The Emergence of Ur-Intentionality: An Ecological Proposal
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Radical Enactivism and the Natural Origins of Content (NOC)
The number of a tree’s rings can covary with the age of the tree; however, this doesn’t entail that the first state of affairs says or conveys anything true about the second, or vice versa. The same goes for states that happen to be inside agents and which reliably correspond with external states of affairs—these too, in and of themselves, don’t “say” or “mean” anything just in virtue of instantiating covariance relations.([13], p. 67)
3. Problems with the NOC and the Emergence of Ur-Intentionality
4. An Ecological6 Proposal for the Emergence of Ur-Intentionality
4.1. Post-Cognitivist Approaches to Perceptual Learning: Enaction and Ecological Psychology
“According to radical enactivists, the way Gibsonians describe perceptual information leads to positions that are akin to the ones offered by representationalists (…). In summary, they find three main issues in the Gibsonian approach: first, the idea that perception requires picking up information from the outside world; second, the idea that this information specifies or is about the environment and the affordances present within it; and, third, that this information is meaningful. In light of this, radical enactivists conclude that EP is not radical enough as it stands and that it needs to be “RECtified”—that is, “sanitized” of its representational commitments (…). Contrary to this view, we have argued that the notions of ‘information,’ ‘specificity,’ and ‘meaning,’ if properly understood, do not entail a commitment to the existence of informational content in the world and, thus, that EP is not in conflict with the principles of the radical forms of embodied cognitive science. First, we have argued that perceptual information as conceived by EP is to be related to the organisms that inhabit a particular eco-niche. (…) According to Gibsonians, perception requires the detection of invariants—that is, structural patterns which remain constant beneath transformations. Because an invariant can only be detected against a particular transformation, invariants as key informational variables only become available through the active exploration of an environment by an agent. In the absence of particular organism–environment interactions, invariants are not available in the environment to be detected. Both reasons, considered together, cast doubt upon the idea that perceptual information is simply outside in the world, independently of organisms. After clarifying the nature of the perceptual information posited by EP, we have discussed whether describing this information as being specific and meaningful entails that this information is of a contentful kind. As we have argued, the notion of specificity refers to the lawful, 1:1 relation between invariant patterns in the ambient array and aspects of the organism– environment interaction. As such, specificity can best be understood as lawful covariation, without any assumption that it carries content. Invariants covary with the environment and the affordances present in it, but they do not convey anything true or false, veridical or non-veridical, and so on about them. Finally, we have explained that the notion of meaning as used in EP is to be related to affordances. Perceptual information, hence, is said to be meaningful for an agent or an organism because it affords certain opportunities for interaction to her, but this meaning is orthogonal to semantics. In light of these arguments, we conclude that EP is radical enough and that it is apt to be included in a full-blown post-cognitivist approach to cognition.”.
4.2. Direct Learning and Ur-Intentionality
5. Conclusions
Author Contributions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Hutto and Myin [13] use “radical enactive cognitive science” and “radical embodied cognitive science” as synonyms. In this paper we follow this lead, so “REC” stands for both. |
2 | To be accurate, RECers dismiss unrestricted CIC, not CIC as such: “CIC assumes that cognition requires the existence of contents of some kind or other. Unrestricted CIC takes this to be true of all mentality, always and everywhere.” ([13], p. 9). However, for the sake of word economy, when we refer to CIC in this paper, we mean unrestricted CIC. |
3 | Hutto and Myin state the Hard Problem of Content as the incompatibility between an explanatory naturalism and the positing of informational content. However, this is not quite accurate, for they in fact assume the existence of informational content and its compatibility with naturalism. What they reject is the assimilation between covariance and content. That is why we state the Hard Problem of Content as being concerned with what is, according to the authors, commonly discussed under the label of informational content. |
4 | It must be said that Hutto, Satne, and Myin have not coined the concept of Ur-intentionality. They cite Muller [14], who discusses Sachs [15] on McDowell and animal minds. However, while Sachs only points to a logical distinction, these authors use this distinction as a desiderata for any theory accounting for the natural origins of content. We thank an anonymous reviewer for pointing this out to us. |
