Next Article in Journal
Projective Geometry as a Model for Hegel’s Logic
Previous Article in Journal
Graph Algebras and Derived Graph Operations
 
 
Font Type:
Arial Georgia Verdana
Font Size:
Aa Aa Aa
Line Spacing:
Column Width:
Background:
Article

On Line Diagrams Plus Modality

by
J.-Martín Castro-Manzano
Faculty of Philosophy, UPAEP University, Puebla 72410, Mexico
Logics 2024, 2(1), 1-10; https://doi.org/10.3390/logics2010001
Submission received: 22 July 2023 / Revised: 17 September 2023 / Accepted: 24 October 2023 / Published: 20 December 2023

Abstract

:
In this paper, we produce an extension of Englebretsen’s line diagrams in order to represent modal syllogistic, i.e., we add some diagrammatic objects and rules to his system in order to reason about modal syllogistics in a diagrammatic, linear fashion.

1. Introduction

If we assume, albeit provisionally, that reasoning is a process that permits the production of some information (i.e., a conclusion) given prior information (i.e., a set of premises)—following certain rules, of course—and that said information can be represented through diagrams, it can be said that diagrammatic inference is the relation that defines our general intuitions about the informal notion of visual inference, and so classical structural norms such as reflexivity, monotonicity, and cut should follow ex hypothesi [1]. With this assumption in mind, we could say a logical diagram—a deductive logical diagram, we should add—is a diagram within a system of diagrams that is sound and complete with respect to a class of valid inferences given a deductive base [2].
Granted this notion of a logical diagram, in this paper, we offer a simple extension of Englebretsen’s logical diagrams in order to represent modal syllogistic, i.e., we add some diagrammatic objects and rules to his system in order to reason about modal syllogistic in a diagrammatic, linear fashion. To reach this goal, we briefly explain some core features of (assertoric and modal) syllogistic and Englebretsen’s diagrammatic system, and then we develop our proposal.

2. Preliminaries

2.1. Assertoric Syllogistic

Assertoric syllogistic ( SYLL ), the system at the core of traditional, Aristotelian logic, is a logic that makes use of categorical statements. A categorical statement is a statement composed of two terms, a quantity, and a quality. The subject and the predicate are called terms: the term-schema S stands for the subject term and the term-schema P stands for the predicate. The quantity may be either universal (All) or particular (Some), and the quality may be either affirmative (is) or negative (is not). Thus, formally, we say a categorical statement is a statement of the form:
Q u a n t i t y S Q u a l i t y P
where Q u a n t i t y { A l l , S o m e } , Q u a l i t y { i s , i s n o t } , and S and P are term-schemes.
The combination of these components produce the four categorical statements: the universal affirmative, “All S is P ,” represented by the label a and thus shortened as SaP ; the universal negative, “All S is not P ” ( SeP ); the particular affirmative, “Some S is P ” ( SiP ); and the particular negative, “Some S is not P ” ( SoP ).
Three categorical statements define a mood, that is, a sequence of categorical statements ordered in such a way that the first two are regarded as premises (major and minor, in that order) and the last one as a conclusion. A categorical syllogism, then, is a mood with three terms one of which appears in both premises but not in the conclusion (known as the middle term and usually represented with the term-schema M ), and two other terms that appear exactly once in each premise and together in the conclusion. The middle term works as a link between these remaining terms and, according to its position, four figures or arrangements can be set up in order to encode the valid syllogistic moods (Table 1) (for the sake of brevity, but without loss of generality, we omit the syllogisms that require existential import).

