1. Introduction
What can account for the quality of experience? Take a glimpse at the night sky (
Figure 1): why does the experience feel subjectively the way it does—like an extended canvas sprinkled with tiny spots at many distinct locations? Then look at the sky on a bright day: why does its vivid blue color feel the way it does? Or why does pain feel painful? And why does a face look like a face? Eventually, a scientific understanding of consciousness should provide a principled, testable answer to such questions, but it is not easy to see how one could even begin to approach them. Indeed, the subjective, qualitative feeling of color or pain—“what it is like” to experience the blueness of the sky or the painfulness of pain [
1]—is regularly invoked to highlight the seemingly unbridgeable explanatory gap between subjective “qualia” and the underlying neural mechanisms [
2].
The paradigmatic examples used to illustrate the “hard problem” of consciousness are typically the subjective feeling of color or pain [
3], rather than the subjective feeling of extendedness of the sky or of our own body. However, the feeling of extendedness is just as qualitative and in need of explanation as the feeling of color or pain [
4,
5]. It is also pervasive: much of our conscious life is spent anchored in body space, upon which we locate touch or pain, and immersed in visual space, which provides an extended canvas over which all the colors, the contours, and the objects we experience are painted, image after image (see Note 1 in
Appendix B). Most important, spatial phenomenology may be a better place than color to attempt an initial account of how consciousness feels. For example, the experience of blue seems to be monolithically impenetrable to introspection, because it just seems inherently blue, with no obvious sign of an internal structure. By contrast, the experience of space is penetrable by introspection in a way that reveals a characteristic internal structure. As we will now argue, the canvas of space can be decomposed in terms of the phenomenal distinctions and relations that compose the experience and make it what it is.
Consider again looking at the night sky: the experience can be described roughly as a two-dimensional canvas (
Figure 1A). Within the experiential canvas, one can readily
distinguish ‘spots’ anywhere, of any size, as large as the entire firmament or as small as a single star (
Figure 1B). Some reflection suggests that what endows the canvas with the characteristically spatial feeling of
extendedness are certain properties of the
relations among spots (
Figure 1C): every spot overlaps with itself; for any spot, we can always find a spot that partially overlaps it such that their intersection is also a spot (connection); a spot that partially overlaps it such that their union is also a spot (fusion); and a spot that includes it or is included by it (inclusion). Further reflection suggests that other properties of the structure of spatial experience follow from the fundamental properties of connection, fusion, and inclusion (
Figure 1D). Thus, a spot picks out a unique region of space, has a unique location within the overall space, a particular size, boundary, and distance from any other spot. Intriguingly, the canvas itself is not experienced as having a boundary: it extends ‘as far as one can see’, in the sense that there is no canvas exterior to it. Typically, the experience of space is embossed by local inhomogeneities, such as stars in the sky or blots on a canvas; moreover, particular regions of space can be highlighted by the spotlight of attention. However, it is important to realize that the spots and characteristic relations that compose phenomenal space are present whether or not some regions stand out: if a bright blot appears somewhere within the canvas, it cannot appear ‘out of nowhere’—a corresponding spot of the same size, with the appropriate relations to other spots, must already have been ‘there’, except that it was dark; similarly, the spot will remain ‘there’ even if the bright blot turns dark like the rest of the canvas (see Note 2 in
Appendix B). Indeed, the experience of space does not depend on inhomogeneities within the canvas, such as bright stars or printed characters, but occurs even if the canvas is fully homogeneous, like a dark sky or an empty screen. Moreover, experiencing space does not require introspection or attention, but occurs without effort, as when walking on a country road with nothing particular in mind.
This crude phenomenal characterization of spatial experience is obviously incomplete—for example, the depth of visual space is not considered. It is also inevitably contaminated by non-spatial features—for example, we cannot help experiencing the color of the canvas, or avoid seeing bright spots as stars. However, we can still attempt to isolate spatial properties by abstracting over other features of experience. For example, within visual space, the canvas could be white or black, red or green, the inhomogeneities dark over a light background or the other way around, yet its phenomenal spatial properties remain largely the same, regardless of its other qualities. Spatial properties do not even need to be tied to the visual modality: extendedness applies just as well to body space, regardless of its local qualities such as touch, pressure, and so on. Thus, despite several limitations, it seems possible to capture the fundamental aspects of the experience of space.
Can the structure of spatial experience be accounted for scientifically, in physical terms, bridging the explanatory gap in a way that is both principled and testable? More precisely, can phenomenal properties be accounted for in a way that connects them to specific substrates in the brain, which are known to determine the specific contents of consciousness?
This paper presents an initial attempt at doing so by employing the principles of integrated information theory (IIT, [
6,
7]), which provides a comprehensive approach to characterize what consciousness is, what is required of a physical substrate to support it, and what determines the quality of particular experiences, including spatial ones.
Briefly, integrated information theory starts from the existence of one’s own consciousness, which is immediate and indubitable. The theory then identifies five essential properties that are also immediate, indubitable, and true of every conceivable experience, namely intrinsicality, composition, information, integration, and exclusion. Intrinsicality means that every experience is subjective—it is for the subject of experience, from its own intrinsic perspective, rather than for something extrinsic to it. Thus, the canvas of my phenomenal space is experienced by me, not by somebody else. Composition means that every experience is structured, being composed of phenomenal distinctions and relations. In the case of spatial experiences, distinctions can be taken as spots and their relations as the way spots connect, fuse, and include each other. Information means that every experience is the particular way it is. For example, the canvas of space may be homogeneous, or embossed by inhomogeneities such as stars, tree branches and leaves, or characters on the screen, in countless possible configurations. Integration means that every experience is unified, being irreducible to independent components. Thus, the canvas of space cannot be reduced to a left side and a right side that are experienced independently—if it were so, there would be two independent consciousnesses rather than one. Finally, exclusion means that every experience is definite—it contains what it contains, neither less nor more. In the case of space, the canvas contains all the spots and relations it contains—not just the left or the right side, or just a single spot in the middle or in the periphery—but it does not contain any spots beyond its borders, such as spots behind one’s head. Importantly, these five essential properties are true of every conceivable experience, not just of spatial ones.
