1. Introduction
The idea that classical information can be encoded on a holographic screen originated in black-hole (BH) physics [
1,
2] and it remains of interest primarily in the context of quantum gravity [
3,
4]. The idea that quantum systems can be restricted to interacting via a classical information channel arises in the theories of measurement [
5,
6] and decoherence [
6,
7]. An information channel and, hence, any communication employing such a channel, is classical if and only if the exchanged information is fully fungible, i.e., encodable in a finite bit string [
8]. Classical channels are relevant whenever classical communication is included within a broader operational protocol, e.g., in a local operations, classical communication (LOCC) protocol [
9]. Studies of parallel quantum and classical communication, however, involve multipartite decompositions, e.g., into agents Alice and Bob, a shared quantum system, a shared classical channel, shared, non-fungible reference frames, and a shared environment that provides free energy and absorbs waste heat. Hence, they require explicit consideration of a large number of distinct physical interactions [
10,
11]. Therefore, in what follows, we restrict our attention to simple, bipartite decompositions in which two quantum systems
A and
B interact exclusively with each other via a single, shared, classical information channel.
Here, we study, in this simple bipartite setting, the relationship between the seemingly-disparate ideas of holographic screens and classical information channels, and show that they are, in fact, equivalent: holographic screens are classical information channels and vice-versa. Any physical situation involving classical communication can, in particular, be reformulated as a situation in which the communicating entities are separated by, and encode information on, a holographic screen. If the classical information channel is considered ancillary to the physics of the communicating systems, as in practice it generally is, then the equivalent holographic screen is also ancillary, i.e., the interaction does not depend on its spatial coordinates. Hence, our result effectively generalizes the holographic principle (HP) from a principle stated in spacetime [
1,
2,
3,
4] to a principle stated independently of spacetime (see [
12] for further details). However, situations in which systems occupying distinct regions of spacetime that are separated by a holographic screen, e.g., the interior and exterior of a BH, can be similarly reformulated as situations in which their physical interaction is confined to a classical information channel.
Let
U be an isolated, finite quantum system (i.e. the Hilbert space
has finite dimension
d) and
be a bipartite decomposition that satisfies the separability condition
at least up to some recoherence time that is long with respect to other times of interest. Classical communication between
A and
B clearly requires such separability; if
is an entangled state,
A and
B by definition cannot exchange classical, i.e., fungible information. Moreover, the separability of
is, in this situation, also sufficient to restrict
A and
B to classical communication. The overall Hamiltonian can be written as
, where the last term fully specifies the
interaction. This interaction is, because
d is finite, fully specified by a finite set of real, finite-resolution eigenvalues and, hence, by a finite bit string. Therefore, we can regard
A and
B as exchanging finite bit strings via an ancillary channel, i.e., a channel with degrees of freedom on which
does not depend. It is natural, in this case, to regard
A as “observing”
B and vice-versa. Zurek has termed the encoding of such bit strings by an “observing” environment “einselection” [
7,
13]. The locus of einselection is the locus of interaction, i.e., the nominal
boundary at which
is defined. We show below that the exchanged bits can in this case be regarded as written on, and read from, an intervening, ancillary holographic screen located at this boundary.
We begin by reviewing the implementation of classical communication by
, and show that any classical channel can be implemented by an ancillary qubit array. We assume the HP in its covariant form [
3] as a fundamental principle of physics, and use it to relate the width in bits of either timelike and lightlike classical channels to areas on which the transmitted information is encoded; these areas are ancillary if the channels are ancillary. We then state and prove our main result relating bipartite separability, classical communication, and holographic encoding. This allows for us to reformulate the holographic principle without reference to an embedding in spacetime, as the principle that holographic screens encode interaction eigenvalues. We briefly discuss three implications of this equivalence: (i) channel serialization induces decoherence; (ii) net mass-energy flows between
A and
B can either increase or decrease channel width; and, (iii) the channel width decreases as
for systems embedded in a surrounding environment in which they have a non-ancillary spacelike separation
r.
2. Implementation of Classical Communication by
The associativity of the Hilbert-space tensor product ⊗ (equivalently, the additivity of the Hamiltonian) renders bipartite decompositions completely general: given any bipartite decomposition
, the interaction
is independent of further decompositions of
A or
B. Any physical situation involving many interacting components
can, therefore, without a loss of generality be described as a set of bipartite interactions between single systems
and their complements
. In order to characterize any such interaction as classical communication, we require separability, as discussed above:
. With this assumption and finite
d, we can assume
has
n eigenvalues, each of which can be represented with
m bits, such that
,
d the dimension of
, as above. The interaction
can then be fully specified with
N bits. Following [
10,
11,
12], we choose a basis in which:
where
or
B, the
are Hermitian operators with eigenvalues in
, the
are such that
,
is Boltzmann’s constant,
is
k’s temperature, and
ln 2 is an inverse measure of
k’s thermodynamic efficiency that depends on the internal dynamics
. The
are traditionally regarded as (binary) “measurement” operators that can be considered “questions to nature” with one-bit answers [
14]; this interpretation depends critically on the separability of
, without which the concepts of “question” and “answer” and, hence, of “measurement” are meaningless [
15]. In this separable setting in which interaction can be considered classical communication, it is natural to think of
as measuring the computational resources required for
k to process one-bit [
11].