2.2. Modal Syllogistic

Modal syllogistic ( SYLL μ ), a system around the core of traditional, Aristotelian logic, is a logic that results from the addition of the modal operators of necessity (□) and possibility (⋄), and their respective rules (again, for the sake of brevity, we do not need to show these rules in this moment, but we will refer to them in the proof below), to assertoric syllogistic. Since its proposal in Pr. An. I, 3, 8–22, it has received lots of attention, and even when this attention has not been always favorable [3,4,5,6,7,8], recent studies have recovered some of its features [9,10,11,12].
Given the addition of these operators, in modal syllogistic, we obtain three kinds of statements: categorical statements simpliciter, de re modal statements of the form
Q u a n t i t y S Q u a l i t y M o d a l i t y P
and de dicto modal statements of the form
M o d a l i t y ( Q u a n t i t y S Q u a l i t y P )
where M o d a l i t y { , } , and the rest of components are defined as above.
With these statements, and in the interest of time, consider, as a representative example, the following de re (Table 2) and de dicto (Table 3) valid syllogistic moods.

2.3. Englebretsen’s Line Diagrams

Englebretsen [13,14] has developed a quite powerful system of line diagrams, let us call it ENGL , with which we can reason about syllogisms (in all fairness, it must be mentioned that ENGL can be used not just to reason about syllogistic, but also about singular, relational, and compound statements —Leibniz’s desideratum—; however, for our current purposes, this presentation is enough). The signature for this system requires (labeled) solid lines and (labeled) dots (Figure 1).
In order to reason about syllogisms, ENGL provides a basic syntax for the categorical statements: straight lines stand for terms while the relations between the lines stand for the relations between terms, as in Figure 2.
With the help of these basic diagrams, we can develop syllogistic inferences quite simply and elegantly through a visual representation of the dictum de omni et nullo principle ( DON for short). This principle states a relation between terms such that everything that is affirmed (or denied) of the whole can be affirmed (or denied) of the parts. Visually, we can accommodate this principle by erasing the middle term, M , in the following diagrams, so that the conclusion gets drawn by drawing down the premises (Figure 3).

3. On Line Diagrams Plus Modality

Taking ENGL as a basic system, we will add two kinds of objects (the square-ish and the diamond-ish diagrams) and some rules in order to produce ENGL μ , an extension of Englebretsen’s line diagrams, in order to represent modal syllogistic, SYLL μ . Our intuition can be better appreciated with the aid of the following diagram, where the solid lines represent the preliminaries, and the dashed lines represent our goals:
Logics 02 00001 i007

3.1. Syntax and Rules

So, first, the syntax for this new system is given by (labeled) solid lines, (labeled) dots (an in ENGL ), and by the addition of the square-ish and diamond-ish diagrams. In order to observe these new objects (namely, the square-ish and diamond-ish diagrams), consider the rules for the system (Figure 4, Figure 5 and Figure 6). So, in Figure 4, we observe the de re rules, from left to right: the elimination of a de re square, and the introduction of a de re diamond. In Figure 5, we have the de dicto rules, the elimination of a de dicto square, and the introduction of a de dicto diamond. Finally, in Figure 6 we have some jointing rules, the joint de dicto rule, and the joint de dicto/de re rule. But some clarifications may be in order here. First, in Figure 4, Figure 5 and Figure 6, we use a line between the diagrams of ENGL μ only as a device to explain how the initial diagram results in a new diagram after applying the rule. Second, it can be claimed that the square and the diamond are just syntactical marks, not diagrams, when used in the de re sense, and that the de dicto squares and diamonds are not really squares or diamonds. These are fair observations: it is true that when used in the de re sense, the square and the diamond can be seen just as syntactical marks, and it is also true that the de dicto squares and diamonds are not really squares or diamonds; that is why we call them square-ish and diamond-ish diagrams, and we have worked with them in such fashion out of convenience.
As should be expected, the idea is that a diagram follows validly from some other diagram if and only if it follows from an application of DON (as in ENGL ) or the previous rules, which we can summarily deploy like this:
  • Elimination of a de re square: S P SP .
  • Introduction of a de re diamond: SP S P .
  • Elimination of a de dicto square: SP SP .
  • Introduction of a de dicto diamond: SP SP .
  • Joint de dicto square: de dicto de   dicto de dicto de dicto .
  • Joint de dicto/de re: 〈de dicto〉 de   dicto / de   re ⊢〈de dicto〉.
And now, in order to show how these diagrams and rules work, let us consider some examples.