The theory then proceeds to characterize the requirements that must be satisfied by the physical substrate of our own consciousness. A physical substrate is intended as a system of connected units in a state, such as a set of active and inactive neurons in our brain. The cause-effect powers of a substrate are assessed by observations and manipulations: for example, neurons can be turned on or off by their inputs, and can turn on or off other neurons through their outputs. If every experience has the essential properties of being intrinsic, structured, specific, unified, and definite, its physical substrate must satisfy these properties in causal terms. Thus, intrinsicality means that a candidate substrate of consciousness, such as a set of neurons in the cerebral cortex, must have cause-effect power upon itself, rather than just with respect to sensory inputs and motor outputs. Composition means that one must consider the structure of intrinsic cause-effect power—how various combinations of neurons can have causes and effects within the system (causal distinctions) and how these distinctions overlap causally (causal relations). Information means that the causes and effects specified by various combinations of neurons are specific states of specific subsets of neurons, yielding a specific cause-effect structure. Integration means that causal distinctions and relations, as well as the overall cause-effect structure they compose, only exist if they are irreducible—if they cannot be reduced to independent causes and effects. Finally, exclusion means that causal distinctions and relations, as well as the cause-effect structure they compose, must be definite, containing what they contain—neither less nor more. What defines the set of neurons that constitute the physical substrate of consciousness—as opposed to any of its subsets or supersets—is being maximally irreducible, as measured by integrated information Φ.
On this basis, integrated information theory proposes an explanatory identity between a particular experience and the particular cause-effect structure specified by a physical substrate in its current state [
6,
7]. Applied to the experience of space, the proposed identity means the following: all the phenomenal distinctions and relations that compose the structure of phenomenal space must correspond one-to-one to causal distinctions and relations that compose the cause-effect structure specified by the neural substrate of spatial consciousness. In other words, all the spots that connect to each other, fuse with each other, and include each other to compose an extended structure characterized by regions, locations, sizes, boundaries, and distances, must have a correspondent in the cause-effect structure specified by the substrate of spatial experience in the brain. We emphasize that the goal is to account in physical terms for spatial experience as such—the causal distinctions and relations that compose it—rather than merely for how the brain represents external space and performs spatial functions. We further emphasize that the proposed correspondence is with the cause-effect structure unfolded from a neural substrate, not with the substrate as such.
A main reason for choosing space to assess the proposed identity between the properties of experience and those of cause-effect structures is that we can propose a plausible neural substrate, namely cortical areas that are organized in a grid-like manner, which are known to map both visual and body space [
8]. As will be shown in the Results section, when properly unfolded to make all their causal powers explicit, grids specify cause-effect structures of extraordinary richness. This richness is needed to fully account for ‘what it is like’ to experience space—all the spots that are co-present in the mind, ordered by characteristic relations of connection, fusion, and inclusion to compose the feeling of an extended canvas.
In what follows, we apply the tools of integrated information theory to unfold the causal powers of simple grid-like substrates by characterizing the causal distinctions and relations they specify. While we examine primarily the cause-effect structures specified by small 1D grids due to their computational advantages, the findings can be generalized to larger, 2D grids. The results support the conjecture that the cause-effect structures specified by grid-like substrates, such as the 2D grids found in posterior cortical regions, could in principle account for the spatial aspects of experience.
3. Results
The cause-effect structure unfolded from the 1D grid substrate in state all-Off described above is partly shown in
Figure 6. Here the structure is illustrated as a simplicial complex. Each distinction has a 1st order relation (its cause relates to its effect), so it is represented by a single vertex; each edge represents a complete 2nd-order relation (a 4-relation between the causes and effects of both distinctions as well as the underlying 2- and 3-relations); each face represents a complete 3rd-order relation; higher-order relations are not shown. The coordinates of the vertices are a t-SNE [
14] projection of the units that constitute the mechanisms and purviews of the distinctions. The t-SNE projection is a useful visualization tool since it happens to pick out two important symmetries of the grid’s intrinsic cause-effect structure: it orders distinctions by their cardinality (how many units they involve) and by the proximity of the grid units (A, B, C, …). Note that, in the case of the 1D grid, the same units tend to constitute the mechanism, cause, and effect of a distinction (
Figure 4), simplifying the representation. Nevertheless,
Figure 6 indicates that the cause-effect structure specified by a simple line-grid substrate in state All-Off is remarkably rich: consider that a 8-unit grid specifies 133 causal distinctions; between these there are 7976 2nd-order relations (‘edges’ in
Figure 6) and more than 870,000 3rd-order relations (‘faces’ in
Figure 6).
In what follows, we assess whether this cause-effect structure can account for the fundamental spatial relation of extendedness, which encompasses connection, fusion, and inclusion of spots. We then examine spatial properties such as regions, locations, sizes, distances, and boundaries that derive from extendedness. Finally, we consider the effects of changing the state of some grid units, corresponding to spatial inhomogeneities, and of increasing their gain, corresponding to highlighting through spatial attention. We also consider whether these spatial properties can be accounted for not just at the level of individual distinctions and relations, but also at the level of compound distinctions and relations, which corresponds more directly to the coarse grain of introspective phenomenology.
A note on terminology and labels in this section: Unless otherwise specified, from here on ‘purview’ should be understood to refer to the combination of a distinction’s cause and effect purviews; ‘relations’ to bundles of relations (cause-cause, cause-effect, effect-cause, and effect-effect); ‘overlap’ to the combination of between-distinction relations (cause-cause overlap, cause-effect overlap and so-on); ‘φR’ to the sum of of the individual between-distinction relations (the cause-cause φ plus the cause-effect φ and so-on). Doing so simplifies the description of the cause-effect structure specified by a grid, taking advantage of its symmetries, primarily the fact that the cause and effect of most distinctions tend to be similar or the same.
3.1. Spots
To bootstrap the process of accounting for phenomenal properties through physical properties, one must start somewhere. In the context of spatial experience, the place to start phenomenally is a
spot picked out by introspection. One can easily distinguish any particular spot—
that spot (
Figure 1). As already pointed out, a spot can be anywhere within the canvas of space, ranging from the totality of space down to any of its points. A spot always overlaps itself, a property we call
reflexivity. In terms of the cause-effect structure specified by a grid, the natural correspondent of a phenomenal distinction is a causal distinction: the mechanism specifying the distinction can be thought of as a ‘handle’ on the cause-effect structure, which ‘pulls’ with it other distinctions that have relations to its cause-effect. As shown in
Figure 4 and
Figure 6, the 1D grid specifies 133 distinctions whose cause-effects can pick out many subsets of units along the grid, ranging from the full set of units down to individual units. An important property of these distinctions is that each one has a 1st-order relation between its cause and its effect. This self-relation corresponds to the phenomenal property that a spot overlaps with itself (reflexivity). One can thus proceed to evaluate whether the relations among causal distinctions in the structure can account for the fundamental phenomenal property of
extendedness which arguably characterizes spatial experiences. We define extendedness in terms of three relational structures—connection, fusion, and inclusion.
