Age of Advertising. Proceedings 2017, 1, 234. https://doi.org/10.3390/IS4SI-2017-03970

AMA Style

Hendlin YH. The Social Obligations of the Cued Self in the Age of Advertising. Proceedings. 2017; 1(3):234. https://doi.org/10.3390/IS4SI-2017-03970

Chicago/Turabian Style

Hendlin, Yogi Hale. 2017. "The Social Obligations of the Cued Self in the Age of Advertising" Proceedings 1, no. 3: 234. https://doi.org/10.3390/IS4SI-2017-03970

Article Metrics

Back to TopTop