3.2. Examples

Example 1.
First, let us consider a valid de re syllogism and its corresponding diagram.
Logics 02 00001 i001In this example, the first diagram represents the arrangement of the premises. The second diagram is the result of applying an elimination of a de re square to the middle term M , and finally, the last diagram is the result of applying DON to the previous diagram, thus erasing the middle term M , and hence obtaining the diagram of the conclusion.
Example 2.
Now, let us consider a valid de dicto syllogism.
Logics 02 00001 i002In this example, the first diagram represents the arrangement of the premises. The second diagram is the result of applying a joint de dicto rule to the first diagram, and finally, the last diagram is the result of applying DON to the previous diagram, thus erasing the middle term M , and hence obtaining the diagram of the conclusion.
Example 3.
Now consider a valid syllogism that combines de dicto and de re modalities.
Logics 02 00001 i003This sequence is a little bit longer. Again, the first diagram represents the premises. The second diagram is the result of applying an elimination of a de dicto square. The third line is the result of using an elimination of a de re square to the middle term M . The fourth diagram is the result of applying DON to the previous diagram, thus erasing the middle term M . The fifth line is an elimination of a de re square to the extreme term P . The sixth line is an introduction of a de re diamond to the extreme term P . And last, the final line is an introduction of a de dicto diamond, thus obtaining the diagram of the conclusion.
Example 4.
Another valid, combined syllogism.
Logics 02 00001 i004Once again, the first diagram represents the premises. The second diagram is the result of applying a joint de dicto/de re. The third line results from using an elimination of a de re square to the middle term M . The fourth diagram is the result of applying DON to the previous diagram. The fifth line is an elimination of a de re square to the extreme term P . The final line is an introduction of a de re diamond to the extreme term P .
Example 5.
Finally, let us consider a valid, relational, de dicto and de re syllogism (in plain English, this syllogism could say, for example, that since (1) all brides love some groom, and (2) necessarilly every groom is wonderful, it follows that all brides possibly love some possibly wonderful people).
Logics 02 00001 i005As expected, the first diagram represents the premises. The second diagram is the result of applying an elimination of a de dicto square. The third line is the result of applying DON to the previous diagram. The fourth line is an introduction of a de re diamond to the extreme term W . Finally, the final line is an introduction of a de dicto diamond.