3.1.1. Connection
Phenomenally, one can check through introspection that, for any spot, one can always find spots with which it composes a connection: for any spot, one can find another spot that overlaps it partially and symmetrically, such that their intersection is also a spot; in turn, any spot is the intersection of two partially overlapping spots. Because two spots overlap over a spot, they overlap each other in the same way as a spot overlaps itself.
To account for phenomenal connection in terms of the cause-effect structure specified by a grid-like substrate, one needs to show that, for any causal distinction specified by the grid, one can find another distinction that is causally related to it in a way that satisfies connection, both ‘upward’ and ‘downward’. For example, consider the distinction CDE in
Figure 7A. One can easily see that CDE is related to another distinction, in this case DEF, by 2nd-order relations among their causes and effects. These relations are complete because they involve all the causes and effects of the distinctions they relate. The completeness of the relation corresponds to reflexivity. Moreover, all these relations are partial (none involves all the units of either’s purview) and symmetric (cause-cause, effect-effect, cause-effect, and effect-cause, and so on). We also see that the intersection between CDE and DEF corresponds to a distinction (DE). Both CDE and DEF fully overlap DE, and any other distinction to which they both relate is also related to DE. DE is thus the
connection of CDE and DEF. In turn, CDE is the connection between the partially overlapping distinctions BCDE and CDEF. Finally,
Figure 7B shows that CDE is connected to many other distinctions besides DEF and is also the connection among many other distinctions within the system (Note: unless otherwise stated, when a set of units is referred to by a label such as CDE with no superscript, the label refers to the units that constitute the mechanism of the distinction).
3.1.2. Fusion
One can also introspectively check that, for any spot, one can always find spots with which it composes a fusion: for any spot, one can find another spot that overlaps it partially and symmetrically, such that their union is also a spot; in turn, any spot is the union of two partially overlapping spots.
To account for phenomenal fusion in terms of the cause-effect structure specified by a grid-like substrate, one needs to show that, for any causal distinction specified by the grid, one can find other distinctions that are causally related to it in a way that satisfies fusion, both ‘upward’ and ‘downward’. Consider again the distinction CDE (
Figure 7E). One can easily see that CDE is related, as before, to DEF, by 2nd-order relations among their causes and effects that are partial and symmetric. We also see that the union of CDE and DEF corresponds to a distinction (CDEF). CDEF fully overlaps both CDE and DEF, and any other distinction that overlaps CDEF also overlaps either CDE, DEF, or both. CDEF is thus the
fusion of CDE and DEF. In turn, CDE is the fusion between partially overlapping distinctions CD and DE. Finally,
Figure 7F shows that CDE fuses with many other distinctions besides DEF.
3.1.3. Inclusion
Finally, one can check through introspection that, for any spot, one can always find a spot that includes it (inclusion up) or is included by it (inclusion down). The phenomenal inclusion relation is reflexive, antisymmetric, and transitive, meaning that a spot includes itself, if it includes a second spot it cannot be included by it, and if the second spot includes a third spot, then the first spot includes the third.
To account for inclusion in terms of the cause-effect structure specified by a grid-like substrate, one needs to show that a causal relation that is reflexive, antisymmetric, and transitive is satisfied by most distinctions specified by the grid. Consider again distinction CDE and some of its causal relations (
Figure 7C). Like all grid distinctions, CDE is related to itself through a 1st–order relation between its cause and effect (reflexivity). It also fully overlaps (down) the distinction DE, corresponding to a complete 2nd-order relations. These relations are antisymmetric, because CDE fully overlaps DE, but not the other way around. They are also transitive because, if there is a causal relation of full overlap (down) between DE and another distinction, such as D, then there is also a relation of full overlap (down) between CDE and D. The figure also shows that CDE includes (down) other distinctions besides DE and C, and is included (up) by many other distinctions within the structure (
Figure 7D). The inclusion relation is denoted by the
symbols. Specific instances of inclusion can be denoted by the labels inclusion-
down (CDE
DE), inclusion-
up (CDE
CDEF) and
mutual-inclusion (CDE = CDE).
3.1.4. Extendedness: Grid-Like and Random-Like Graphs
Figure 8 summarizes which distinctions specified by the line-grid satisfy extendedness, characterized in terms of connection, fusion, and inclusion. In general, because of the highly symmetric connectivity among grid units, most distinctions satisfy connection (118/133). Furthermore, all distinctions are included (up and/or down) by a large number of other distinctions within the structure in a way that accords with reflexivity, antisymmetry, and transitivity. Reflexivity holds across the structure because the cause and effect of grid mechanisms are most often identical (115 out of 133) and otherwise very similar (16 with cause and effect differing by a single unit, 2 distinctions by 2 units). Most distinctions are extended (117/13): they satisfy fusion in addition to connection and inclusion. One distinction, the
total distinction (ABCDEFGH), is purely extended down, because it includes the entire grid and is only a fusion of other distinctions; the remaining 16 distinctions are reflexive and yet neither extended up or down, because they have 1-unit purviews that neither connect to nor include down any other distinction. Given that most distinctions and relations specified by a grid-like substrate, except for total and point distinctions, satisfy extendedness, we call the cause-effect structure specified by a grid-like substrate an
extension.
By way of comparison,
Figure 8B summarizes which distinctions satisfy extendedness—connection, fusion, and inclusion—for a ‘random’ network (
Figure 8B), constituted of the same number of units and connections as the line-grid, but with connections scrambled quasi-randomly (allowing some to become negative, indicated in red). The cause-effect structure specified by the random network has 153 distinctions, 20 more than the grid, but of these only one is connected both up and down, none are fused up and down, and therefore none are extended. Self-relations in the random network are mostly over single units, as shown in
Figure 8B, and 18 distinctions have no self-relation at all. Similar results were obtained for other “random” networks (not shown).
3.1.5. Regions
Several properties of spatial experience can be understood as derivable from extendedness. Introspectively, the
region covered by a spot can be thought of as the set of all the spots it fully overlaps. In the cause-effect structure specified by a grid, a region corresponds to all the distinctions that are included down by a particular distinction—its
subtext (
Figure 9A, in orange). More strictly, it corresponds to those down-included distinctions that decompose it recursively (CDE decomposes to CD and DE). This stricter criterion excludes the 1st-order distinctions (
,
, and so on).
3.1.6. Locations
Introspectively, the
location of a spot can be thought of as the set of all the spots that fully overlap that spot, constraining its place within the totality of the space. A helpful analogy is a geographical address: the location of a place is given by a set of larger places that include it. In the cause-effect structure specified by a grid, a location corresponds to all the distinctions that include up a particular distinction—its
supertext (
Figure 9B, in blue). More strictly, it corresponds to those up-included distinctions to which it extends recursively (as CDE extends to CDEFG, which extends to ABCDEFGH).