Communication between
A and
B being classical implies that exchanged bits are irreversibly sent and received; hence, each bit incurs a thermodynamic cost of
[
16]. If transferring
N bits requires time
, the action is:
where
. Here,
and the channel is both symmetric and parallel in units of
. The thermodynamic entropy of
A as measured by
B is, therefore,
N bits, as is the thermodynamic entropy of
B as measured by
A. However, note that
A cannot measure the entanglement entropy of
B, as
A has no observational access to
. As
is separable, the entanglement entropy of the decomposition
is, by definition, zero.
The communication channel defined by (
1) and (
2) is ideal by definition: no energy is lost, and no third system exists to contribute noise [
11]. The channel has no degrees of freedom on which
depends, and, in particular, no spatial degrees of freedom on which
depends; hence, it is entirely ancillary. As a concrete implementation of an ideal, ancillary classical information channel with fixed bandwidth, consider an array of
N mutually-non-interacting qubits, as shown in
Figure 1. Here, the operators
each implement
z-spin operators
either as preparation or measurement; we assume equal efficiencies and equivalent
z-spin reference frames for
A and
B a priori [
10]. We can view each qubit in the array as sequentially prepared by
A and then measured by
B during a time step of duration
, and then prepared by
B and measured by
A during the next time step of duration
. This alternating interaction is effectively bipartite; letting
C be the channel,
A effectively prepares
, and then
B effectively measures
. This entanglement swap induces decoherence [
17], as discussed in
Section 5.1 below, confirming that any such channel is classical.
It is natural to interpret the qubit array in
Figure 1 as an input/output register via which two quantum computers,
A and
B, communicate. Because
A and
B interact by preparing and then measuring, using equivalent reference frames, the states of the qubits in the register, their interaction is classical.
3. Timelike and Lightlike Communication Channels
The Hamiltonian (
1) describes an interaction between spin-like degrees of freedom, with no dependence on the spatial degrees of freedom. However, any realistic classical channel must be physically implemented [
18], e.g., by photons. The HP specifies a minimal area, i.e., a minimal set of spatial degrees of freedom, for any such physically-implemented channel; an
N-qubit array such, as shown in
Figure 1, requires a minimal area of
,
the Planck length [
3,
4]. These spatial degrees of freedom remain strictly ancillary to (
1); they are, however, effectively incorporated into the sending system by the receiving system as above. Hence, they induce decoherence.
Let us first consider an ideal, unidirectional, purely-timelike channel, corresponding to an ideal classical memory that
B writes
N-bit strings on at
t and
A reads
N-bit strings from at some
,
. As
A and
B, in this case, only have timelike separation, it is natural to interpret them as alternating "snapshots" of a single system writing on and reading from its ideal, internal, classical memory. Special relativity restricts the information written on the memory at
t to the past light cone of the memory. The HP in its covariant form [
3],
with
the classical, thermodynamic entropy of any light-sheet
of the (spacelike) boundary
of the channel
C and
the area of the boundary in Planck units, relates the quantity of this writable classical information to the area of the memory written on. Consistent with the discussion above, the classical information holographically encoded on
tells an external observer nothing about the entanglement entropy of the system contained within
; the relationship between these two entropies remains an open question [
19,
20]. Indeed, in this covariant formulation of the HP, it is not even necessary that
be closed [
3]. As shown in
Figure 2a, when only considering the upward arrows, the same holographic considerations apply to the process of reading from the memory: the obtained information can only flow into the forward light cone of the memory.
A and
B both experience causality when interacting with this channel; for both systems, information flows from the past and into the future.
The downward arrows presented in
Figure 2a show
A writing on the memory and
B reading from it. When considering both sets of arrows, the interaction and, hence, the channel is bidirectional. Provided that reading and writing alternate, as in
Figure 1, both systems still experience causality; information flows unidirectionally from past to future when
B writes and
A reads, and also flows unidirectionally, with the sign of
t reversed to capture the alternating action, from past to future when
A writes and
B reads. Thus, alternating reads from and writes to the memory renders reversibility of the dynamics consistent with irreversible encoding of the received bits.