3.3. A Formal Result

Up to this point, we have seen that ENGL can be extended so as to obtain ENGL μ . Now, we would like to offer some evidence to the effect that SYLL μ can be modeled by ENGL μ . So, consider the next:
Proposition 1.
A syllogism is valid in SYLL μ iff its diagram is valid in ENGL μ .
Proof. 
From left to right, we proceed by construction. So, suppose S is an arbitrary syllogism that is valid in SYLL μ ; then, we have to show that its corresponding diagram in ENGL μ follows from DON or an application of rules 1 to 6. Now, if S is valid in SYLL μ , then, according to [9], (a) the middle term of S is distributed (i.e., it is universal or negative) in at least one premise, (b) every term distributed in the conclusion of S is distributed in the premises of S , (c) the number of particular (resp. negative) premises of S is equal to the number of particular (resp. negative) conclusions of S , (d) the conclusion of S is not stronger than any premise of S (according to [9], there is a transitivity or “strength” of modal operators in such a way that T implies T , T implies T , T implies T , and T implies T . So, a first statement (or term) is stronger than a second statement (or term) if and only if the first implies the second but not the other way around. The intuition is that a necessary condition for the validity of any inference is that the conclusion cannot exceed any premise in strength: the scholastics called this the peiorem rule, namely, peiorem semper sequiter conclusio partem), and (e) the number of de dicto⋄ premises of S is not greater than the number of de dicto⋄ conclusions of S .
Given conditions (a) to (d), S must be of one of the following de re forms (Table 4):
Now, let us model these syllogisms in ENGL μ in order to obtain their respective diagrams (Figure 7).
Notice that if conditions (a), (b), and (c) hold, the diagram of S in ENGL μ , D , looks exactly like the diagram of a valid syllogism in ENGL . Additionally, if condition (d) holds, then the order of the new de re rules also holds. Indeed, if condition (d) is met, then D follows from ordered applications of rules 1, 2, 3, and 4. Condition (e) is trivial in this case because there are zero de dicto⋄ statements.
And that does it for the de re syllogisms; now, given conditions (a) to (e), S must be of one of the following de dicto forms (Table 5):
Likewise, let us model these syllogisms in ENGL μ in order to obtain their respective diagrams (Figure 8).
Observe, then, that if conditions (a), (b), and (c) hold, the diagram of S in ENGL μ , D , looks exactly like the diagram of a valid syllogism in ENGL . If condition (d) holds, then D follows from ordered applications of rules 1, 2, 3, and 4. And if condition (e) is met, then the number of a de dicto⋄ diagrams of D is not greater than the number of de dicto⋄ conclusions.
Finally, if S is a combination of valid de dicto and de re forms, then S can be reduced to a de dicto form, since de re syllogisms can be reduced to assertoric syllogisms by collapsing the modal de re terms into simple, assertoric terms.
From right to left, we proceed by reductio. Thus, suppose an arbitrary diagram D is valid in ENGL μ but its corresponding syllogism S is invalid in SYLL μ . If S is invalid in SYLL μ , then S does not comply with at least one of the conditions (a) to (e). Now, if D is valid in ENGL μ , it complies with DON or the modal rules 1 to 6. If D complies with DON , then conditions (a) to (c) of SYLL μ must hold for S . Indeed, if D complies with DON , then the diagram of the middle term M is between the diagrams of S and P , which implies that M is distributed (which is condition (a)); the diagram of S and P is in the required position of the conclusion, so that every term distributed in the conclusion of S is distributed in the premises of S (which is condition (b)), and the number of intersections (resp. negated terms) in the diagram of the premises is equal to the number of intersections (resp. negated terms) in the diagram of the conclusion (which is condition (c)). And now, if rules 1 to 4 hold for D , then S must follow the order of strength of the modal operators, so that the conclusion of S is not stronger than any premise of S (which is condition (d)); finally, if D follows from rules 5 or 6, then the number of de dicto⋄ premises of S is not greater than the number of de dicto⋄ conclusions of S (which is condition (e)). But then, if D complies with DON or rules 1 to 6, S follows conditions (a) to (e), and then S is valid in SYLL μ , which contradicts our initial assumption. □

4. Final Remarks

In this paper, we have offered a simple extension of Englebretsen’s line diagrams in order to represent modal syllogistics. We can wrap this up with the help of the next diagram:
Logics 02 00001 i006
This exercise, though humble, shows the power of Englebretsen’s diagrams in the sense that they are so basic that they allow us to add different objects and rules in order to increase both their deductive and expressive powers (cf. [15]), and opens a non-zero-sum discussion between systems that represent modal logic using diagrams, for instance, between Peircean existential graphs and Englebretsen diagrams in terms of their logical parsimony in the sense that whatever the results of such a discussion, we will all win. Let us win!

Funding

This research was funded by an UPAEP University grant w./no.

Data Availability Statement

No new data were created or analyzed in this study. Data sharing is not applicable to this article.

Acknowledgments

We would like to thank George Englebretsen for so many valuable lessons on logic and diagrams. And also, we would like to thank María Fraile-Galaz for drawing down the diagrams for ENGL μ .

Conflicts of Interest

The author declares no conflicts of interest.