3.1.7. Sizes, Boundaries, and Distances
Ideas about space are often built around notions like size and distance as defined operationally from an extrinsic, ‘objective’ (intersubjective) perspective. However, these notions are ultimately based on the intrinsic, subjective perspective of a conscious experiencer. For example, the phenomenal
size of a spot can be characterized introspectively by the number of spots it includes down (the size of its region), or more precisely as the number of ways the spot can be decomposed down to points. In the cause-effect structure specified by a grid, the size of a distinction can be defined as the number of distinctions it fully includes (the size of its subtext), or more precisely as the number of ways the distinction can be decomposed down to distinctions that are purely extended up (
Figure 9C).
Another property of spatial experience is the
boundary of a spot. For any spot, we can introspect that it has a boundary, which can be thought of as the set of the
smallest spots that are connected to it. In the cause-effect structure, the boundary of a distinction corresponds to the set of the smallest distinctions that are connected to it (
Figure 9D). Also, just as a space itself has no boundary, a distinction may have no connections if it is purely extended down (the ‘total distinction’, e.g., ABCDEFGH). The example of
Figure 9D captures this aspect of boundaries in a space: the distinction ABCD has a region extending from A to D, but its only boundary spot is DE: ABCD has no boundary on its ‘A side’.
Finally, the phenomenal
distance between
any two spots can be thought of as the smallest spot they both extend (up) to, i.e., their
least fusion. In terms of the cause-effect structure specified by a grid, the distance between two distinctions corresponds to the subtext of the smallest distinction to which they both extend (up) (
Figure 9E). Importantly, a distance can be defined for
any pair of distinctions within the structure, in accordance with intuitions about space.
Together, the set of relations that bind a given distinction to other distinctions within the cause-effect structure form its
context. If a mechanism is a ‘handle’ on the cause-effect structure, the context is what one gets when the handle is ‘pulled’. The context of a distinction is analogous to the star of a vertex in a simplicial complex [
13].
3.2. Inhomogeneities
Introspectively, spatial
inhomogeneities are local disruptions in extendedness. For example, one or more spots may ‘stand out’ from the rest of space, say bright stars in the otherwise dark sky, even though the overall, extended fabric of space is preserved. Typically, an inhomogeneity is associated with a difference in local qualities, such as colors. However, there is a purely spatial aspect to an inhomogeneity, since the same inhomogeneity can be associated, at the same location, with a boundary between a bright and a dark region, a red and a blue region, and so on.
Figure 10 shows the consequences of introducing an inhomogeneity by turning On a few units (CDEF), as would be the case if they were activated by a stimulus. Compared to the cause-effect structure specified by a grid with all units Off, many relations are reduced in their
φR value (indicated by the ‘hollow’ symbols), especially the supertext of CDEF. On the other hand, other components of the structure are enhanced (indicated by the ‘solid’ symbols), especially the subtext of CDEF and that of other distinctions included by it {CDE, DEF, CD, DE, EF}. Some distinctions to which CDEF is connected are enhanced, in particular its two boundary spots BC and FG. Importantly, the overall cause-effect structure is still generally extended (75/133 distinctions are extended up and/or down). Translating back to phenomenology, the overall effect of turning on a patch of units is that the region they specify is made more salient, its location within the rest of space less so, while the experience remains altogether spatial.
It is important to note that the consequences of an inhomogeneity in the state of some units can depend strongly on their activation function. For example, if the strength of connections among active units were to increase above their baseline level, the φ value of most distinctions and relations they specify may increase as well.
3.3. Attentional Highlighting
Introspectively, the
spotlight of attention can shift from one location to another as well as expand or contract [
15,
16]. Phenomenally, the attended region of space appears to be
highlighted—as if more of the experience were concentrated there—at the expense of the rest of the canvas.
This local highlighting has a direct correlate in the cause-effect structure of an attended spot within a grid, assuming a simple model of spatial attention. Spatial attention involves an increase in the response gain of neurons in the selected region of space [
17,
18,
19], which was simulated by increasing the response gain of spotlighted units in the grid. In
Figure 11, the ‘unattended’ grid, with all units Off, is the same as in all previous examples (with threshold
z = 0.25). To simulate and ‘attended’ spot, the gain of units CDEF was slightly increased (their
z reduced by 10% to
z = 0.225). The unfolded cause-effect structure reveals an enhancement of many relations, especially those belonging to the context of distinctions CDEF, CDE, and DEF. Again, the overall cause-effect structure is still extended (112/133 distinctions are extended up and/or down). Translating back to phenomenology, the overall effect of increasing the gain of a subset of units is that the spot they specify is highlighted.
3.4. Compound Distinctions and Relations
The previous sections provided evidence for a close correspondence between phenomenal properties of spatial experience and physical properties of a substrate at the level of the individual distinctions and relations that compose the cause-effect structure it specifies. However, the section on attentional highlighting also showed that, when we introspect and employ the spotlight of attention to increase the gain of a subset of units, we highlight not just individual distinctions and relations, but rather
groups of distinctions and relations, composed of many distinctions and their contexts. For example, as illustrated in
Figure 11, attending to a subset of units within the grid (CDEF) affects not only the distinction CDEF, but all the included distinctions CDE, DEF, CD, DE, EF, CE, DF, C, D, E, F, together with their contexts. Accordingly, the combination of all the distinctions picked out by CDEF is called a
compound distinction, and the their combined context is called a
compound context (within which one can distinguish, as usual, connections, fusions, and inclusions).
Strictly speaking, then, it is at the level of compound distinctions and contexts that we can handily employ introspection to establish a correspondence between phenomenal and physical properties, including spots and the fundamental property of spatial extendedness. Even so, it can be shown that, if a phenomenal spot is taken to correspond to a compound distinction, extendedness percolates from the level of individual distinctions and contexts to that of compound distinctions and contexts. Specifically, the properties of connection, fusion, and inclusion among spots hold for contexts of distinctions, which in turn implies that they must also hold for compound distinctions and compound contexts. Thus, when a distinction is connected to another, their compound contexts must also be connected—in particular their compound subtexts. When two distinctions are fused, their compound contexts must overlap in a fusion. Finally, when a distinction is included by another, the former’s compound context must be fully overlapped by the latter’s. Similar considerations apply to regions, locations, sizes, distances, and boundaries.
3.5. A 2D Grid
The examples in this section have focused on a small 1D line-grid network because it allowed us to unfold its cause-effect structure in its entirety. Even in this case, the cause-effect structure turns out to be composed of a remarkably large number of distinctions and relations. Of course, our experience of space, which motivated the characterization of extendedness, is (at least) 2D-extended, rather than 1D-extended. Furthermore, its neural substrate is likely constituted by 2D-grids, rather than 1D grids. Nevertheless, the organizational principles that make a cause-effect structure extended generalize from 1D to 2D substrates, because they are determined by the near-neighbor arrangement of the connectivity. This point is illustrated in
Figure 12.