Figure 2b shows a lightlike communication channel. This channel is equivalent to that in
Figure 2a, except the two ends, and, hence, the sending and receiving systems, are separated in space. Here, the natural interpretation is the usual one of spatially-separated observers communicating via an ancillary classical channel. Any such communication channel can, thus, also be considered to be a classical memory; the only difference between timelike and lightlike channels lies in where, in an ancillary space, relative to the writing location, the memory is read. The data encoded by the memory are insufficient for determining this spatial relationship, which, as before, is ancillary to
; therefore, neither a writer on or a reader of the memory can distinguish a timelike from a lightlike channel. We consider in
Section 5.3 below the situation in which
A and
B are embedded in a non-ancillary space, and show that in this case, the channel width decreases with their non-ancillary spacelike separation
r.
The width of the channel in time can be decreased to a minimum of
. In this case, the channel can be considered to have the structure of
Figure 1, with each qubit confined to a minimal voxel with volume
.
4. Holographic Screens Encode Interaction Eigenvalues
The considerations above can be summarized by the following:
Theorem 1.
Let be a bipartite decomposition of a finite quantum system U into components A and B. The following statements are equivalent:
- A:
The state is separable: .
- B:
The systems A and B communicate via an ideal, ancillary classical information channel with finite capacity.
- C:
The eigenvalues of the interaction are written on a finite, ancillary holographic screen at the boundary.
Proof. - A → B:
([11] Theorem 1) If
A and
B are separable, the interaction
can be written in the form (
1), with the
N Hermitian operators
,
or
B, having binary eigenvalues. The
interaction at any time
t is, in this case, completely specified by an
N-bit string. Hence, nothing is lost by replacing the interaction with an exchange of
N-bit strings, i.e., with finite-bandwidth classical communication. There are no intervening systems to introduce noise and energy is perfectly conserved; hence the channel is ideal and can be considered to be ancillary.
- B → C:
A classical information channel can be timelike or lightlike. The information encoded into the channel by
A (
B) must be within the past lightcone of
A’s (
B’s) end of the channel, while the information that is received from the channel by
A (
B) can only flow into the future lightcone of
A’s (
B’s) end of the channel. These past and future light cones are light-sheets of the two ends of the channel, and define equal areas
of the boundaries
and
of the two channel ends by (
3). These boundaries are by definition holographic screens for
A and
B, respectively. As the only information exchanged through the channel consists of encodings of eigenvalues of
, this is the only information on the relevant light-sheets and the only information encoded on the boundaries. The boundaries have no degrees of freedom on which
depends; hence, they are ancillary.
- C → B:
The eigenvalues of have a finite binary encoding, hence the intervening screen has finite area. As it encodes classical information that is accessible to both A and B, it is a classical channel between A and B.
- B → A:
In order for A and B to exchange finite classical information specifying their states, their states must be well-defined. As , must be separable as .
☐
This equivalence allows us to generalize the HP to the claim that if
A and
B are components of a finite separable system
, they can be regarded as separated by an ancillary holographic screen that classically encodes the eigenvalues of their interaction
at a density no greater than one-bit per
. This formulation assumes no embedding of
A or
B into spacetime, so can be regarded as a purely quantum principle that effectively defines the spatial area of the screen in terms of the information it encodes (cf. [
12]).
The independence of Theorem 1 from spacetime and, therefore, from geometric considerations is of particular relevance in BH physics. It is standardly assumed that unitarity requires entanglement between a BH and its Hawking radiation and, in consequence, entanglement between early and late Hawking radiation [
21,
22,
23]. If this is the case, the BH and its Hawking radiation constitute, at all times, a single system
B in an entangled state
. For this state
to be observable from the BH exterior
A, it must be separable from the state
of the exterior, i.e., the joint state
must be separable as
and, hence, have identically zero entanglement entropy. In this case, Theorem 1 applies, the horizon separating
B from
A becomes a holographic screen that classically encodes the eigenvalues of
, and the HP stipulates that this holographic screen must have area
,
N the total number of bits required to classically encode the eigenvalues of
. However, this holographic screen is not simply connected when observed from
A, as a component of the holographic screen surrounds each "particle" (e.g. photon) of Hawking radiation and encodes the eigenvalues of its local interaction with
A. This is precisely the situation envisaged in Susskind’s “octopus” model of Hawking radiation, each component of which is connected by an Einstein-Rosen bridge to the parent BH [
24].
6. Conclusions
Here we have shown that, given a bipartite decomposition of a finite-dimensional quantum system U that satisfies the separability condition , the interaction can be described as noise-free classical communication via an ancillary information channel, which itself can be represented as a holographic screen with area , N the number of bits required to encode the eigenvalues of . This result generalizes the HP to a purely quantum principle that is independent of spacetime embedding and, hence, of geometry.
We have shown elsewhere that the HP in this generalized form implies gauge invariance [
12]; hence, we expect that a generalization of the usual AdS/CFT duality [
28] will be possible. Currently, we are investigating the question of how the entanglement entropy within a BH relates to the thermodynamic entropy of the horizon [
29]. We defer to future work a full analysis of the BH information paradox [
22,
23], which requires at least a tripartite decomposition (Alice, the BH, and everything else) for its formulation.