Next Article in Journal
Minardi, E. Thermodynamics of High Temperature Plasmas. Entropy, 2009, 11, 124-221
Next Article in Special Issue
In Defense of Gibbs and the Traditional Definition of the Entropy of Distinguishable Particles
Previous Article in Journal
Thermoeconomic Optimum Operation Conditions of a Solar-driven Heat Engine Model
Previous Article in Special Issue
Thermodynamics of the System of Distinguishable Particles
 
 
Font Type:
Arial Georgia Verdana
Font Size:
Aa Aa Aa
Line Spacing:
Column Width:
Background:
Letter

Gibbs’ Paradox in the Light of Newton’s Notion of State

Senzig, Ahornallee 11, D-15712 Königs Wusterhausen, Germany
Entropy 2009, 11(3), 454-456; https://doi.org/10.3390/e11030454
Submission received: 10 July 2009 / Accepted: 3 September 2009 / Published: 7 September 2009
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Gibbs Paradox and Its Resolutions)

Abstract

:
In this letter, it is argued that the correct counting of microstates is obtained from the very beginning when using Newtonian rather than Laplacian state functions, because the former are intrinsically permutation invariant.

Consider the classical mixing entropy, in particular the following case of “two identical fluid masses in contiguous chambers” ([1], Ch. XV, p. 206). “The entropy of the whole is equal to the sum of the entropies of the parts, and double that of one part. Suppose a valve is now opened, making a communication between the chambers. We do not regard this as making any change in the entropy, although the masses of gas or liquid diffuse into one another, and although the same process of diffusion would increase the entropy, if the masses of fluid were different.” ([1], Ch. XV, pp. 206 f.)
The paradox consists in that the Lagrange-Laplacian notion of state (comprising the dynamical variables positions and velocities or momenta of all bodies involved [2]) does predict a change in entropy, because it counts the interchange of two “identical” particles as representing two different states—at variance with the experimental outcome and with Gibbs’ writing quoted above.
This situation suggests to seek a state description, where the state is not changed by the opening of the valve above. In other words, the state description should be invariant against the interchange of equal bodies. As a matter of fact, such a state description has been used—among others—by Newton [3].
According to the laws of motion in his Principia [4], the state of a body is given by its momentum vector, p . In case of several bodies without external interaction, their total momentum,
p t o t = p 1 + p 2 +
is conserved. And it is invariant against the interchange of bodies of equal mass if m 2 = m 1 .
p t o t = m 1 v 1 + v 2 +
Analogously, the classical Hamiltonian is invariant against the interchange of bodies of equal mass, charge, etc. And because the thermodynamic equilibrium of a Gibbsian ensemble is determined by the Hamiltonian of the system under consideration ([1], Ch. I), it is invariant either. The factor 1 / N ! is thus not due to the (questionable) indistinguishability of quantum particles, but due to the permutation invariance of the classical Hamiltonian.
In other words, Lagrange-Laplacian state functions do not predict the experimentally observed behaviour, while Newtonian ones do. This suggests that it is not the states of motion which determine the statistics, but the stationary states. As a matter of fact, Einstein [5] has shown, that Planck’s quantum distribution law is a consequence of the discrete energy spectrum of a Planck resonator (quantum oscillator), while the classical distribution law results from the continuous energy spectrum of a classical oscillator. It is noteworthy that (in)distinguishability does not play any role here.
How does this reasoning manifest itself in the counting of micro-states?
Consider the textbook case of 2 fair coins and the 4 possible results of one fair toss (H = head, T = tail).
casecoin 1coin 2MBBEFD
1HH 1 4 1 3 0
2 3 m d H m d T m d T m d H 1 4 1 4 1 3 1
4TT 1 4 1 3 0
Maxwell-Boltzmann (MB) statistics assigns to each of the 4 cases the probability of 1/4. Bose-Einstein (BE) statistics considers the cases 2 and 3 to be one and the same, and assigns to each of the 3 remaining cases the probability of 1/3. Fermi-Dirac (FD) statistics also considers the cases 2 and 3 to be one and the same and, additionally, forbids the cases 1 and 4 (Pauli ban).
Now, as outlined above, from the viewpoint of Newtonian (stationary) states, the cases 2 and 3 are “automatically” one and the same. In other words, “Newtonian counting”—though being entirely classical—yields BE, i.e., quantum statistics. Similar conclusions have been drawn by Bach [6] along another route of reasoning.
In summary, Gibbs’ paradox concerning the mixing entropy can be resolved completely within classical physics (cf. [6][7][8]). This result is important for the self-consistency of classical statistical mechanics [9] as well as for the unity of classical physics [10].