Figure 12A shows a 2D, planar ‘hex’ grid, in which each unit is connected to itself and to six neighbors arranged according to the vertices of a hexagon. Weights and activation rules are similar to the line network of
Figure 2, with parameters adjusted to account for the increase number of connections. Specifically, the lateral connections are weaker, with
w = 0.0625; the Naka-Rushton exponent is shallower, with
n = 3; and the threshold is higher, with
z = 0.4125. As in the 1D case, every contiguous patch of the 2D grid specifies a causal distinction, three of which are illustrated in
Figure 12B. As with the 1D grid, each distinction specified by the 2D grid specifies a cause and effect over a similar subset of units. Furthermore, the distinctions specified by the 2D grid are related in a way that satisfies extendedness (connection, fusion, inclusion) in a way similar to the 1D grid (
Figure 12C).
The difference between the cause-effect structures specified by 1D and 2D grids resides instead in the dimensionality of extendedness.
Appendix A Figure A1 shows a
refinement of a distinction as a recursive decomposition of a ‘top’ distinction, based on the three relations that characterize extendedness. A decomposition yielding a refinement proceeds through fusion-down relations (starting with a distinction, and then finding two distinctions that it fuses), with the requirement that the smallest distinctions included by the ‘top’ distinction are conserved throughout the decomposition (analogous to the notion of ‘open cover’ from topology; see
Appendix C). In the 1D case, every refinement is such that any of its distinctions is always related to another by a 2nd-order connection relation; furthermore, there must be at least one refinement with no connection relations of order >2. In the 2D case, every refinement is such that any of its distinctions is always related to
two others by a 3nd-order connection relation; furthermore, there must be at least one refinement with no connection relations of order > 3. The dimensionality of extendedness, corresponding to the prescribed order of the connection relation minus 1, is a close analogue of the Lebesgue covering dimension of classical topology, as described in
Appendix C.
4. Discussion
We have employed the tools of integrated information theory (IIT) to show that basic phenomenal properties of spatial experiences—what makes space feel the way it does—can be accounted for, in a principled manner, by physical properties of a grid-like substrate, namely by the cause-effect structure it specifies. The one-to-one correspondence between phenomenal and physical properties outlined above represents a first attempt to deploy the theory to account for the quality of experience. Previous theoretical work focused primarily on the general requirements for a physical substrate of consciousness [
6,
7,
20] and on the grain of its constituent units [
20,
21]. Complementary empirical work assessed the prediction that the breakdown of consciousness should be associated with a breakdown of the brain’s capacity for integrated information [
22,
23].
As a first test case, we chose the phenomenology of space because spatial experiences are pervasive and more penetrable by introspection than other aspects of consciousness. Moreover, the physical substrate of spatial experience may be comparatively easy to characterize in neural terms. Below we briefly consider some of the difficulties that stand in the way of a proper appreciation of a scientific account of spatial qualia; the proposed correspondence between the phenomenal properties of spatial experiences and physical properties of grid-like substrates, as given by the cause-effect structures they specify; the evidence that grids in the brain may constitute the substrate for spatial experience; some ensuing predictions; and the inadequacy of approaches that cannot account for the way spatial experience feels.
4.1. The Problem of Spatial Qualia
The account of spatial experience investigated in this paper must contend with deep-seated assumptions about the nature of both the phenomenal and the physical. A first problem has to do with spatial experience itself. Much work has been devoted to understanding how external physical space—the space ‘out there’—is represented in the brain in a way that accounts for spatial functions and behaviors (see Note 6 in
Appendix B). The way space is experienced within consciousness has received much less thought (see Note 7 in
Appendix B). However, it is essential to realize that the subjective feeling of extendedness—what it is like to experience the vast canvas of the sky—is just is as qualitative and in need of explanation as that of color or pain. But it is easier to tackle, because of our ability to penetrate introspectively some aspects of the structure of spatial experience, an ability we mostly lack for color or pain (see Note 8 in
Appendix B).
Second, one must realize that there is much more than meets the eye to a spatial experience, even a seemingly ‘simple’ one. Consider the experience of a blank canvas. The two words ‘blank canvas’ seem sufficient to convey the content of the experience to other human beings. However, this brevity in communication is only possible because it presupposes that other humans already know what space feels like. Things change if one is to characterize what an experience of extendedness feels like without taking space as given. To do so, one needs to identify the phenomenal components that make a canvas feel extended. As suggested here, these components are a large number of distinctions, corresponding to experienced spots; and an immense number the relations that bind them into a single phenomenal structure according to connection, fusion, and inclusion, corresponding to the feeling of extendedness. Phenomenal regions, locations, sizes, boundaries, and distances can then be described as sub-structures within this overall organization of distinctions and relations.
Third, one must realize that, to account in physical terms for
spatial experience as such, it is not enough to account for how the brain represents external space and performs spatial functions. Instead, one should strive to provide a one-to-one correspondence between the phenomenal distinctions and relations that compose the experience and the causal distinctions and relations that compose the cause-effect structure specified by a physical substrate (see Note 9 in
Appendix B). Otherwise, the structure of experience remains completely unexplained—associated to its physical substrate in the brain in a way that seems utterly mysterious as well as arbitrary.
Fourth, one must realize that there is much more than meets the eye (and the hand) to a physical substrate. We typically think of a physical substrate, say a neural network, as consisting of nothing but neurons and their connections. By observing and manipulating the units of the network we can understand how it does what it does and ultimately predict its behavior. However, as illustrated here with a small grid of binary units, to properly characterize the cause-effect powers of a substrate one must unfold its cause-effect structure in full, making explicit all the causal distinctions and relations it specifies. Only then can one attempt to establish a correspondence between what exists in phenomenal and physical terms.
4.2. The Causal Properties of Grid-Like Physical Substrates and Their Correspondence to the Phenomenal Properties of Spatial Experiences
As stated in the Introduction, according to integrated information theory every experience has five essential properties: intrinsicality (existing for the subject of experience); composition (being structured by phenomenal distinctions and their relations); information (being the specific way it is); integration (being irreducible); and exclusion (being definite). Spatial experiences satisfy these properties and appear to add further properties that make them characteristically spatial (
Figure 1A). To recapitulate, the canvas of space, even in the absence of any object, is composed of a vast number of distinctions (spots,
Figure 1B) that are bound to each other by characteristic relations (extendedness,
Figure 1C). Specifically, one can determine introspectively that every spot within the canvas overlaps with itself; it connects to some other spot and is the connection of two other spots; it fuses with and is the fusion of other spots; and it includes (down) or is included (up) by some other spot. The only exceptions are the total spot, which only extends down to other spots, and the points, which only extend up to other spots. Other phenomenal features of spatial experience can be thought of as deriving from the fundamental property of extendedness (
Figure 1D): the region of space picked out by a spot, its location in space, its size, boundary, and distance from other spots. Finally, one can experience regions of space that stand out from the rest of space due to local inhomogeneities, or because they are highlighted by attention.