5 | This issue regarding the centrality of the organism rather than genes or populations is a very hot topic in contemporary biological theory debates. E-cognition approaches in principle should benefit the EES since both approaches strongly focus on the organism and its capability to adjust to environmental changes through flexible behavior. For more information, see Walsh and Heras-Escribano [18,19]. |
6 | Along this paper, we use “ecological” to refer to the approach to perception developed by James and Eleanor Gibson, and to its forward developments since the 1970’s. |
7 | Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for inviting us to reproduce the main conclusions of the analysis of Segundo-Ortin et al. [23] on the compatibility of radical enactivism and ecological psychology. |
8 | It must be noted that we do not claim that neural activity is not relevant for perceptual learning, or that a complete multi-level account of the phenomena must leave the neural scale aside. There is, in fact, some recent work in the ecological psychology literature that points to a way of describing the neural mechanisms involved in perceptual learning without relying on the concept of information processing (see e.g., [30]). |
9 | Millikan [34] discusses classical examples of perceptual learning in the literature of ecological psychology. We point to her discussion for a useful contrast between both approaches regarding this issue. |
10 | We thank an anonymous reviewer for pointing this to us. |
11 | One of the reasons that we prefer direct learning to the enactive approach to perceptual learning in Di Paolo et al. [22] is that ecological psychologists have gathered empirical evidence for supporting their claims since several decades ago using in vivo experimental studies in human beings, something that enactivists are far from doing, at least at the same scale than ecological psychologists. For more information on the differences between enaction and ecological psychology, see [36,37]. |
References
- Hutto, D.; Satne, G. The natural origins of content. Philosophia 2015, 43, 521–536. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hutto, D.; Satne, G. Continuity Skepticism in Doubt: A Radically Enactive Take. In Embodiment, Action and Culture: Investigating the Constitution of the Shared World; Durt, C., Fuchs, T., Tewes, C., Eds.; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2017; pp. 107–129. [Google Scholar]
- Gibson, E.; Pick, A. An Ecological Approach to Perceptual Learning and Development; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2000. [Google Scholar]
- Jacobs, D.; Michaels, C. Direct learning. Ecol. Psychol. 2007, 19, 321–349. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Higueras-Herbada, A.; De Paz, C.; Jacobs, D.; Travieso, D.; Ibáñez-Gijón, J. The Direct Learning Theory: A Naturalistic approach to learning for the post-cognitivist era. Adapt. Behav. 2019, 27, 389–403. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Colombo, M.; Piccinini, G. The Computational Theory of Mind; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2023. [Google Scholar]
- Piccinini, G. Neurocognitive Mechanisms: Explaining Biological Cognition; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2020. [Google Scholar]
- Clark, A. Being There: Putting Brain, Body, and World Together Again; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 1998. [Google Scholar]
- Piccinini, G. Situated neural representations: Solving the problems of content. Front. Neurorobot. 2022, 16, 846979. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Varela, F.; Thompson, E.; Rosch, E. The Embodied Mind: Cognitive Science and Human Experience; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Ward, D.; Silverman, D.; Villalobos, M. Introduction: The varieties of enactivism. Topoi 2017, 36, 365–375. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hutto, D. REC: Revolution effected by clarification. Topoi 2015, 36, 377–391. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hutto, D.; Myin, E. Radicalizing Enactivism: Basic Minds without Content; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- Muller, H.D. Naturalism and Intentionality. In Contemporary Philosophical Naturalism and Its Implications; Bashour, B., Muller, H., Eds.; Routledge: London, UK, 2013; pp. 13–155. [Google Scholar]
- Sachs, C.B. Resisting the disenchantment of nature: McDowell and the Question of Animal Minds. Inquiry 2012, 55, 131–147. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Abramova, K.; Villalobos, M. The apparent (Ur-)Intentionality of living beings and the game of content. Philosophia 2015, 43, 651–668. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rowlands, M. Hard problems of intentionality. Philosophia 2015, 43, 741–746. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Walsh, D.M. Organisms, Agency, and Evolution; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Heras–Escribano, M. The evolutionary role of affordances: Ecological psychology, niche construction, and natural selection. Biol. Philos. 2020, 35, 30. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lobo, L. Current Alternatives on Perceptual learning: Introduction to special issue on Post-cognitivist approaches to Perceptual learning. Adapt. Behav. 2019, 27, 355–362. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Nöe, A. Action in Perception; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2004. [Google Scholar]