Abbreviations

The following abbreviations are used in this manuscript:
ENGL Englebretsen’s line diagrams
ENGL μ Englebretsen’s line diagrams plus modality
DON Dictum de omni et nullo
Pr. An.Aristotle’s Prior Analytics
SYLL Assertoric syllogistic
SYLL μ Modal syllogistic

References

  1. Castro-Manzano, J.M. Remarks on the Idea of Non-monotonic (Diagrammatic) Inference. Rev. Filos. Open Insight 2017, 8, 243–263. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  2. Castro-Manzano, J.M. When Do We Say That a Diagram is a Logic Diagram? A Comparative Study. Cogency J. Reason. Argum. 2021, 13, 71–103. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  3. Becker, A. Die Aristotelische Theorie der Möglichkeitsschlüsse; Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft: Berlin, Germany, 1968. [Google Scholar]
  4. Bocheński, J. Formale Logik; Karl Alber: München, Germany, 1962. [Google Scholar]
  5. Łukasiewicz, J. Aristotle’s Syllogistic from the Standpoint of Modern Formal Logic; Clarendon Press: Oxford, UK, 1957. [Google Scholar]
  6. Kneale, W.; William Kneale, M.; Kneale, W.; Kneale, M.; Conte, A.; Press, O.U. The Development of Logic; Clarendon Press: Oxford, UK, 1962. [Google Scholar]
  7. Hintikka, J.; Hintikka, K. Time & Necessity: Studies in Aristotle’s Theory of Modality; Clarendon Press: Oxford, UK, 1973. [Google Scholar]
  8. Striker, G. Assertoric vs. Modal Syllogistic. Anc. Philos. 1994, 14, 39–51. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  9. Englebretsen, G. Preliminary notes on a new modal syllogistic. Notre Dame J. Form. Log. 1988, 29, 381–395. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  10. Rini, A.A. Is There a Modal Syllogistic? Notre Dame J. Form. Log. 1998, 39, 554–572. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  11. Thom, P. The Logic of Essentialism: An Interpretation of Aristotle’s Modal Syllogistic; The New Synthese Historical Library: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 2012. [Google Scholar]
  12. Malink, M. Aristotle’s Modal Syllogistic; Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2013. [Google Scholar]
  13. Englebretsen, G. Linear diagrams for syllogisms (with relationals). Notre Dame J. Form. Log. 1991, 33, 37–69. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  14. Englebretsen, G. Something to Reckon with: The Logic of Terms; Canadian Electronic Library: Books Collection; University of Ottawa Press: Ottawa, ON, Canada, 1996. [Google Scholar]
  15. Englebretsen, G.; Castro-Manzano, J.M.; Pacheco-Montes, J.R. Figuring It Out: Logic Diagrams; Philosophical Analysis; De Gruyter: Berlin, Germany, 2019. [Google Scholar]
Figure 1. Signature of ENGL .
Figure 1. Signature of ENGL .
Logics 02 00001 g001
Figure 2. Categorical statements. Clockwise: SaP , SeP , SoP , SiP .
Figure 2. Categorical statements. Clockwise: SaP , SeP , SoP , SiP .
Logics 02 00001 g002
Figure 3. Syllogisms of the first figure. Clockwise: MaPSaM SaP , MePSaM SeP , MePSiM SoP , MaPSiM SiP .
Figure 3. Syllogisms of the first figure. Clockwise: MaPSaM SaP , MePSaM SeP , MePSiM SoP , MaPSiM SiP .
Logics 02 00001 g003
Figure 4. De re rules. Elimination of a de re square, and introduction of a de re diamond.