Integrated information theory then claims that every property of an experience must be accounted for by a property of the cause-effect structure specified by a physical substrate in a particular state. What kind of physical substrate could specify a cause-effect structure that can account not only for the properties that are true of every conceivable experience (intrinsicality, composition, information, integration, and exclusion), but also for the properties that make an experience characteristically spatial? After illustrating how the tools of the theory can be employed to fully unfold the cause-effect structures specified by a simple substrate, we analyzed the cause-effect structure specified by a grid-like substrate, primarily a small 1D grid. The Results section indicates that the cause-effect structure specified by the grid, but not by a random network, can in principle account for many properties of spatial experiences.
As shown in
Figure 6, the cause-effect structure specified by a 1D grid is composed of a large number of causal distinctions and a very large number of relations that bind them in a characteristic way. In the case of the grid, the existing distinctions (those that are maximally irreducible) specify causes and effects that overlap over individual units (1st-order distinctions); over pairs of adjacent or nearly adjacent units (2nd-order), over triplets of adjacent or nearly adjacent units (3rd-order); and so on, up to a highest-order distinction that specifies a symmetric cause and effect over all the units of the grid. As shown in
Figure 12, the organization of distinctions according to adjacency also applies to a 2D grid. Note that, for each distinction specified by a grid, the cause overlaps with the effect, yielding a 1st-order complete relation - a self-relation characterized by reflexivity.
The adjacency among units is apparent to an external observer who is already endowed with the ability to recognize this kind of ordering. However, from the intrinsic perspective of the system itself, the ordering must be established by the intrinsic organization of the causal relations among the distinctions specified by its mechanisms. As shown here, most distinctions specified by the grid are bound to other distinctions by causal relations that conform to extendedness (
Figure 13): each distinction connects to some other distinction that overlaps it partially and symmetrically; it likewise fuses with or is the fusion of other overlapping distinctions; and it includes or is included by other distinctions. The only exceptions are the total distinction that only extends down to other distinctions, and the point distinctions that only extends up to other distinctions. Altogether, the extendedness relations yield a partial ordering of distinctions that corresponds precisely to the partial ordering of spots in spatial experience. Again, the relations that characterize extendedness also apply to the cause-effect structure specified by a 2D grid, with the difference that distinctions extend in 2 dimensions, rather than 1 dimension, corresponding to a Lebesgue dimension of 3 and 2, respectively (
Appendix C).
Other phenomenal properties of spatial experience that are derivable from extendedness find a correspondent in the cause-effect structure specified by the grid: the region of space picked out by a spot corresponds to the set of all distinctions fully included by a given distinction (its subtext); the location of a spot to the set of all distinctions that fully include a given distinction (its supertext); the size of a spot to the number of distinctions fully included by a given distinction; the boundary of a spot to the set of smallest distinctions that are connected to a given distinction; the distance between any two spots as the smallest distinction to which two distinctions extend (up) (see Note 10 in
Appendix B).
Finally, local inhomogeneities that emboss the canvas of phenomenal space, such as stars in the night sky, can be accounted for by local inhomogeneities in the cause-effect structure. Attentional highlighting, which similarly makes some spots stand out from the rest of space, can be accounted for by the selective enhancement of some distinctions and relations.
We end this section with an example that highlights, in a nutshell, some minimal requirements that a cause-effect structure must satisfy to account for experiencing space, again in a simple 1D case (
Figure 14).
Figure 14A–C illustrates reduced substrates whose cause-effect structures lack critical ingredients. For instance, if only the bottom-order cause-effects were specified (
Figure 14A), it would not be possible to experience them as composing a larger distinction, hence none of them could feel extended (in fact, in this case they would not even be integrated). If only the top-order cause-effect were specified (
Figure 14B), it would not be possible to experience that phenomenal distinction as composed of finer distinctions, hence it could not feel extended but at most as a single undifferentiated ‘lump’. If both the top- and bottom-order cause-effects were specified, but no purviews and relations in between, the bottom-order purviews would be related to the top one, but they would not be ordered with respect to each other, hence the structure could not feel spatial either (
Figure 14C) (see Note 11 in
Appendix B). In short, experiencing the extendedness that characterizes space requires a substrate that specifies a large number of causal distinctions and relations that bind them in an appropriate order, which corresponds to extendedness (
Figure 14D). A grid offers exactly this kind of substrate. Accordingly, we called the cause-effect structure specified by a grid-like substrate an
extension.
4.3. Some Outstanding Issues
At this stage, we have not explicitly addressed several additional properties associated with phenomenal space, beginning with the phenomenal experience of depth and whether spatial experience qualifies as 2D, 3D, or somewhere in between (see Note 12 in
Appendix B). We also did not address how the feeling of a perspectival ‘center’ of space [
24] might be specified. Apart from some asymmetries due to border effects (
Figure 4), a natural center may be provided by grids specifying body space, which would be heavily bound by relations to the middle of visual space, and by grids responsible for initiating movements near the body midline. We also did not consider how causal distinctions and relations specified by units arranged hierarchically, in an inverted tree-like fashion, can be bound with those specified by grid-like areas, corresponding to the phenomenal binding of objects in space. Nor have we considered the possible role of units arranged into local cliques at every position in grid-like areas in specifying qualities such as color, under the assumption that color, too, can be accounted for in structural terms.
On the other hand, the results presented here suggest further correspondences between properties of phenomenal space and properties of cause-effect structures specified by grids. Thus, just as nearby spots are phenomenally similar with respect to their region, location, and distances within the space, nearby sub-structures are similar with respect to their subtext and supertext. Furthermore, just as the overall structure of experienced space is largely stable regardless of local inhomogeneities such as stars, edges, objects and so on, the cause-effect structure specified by a grid is largely stable regardless of local inhomogeneities triggered by changes in the state of the grid’s units or by increased or decreased salience associated with attentional highlighting. Finally, we have shown that, just like experienced space does not have a boundary, in the sense that there is no further space exterior to it [
25], the cause-effect structure specified by a grid also has no exterior and therefore no boundary at its ‘edge’.