Acknowledgements

I feel indebted to Michael Erdmann and Peter Göring for their critical reading of an earlier version of the manuscript and helpful discussions. I have also benefitted from numerous discussions in the moderated Usenet group sci.physics.foundations, from the common work with Shu-Kun Lin and Theo Nieuwenhuizen on the edition of this special issue, and from correspondence with Daniel Gottesman and Steven French. The critical remarks of two referees have been thankfully accounted for. Parts of this work have been supported by the Deutsche Akademie der Naturforscher Leopoldina [10].

References

  1. Gibbs, J.W. Elementary Principles in Statistical Mechanics Developed with Especial Reference to the Rational Foundation of Thermodynamics; Scribner: New York, NY, USA, 1902. [Google Scholar]
  2. de Laplace, P.S. Essai Philosophique sur la Probabilité; Courcier: Paris, France, 1814. [Google Scholar]
  3. Enders, P. Equality and Identity and (In)distinguishability in Classical and Quantum Mechanics from the Point of View of Newton’s Notion of State; Sidharth, B.G., Honsell, F., de Angelis, A., Eds.; Frontiers of Fundamental and Computational Physics. Proc. 6th Int. Symp., Udine, Italy, 26-29 Septemper, 2004; Springer: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 2006; pp. 239–245. [Google Scholar]
  4. Newton, I. The Principia. Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy (A New Translation by I. Bernhard Cohen and Anne Whitman assisted by Julia Buden, Preceded by A Guide to Newton’s Principia by I. Bernhard Cohen); University of California Press: Berkeley, CA, USA, 1999. [Google Scholar]
  5. Einstein, A. Die Plancksche Theorie der Strahlung und die Theorie der spezifischen Wärme. Ann. Phys. 1907, 20, 180–190. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  6. Bach, A. Indistinguishable Classical Particles; Berlin Springer: Heidelberg, Germany, 1997. [Google Scholar]
  7. Jaynes, E.T. The Gibbs Paradox. In Maximum Entropy and Bayesian Methods; Smith, C.R., Erickson, G.J., Neudorfer, P.O., Eds.; Kluwer: Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 1992; pp. 1–22. [Google Scholar]
  8. Saunders, S. On the explanation for quantum statistics. Stud. Hist. Phil. Mod. Phys. 2006, 37, 192–211. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  9. Enders, P. Is Classical Statistical Mechanics Self-Consistent? (A paper of honour of C.F. von Weizsäcker, 1912-2007). Progr. Phys. 2007, 3, 85–87. [Google Scholar]
  10. Enders, P. Zur Einheit der Klassischen Physik. Nova Acta Leopoldina, Suppl. 2006, 20, 48. [Google Scholar]

Share and Cite

MDPI and ACS Style

Enders, P. Gibbs’ Paradox in the Light of Newton’s Notion of State. Entropy 2009, 11, 454-456. https://doi.org/10.3390/e11030454

AMA Style

Enders P. Gibbs’ Paradox in the Light of Newton’s Notion of State. Entropy. 2009; 11(3):454-456. https://doi.org/10.3390/e11030454

Chicago/Turabian Style

Enders, Peter. 2009. "Gibbs’ Paradox in the Light of Newton’s Notion of State" Entropy 11, no. 3: 454-456. https://doi.org/10.3390/e11030454

Article Metrics

Back to TopTop