Figure 4. De re rules. Elimination of a de re square, and introduction of a de re diamond.
Logics 02 00001 g004
Figure 5. De dicto rules. Elimination of a de dicto square, and introduction of a de dicto diamond.
Figure 5. De dicto rules. Elimination of a de dicto square, and introduction of a de dicto diamond.
Logics 02 00001 g005
Figure 6. Jointing rules. Joint de dicto square, and joint de dicto/de re.
Figure 6. Jointing rules. Joint de dicto square, and joint de dicto/de re.
Logics 02 00001 g006
Figure 7. Valid de re syllogisms in ENGL μ .
Figure 7. Valid de re syllogisms in ENGL μ .
Logics 02 00001 g007
Figure 8. De dicto syllogisms.
Figure 8. De dicto syllogisms.
Logics 02 00001 g008
Table 1. Valid syllogistic moods.
Table 1. Valid syllogistic moods.
Figure 1Figure 2Figure 3Figure 4
1. MaP 1. PeM 1. MiP 1. PaM
2. SaM 2. SaM 2. MaS 2. MeS
SaP SeP SiP SeP
1. MeP 1. PaM 1. MaP 1. PiM
2. SaM 2. SeM 2. MiS 2. MaS
SeP SeP SiP SiP
1. MaP 1. PaM 1. MoP 1. PeM
2. SiM 2. SoM 2. MaS 2. MiS
SiP SoP SoP SoP
1. MeP 1. PeM 1. MeP
2. SiM 2. SiM 2. MiS
SoP SoP SoP
Table 2. Some valid de re syllogisms.
Table 2. Some valid de re syllogisms.
1. Ma P 1. Ma P 1. Ma P 1. Ma P
2. Sa M 2. Sa M 2. Sa M 2. SaM
Sa P SaP Sa P Sa P
1. Ma P 1. Ma P 1. Ma P 1. MaP
2. SaM 2. SaM 2. Sa M 2. Sa M
SaP Sa P Sa P SaP
1. MaP 1. MaP 1. MaP 1. Ma P
2. Sa M 2. SaM 2. SaM 2. SaM
Sa P SaP Sa P Sa P
Table 3. Some valid de dicto syllogisms.
Table 3. Some valid de dicto syllogisms.
1. ( MaP ) 1. ( MaP ) 1. ( MaP )
2. ( SaM ) 2. ( SaM ) 2. ( SaM )
( SaP ) SaP ( SaP )
1. ( MaP ) 1. ( MaP ) 1. MaP
2. SaM 2. SaM 2. ( SaM )
SaP ( SaP ) SaP
1. MaP 1. MaP 1. MaP
2. ( SaM ) 2. SaM 2. SaM
( SaP ) SaP ( SaP )
Table 4. Valid de re syllogisms.
Table 4. Valid de re syllogisms.
1. M a , a , e , e P 1. M a , a , e , e P 1. M a , a , e , e P
2. S a , i , a , i M 2. S a , i , a , i M 2. S a , i , a , i M
S a , i , e , o { P , P } S a , i , e , o { P , P , P } S a , i , e , o { P , P , P }
1. M a , a , e , e P 1. M a , a , e , e P 1. M a , a , e , e P
2. S a , i , a , i M 2. S a , i , a , i M 2. S a , i , a , i M
S a , i , e , o { P , P } S a , i , e , o P S a , i , e , o P
Table 5. Valid de dicto syllogisms.
Table 5. Valid de dicto syllogisms.
1. ( M a , a , e , e P ) 1. ( M a , a , e , e P )
2. ( S a , i , a , i M ) 2. S a , i , a , i M
{ ( S a , i , e , o P ) , S a , i , e , o P , ( S a , i , e , o P ) } { S a , i , e , o P , ( S a , i , e , o P ) }
1. M a , a , e , e P 1. M a , a , e , e P
2. ( S a , i , a , i M ) 2. S a , i , a , i M
{ S a , i , e , o P , ( S a , i , e , o P ) } { S a , i , e , o P , ( S a , i , e , o P ) }
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content.

Share and Cite

MDPI and ACS Style

Castro-Manzano, J.-M. On Line Diagrams Plus Modality. Logics 2024, 2, 1-10. https://doi.org/10.3390/logics2010001

AMA Style

Castro-Manzano J-M. On Line Diagrams Plus Modality. Logics. 2024; 2(1):1-10. https://doi.org/10.3390/logics2010001

Chicago/Turabian Style

Castro-Manzano, J.-Martín. 2024. "On Line Diagrams Plus Modality" Logics 2, no. 1: 1-10. https://doi.org/10.3390/logics2010001

Article Metrics

Back to TopTop