We have also shown that this spatial cause-effect structure, characterized by extendedness, is specified by grid-like substrates (
Figure 8A) but not by other kinds of substrates, such as ones with units connected at random (
Figure 8B). However, a general characterization of the relationship between the organization of substrates and their unfolded cause-effect structure, and of the features of lattice-like substrates that allow them to specify cause-effect structures of a spatial kind, remains beyond the scope of this paper.
4.4. Introspection: An Indispensable but Imperfect Tool to Bootstrap a Physical Account of Phenomenal Properties
Because the structure of experienced space is at least partly penetrable, we can employ introspection to attend any spot and to characterize the fundamental properties that make it feel extended—through reflexivity, connection, fusion, and inclusion with other spots—as well as derived properties such as the region of space it occupies, its location within the overall canvas, its size, boundary, and distance from other spots. Doing so allows us to assess the proposed correspondence between the phenomenal structure of space and the cause-effect structure specified by a grid. To the extent that the correspondence can be considered as validated, it is reasonable to infer that the fabric of space as phenomenal extension remains largely the same when we are not introspecting and attending specific spots: every spot is ‘there’ where it belongs—at its particular location and distance from every other spot—right in front of our eyes, without any effort on our part. In accordance with this inference, we have shown here that the cause-effect structure specified by a grid is an extension regardless of the presence of inhomogeneities or attentional highlights.
While introspection is an essential tool to validate the proposed correspondence between phenomenal and physical properties, it comes with many limitations. Indeed, once a correspondence is tentatively established, an analysis of the cause-effect structure specified by a substrate can reveal features that are typically not available to introspection. For example, it may be nearly impossible to penetrate through introspection down to the level of the individual distinctions or relations that are assumed to compose all of experience. As illustrated here, attention can be simulated by increasing the excitability of a subset of units, as could be done by back-projections from higher-level to lower-level, topographically organized cortical areas. Doing so, however, highlights not just a single distinction, but a compound distinction and an associated compound context of relations (
Figure 13) (see Note 13 in
Appendix B). Thus the correspondence between phenomenal and causal properties can only be validated coarsely through introspection—at the level of compound distinctions and contexts. That such a correspondence may hold all the way down to individual distinctions and relations is therefore an inference—albeit an inference from the best explanation.
Another limitation of introspection has to do with our inability to divest our experience of the phenomenal properties under study—in the present case those of spatial experiences—of extraneous phenomenal contents. As was argued in the Introduction, ideally we would like to isolate those properties of experience that make it spatial, abstracting away from non-spatial properties. For example, within visual space, we can reason that the canvas could be white or black, red or green, the inhomogeneities dark over a light background, or the other way around, yet its spatial features remain largely the same, regardless of its local qualities. Similarly, we can try and attend to a spot as a purely spatial distinction, as if we did not have the concept of ‘spot’ in our mind, not to mention the more general concept of ‘visual’. However, it is impossible for us to truly experience space without seeing its color, or without seeing a spot as an instance of the concept ‘spot’. The very richness of distinctions and relations that compose spatial experience suggests that the number of other distinctions and relations that compose an experience, even when merely introspecting empty space, must be even larger, and cannot be prevented from contributing to it, making the isolation of purely spatial properties a non-trivial exercise.
4.5. Some Points of Contact with Mereology and Topology
It is worth briefly considering how the present approach relates to classic disciplines that study abstract properties of parts and wholes (mereology), abstract properties of space (geometry and topology), or both (mereotopology, [
26]), notably in their discrete, atomic version [
27]. Because the development of these disciplines is necessarily grounded in our own phenomenology, especially the phenomenology of spatial experience, it is not surprising that there should be many points of contact. For example, the present approach shows that the causal relations between two causal distinctions A and B can be characterized as follows: A’s cause-effect is included (up) by B’s; B’s cause-effect includes (down) A’s; A’s cause-effect includes B’s and B’s cause-effect includes A’s; A’s cause-effect partially overlaps B’s; and A’s cause-effect is not related to B’s. Similarly, a set of five jointly exhaustive and pairwise disjoint relations characterize mereology [
27], namely: A is a proper part of B (corresponding to inclusion down as discussed here); B contains A as a proper part (inclusion up); A coincides with B (mutual inclusion); A partially overlaps B (connection); and A is disjoint from B (no relation). There are also points of contact with geometry and topology, and more specifically with discrete mereotopology [
27]. For example, extendedness as defined here shares some aspects with the definition of topological spaces and with closure operations. Moreover, notions such as regions, boundaries, distances, and so on, are defined in ways analogous to discrete mereotopology. Finally, a case could be made that fundamental set-theoretic notions such as intersection and union may also find their origin in fundamental properties of spatial experience such as connection and fusion.
Nevertheless, there are also some key differences between the present approach and that of these abstract disciplines. An obvious difference is that here a ‘part’, taken as a sub-structure, is composed of
both distinctions
and the relations that bind them in a particular way. Classic extensional mereology, instead, ignores relations. The most important difference, however, is that all the ‘parts’ considered here are required to
exist: in phenomenal terms, they are required to exist as components of an experience; in physical terms, they are required to exist as sub-structures of a cause-effect structure. As an example, among all possible distinctions and relations, only those having maximally irreducible cause-effect power exist in a causal, intrinsic sense, while those that are reducible do not (
Figure 4). In classic extensional mereology, by contrast, all possible parts are on equal footing—a principle called unrestricted composition. With respect to space, the fundamental relational properties of spatial experience considered here—reflexivity and extendedness, comprising connection, fusion, and inclusion—as well as derived properties such as regions, locations, sizes, boundaries, distances, inhomogeneities, and highlights, can be accounted for systematically in terms of intrinsic causal properties of the cause-effect structure specified by a grid, without any abstract, extrinsic ingredient (see Note 14 in
Appendix B). By contrast, in topology and mereotopology similar notions are defined abstractly and extrinsically, rather than causally and intrinsically (see Note 15 in
Appendix B).
4.6. Grids in the Brain as a Substrate for Spatial Experience
The proposal that cause-effect structures specified by grid-like networks can account for many key features of spatial experiences leads naturally to the hypothesis that the neural substrate of spatial consciousness might be provided by grid-like networks in our brain. Many areas of the cerebral cortex, especially in its posterior regions, are organized topographically, meaning that nearby units within each area show similar response properties with respect to sensory stimuli [
28]. Systematic variations of stimulus parameters, such as the position of visual stimuli in external space, typically map ‘topographically’ onto systematic variations of response properties on the cortical surface [
29,
30,
31]. Areas dealing with non-visual modalities, such as touch, are also organized like maps—for example, primary somatosensory cortex maps bodily locations in an orderly way [
28].