- Di Paolo, E.A.; Bührmann, T.; Barandiaran, X.E. Sensorimotor Life: An Enactive Proposal; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Segundo-Ortin, M.; Heras–Escribano, M.; Raja, V. Ecological psychology is radical enough: A reply to radical enactivists. Philos. Psychol. 2019, 32, 1001–1023. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gibson, J.J.; Gibson, E.J. Perceptual learning: Differentiation or enrichment? Psychol. Rev. 1955, 62, 32–41. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Gibson, E.J.; Walk, R.D. The “Visual Cliff”. Sci. Am. 1960, 202, 64–71. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Walk, R.D.; Gibson, E.J. A comparative and analytical study of visual depth perception. Psychol. Monogr. Gen. Appl. 1961, 75, 1–44. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Adolph, K.; Eppler, A.; Gibson, E.J. Crawling versus walking Infants’ perception of affordances for locomotion over sloping surfaces. Child Dev. 1993, 64, 1158–1174. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Adolph, K.; Cole, W.; Komati, M.; Garciaguirre, J.; Badaly, D.; Lingeman, J.; Chan, G.L.; Sotsky, R. How Do You Learn to Walk? Thousands of Steps and Dozens of Falls per Day. Psychol. Sci. 2012, 23, 1387–1394. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Adolph, K.E.; Vereijken, B.; Denny, M.A. Learning to crawl. Child Dev. 1998, 69, 1299–1312. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Raja, V. From metaphor to theory: The role of resonance in perceptual learning. Adapt. Behav. 2019, 27, 405–421. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Szokolszky, Á.; Read, C.; Palatinus, Z.; Palatinus, K. Ecological approaches to perceptual learning: Learning to perceive and perceiving as learning. Adapt. Behav. 2019, 27, 363–388. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Satne, G. Practical knowledge and shared agency: Pluralizing the Anscombean view. Inquiry 2020, 67, 1018–1045. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Segundo-Ortín, M.; Satne, G. Sharing attention, sharing affordances: From dyadic interaction to collective information. In Access and Mediation: Interdisciplinary Perspectives on Attention; Wehrle, M., D’Angelo, D., Solomonova, E., Eds.; De Gruyter: Berlin, Germany, 2022; pp. 91–113. [Google Scholar]
- Millikan, R.G. Beyond Concepts: Unicepts, Language, and Natural Information; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Hutto, D.; Myin, E. Evolving Enactivism: Basic Minds Meet Content; MIT Press: Cambridge, MA, USA, 2017. [Google Scholar]
- Heft, H. Ecological psychology and enaction theory: Divergent groundings. Front. Psychol. 2020, 11, 991. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Heras-Escribano, M. Ecological psychology, enaction, and the quest for an embodied and situated cognitive science. In Situated Cognition Research: Methodological Foundations; Casper, M.O., Artese, G.F., Eds.; Springer International Publishing: Cham, Switzerland, 2023; pp. 83–102. [Google Scholar]
- Jacobs, D.; Vaz, D.; Michaels, C. The learning of visually guided action: An information-space analysis of pole balancing. J. Exp. Psychol. Hum. Percept. Perform. 2012, 38, 1215–1227. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Bongers, R.; Michaels, C. The role of eye and head movements in detecting information about fly balls. J. Exp. Psychol. Hum. Percept. Perform. 2008, 34, 1515–1523. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Zaal, F.T.J.M.; Michaels, C. The information for catching fly balls: Judging and intercepting virtual balls in a CAVE. J. Exp. Psychol. Hum. Percept. Perform. 2003, 29, 537–555. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Michaels, C.; Zeinstra, E.B.; Oudejans, R.R.D. Information and action in punching a falling ball. Q. J. Exp. Psychol. Sect. A 2001, 54, 69–93. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Jacobs, D.; Michaels, C. Lateral interception I: Operative optical variables, attunement, and calibration. J. Exp. Psychol. Hum. Percept. Perform. 2006, 32, 443–458. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Reed, E.S. An outline of a theory of action systems. J. Mot. Behav. 1982, 14, 98–134. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Heras-Escribano, M. The Philosophy of Affordances; Palgrave Macmillian: London, UK, 2019. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2024 by the authors. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Heras-Escribano, M.; Martínez Moreno, D. The Emergence of Ur-Intentionality: An Ecological Proposal. Philosophies 2024, 9, 54. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies9030054
Heras-Escribano M, Martínez Moreno D. The Emergence of Ur-Intentionality: An Ecological Proposal. Philosophies. 2024; 9(3):54. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies9030054
Chicago/Turabian StyleHeras-Escribano, Manuel, and Daniel Martínez Moreno. 2024. "The Emergence of Ur-Intentionality: An Ecological Proposal" Philosophies 9, no. 3: 54. https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies9030054