Within each area, units sharing response properties are also preferentially connected. For example, the anatomical connectivity of primary visual cortex is such that neurons that are close to each other are strongly connected, whereas neurons that are far away may not be connected at all [
32]. Similar arrangements have been described for areas higher up in the visual hierarchy, as well as for sensory areas in non-visual modalities. The converging feedforward/diverging feedback connectivity between hierarchically organized grid-like cortical areas is also topographically ordered, suggesting that much of posterior cortex may be considered as a stack of grids, where each node has both lateral intra-areal and feedforward/feedback inter-areal connections to neighboring nodes [
33,
34] (see Note 16 in
Appendix B).
Altogether, a rough calculation indicates that topographically organized areas may make up more than one third of the cerebral cortex of humans, and even more in rodents because of the predominance of sensory cortices. It should be emphasized, however, that not all topographically mapped areas are necessarily connected in a grid-like manner; that is, maps are not necessarily grids. Thus, thalamic nuclei that are topographically organized in their responses to sensory stimuli and provide topographically mapped reciprocal connections to cortical areas are not grid-like, as they lack lateral connections among relay neurons [
35]. Conversely, grid-like organization and topographic mappings are found in brain regions outside of the thalamocortical system, such as the superior colliculus [
36].
Most important for the present purposes, grid-like cortical areas appear to be directly involved in experiencing space. For example, broad unilateral lesions of visual cortical areas produce contralateral blindness of which patients are typically not aware (hemianopia, [
37,
38]). From their intrinsic perspective, one side of visual space ceases to exist altogether—it is simply ‘not there’. Indeed, after unilateral resection of the occipital lobe, the extent of imagined space shrinks (‘how large is an elephant’, [
39]). Split-brain patients, speaking through their left hemisphere, are also unaware of the left side of the visual field [
40]. Even an indirect deactivation or disconnection of grid-like visual cortices may lead to the disappearance of one side of space, as is the case in hemineglect [
41,
42]. Again, patients are typically not aware of lacking a portion of space and they may only realize their deficit indirectly, because they bump into objects or are told by others. In hemineglect, too, the extent of imagined space shrinks [
43]. If a smaller portion of posterior cortex is lesioned, patients have scotomas (local blindness) for the corresponding portion of space. In this case, too, the blind region does not look dark or empty, but is simply not seen [
38]. This is unlike the case of artificially-induced scotomas that leave visual cortex unchanged and the scotomatous region spatially intact and ‘filled-in’ [
44], see also Note 17 in
Appendix B).
Stimulation and recording studies provide evidence complementary to lesions studies. Stimulation experiments, whether through intracranial electrodes or through magnetic pulses applied transcranially, show that direct activation of grid-like areas in both primary visual cortex and parietal cortex can produce phosphenes that are localized in experienced space consistent with their topographic organization [
45]. Recording studies using sensory stimuli have demonstrated a systematic correspondence between where activations occur in visual cortical areas (such as V1–V2 and V5) and where certain features are experienced in subjective 2D space. This is true not only when we look at a screen, but also when we imagine or dream objects as located at particular positions in visual space [
46,
47]. Indeed, there are now clinical trials for direct visual cortical stimulation to produce phosphenes in blind patients. In summary, there is a systematic correspondence between positions in the external world, positions in grid-like cortical maps, and locations in experienced space. Paradoxically, it is the very straightforwardness of this correspondence that may conceal the difficulty of accounting for why space feels the way it does (see Note 18 in
Appendix B).
4.7. Some Tests and Predictions
If phenomenal spaces correspond to cause-effect structures specified by cortical grid-like substrates, then changes in such substrates should lead to predictable changes in spatial experience. An interesting question is whether phenomenal features of certain scotomas, such as filling in, ‘warping’, or ‘sewing’ of the surrounding space, can be predicted from features of the cause-effect structure specified by cortical grids, depending on the underlying cause. Counterintuitive predictions are especially important. For example, in the view presented here, a cortical grid should support the experience of space whether it is active or inactive, as long as it is in working order—that is, an
inactive neuron is fundamentally different from an
inactivated neuron, because the former still has causal powers in the system [
7]. Thus, the dark sky or a blank screen should still be experienced as spatially extended, even though activity in cortical grids may be at background levels. Background activity in cortical grids should support a pure experience of space also in the absence of perceived objects and while disconnected from external inputs, as can be achieved during certain dreams [
48] or meditation states [
49]. A related prediction is that changes in the strength of lateral connections in a grid-like area should be associated with changes in spatial experience, even if neural activity did not change [
7]. To begin testing this prediction experimentally, we sought to induce local changes in connection strength by repeatedly presenting synchronous point-like stimuli at two cortical positions linked by lateral connections [
50]. After training, point-like stimuli presented at untrained positions further apart appeared closer than before. This result is consistent with a contraction of experienced space due to changes in connection strength rather than to changes in neural activity. Other findings potentially consistent with this interpretation have also been reported [
51]. Lateral connections in cortical grids such as V1 are usually thought to serve ancillary functions, such as modulating ‘information-processing’ carried out by feed-forward connections [
52,
53,
54]. According to the present proposal, instead, the lateral connections that constitute grid-like networks are responsible for experiencing space
tout court, whether or not they carry neural activity. Thus, if lateral synaptic connections were inactivated without inactivating the associated pre- or post-synaptic neurons, the experience of space would cease, irrespective of any activity along feedforward connections. A complementary prediction is that, in principle, properly extending a cortical grid with additional neural hardware, such as implanted cortical organoids, should extend experienced space.
The proposal that grid-like areas, primarily located in posterior cortex, specify cause-effect structures that correspond in a one-to-one manner to the experience of space also provides a novel angle on long-standing controversies about the nature of phenomenal space. Some have argued that it has largely Euclidean properties [
55], others a spherical geometry [
56], others hyperbolic [
57], yet others emphasize how its geometrical properties vary with eccentricity, the presence of objects, attention, and even task setting [
58,
59]. If the structure of experienced space corresponds to the cause-effect structure specified by cortical grids, as proposed here, such complexity would be expected. This is because the precise features of the experience would depend on the precise pattern of connections, which varies with eccentricity and other factors, as well as on changes in connection strength associated with the presence of objects, attentional modulation, and on other idiosyncratic influences, such as early visual experience of individual subjects (see Note 19 in
Appendix B).
In principle, this proposal should also lead to testable predictions concerning other features of phenomenal space: the way space extends across the midline thanks to callosal connections; the way higher-level grid-like areas contribute to the experience of space thanks to convergent/divergent, topographically mapped connections to lower-level areas, as well as to the binding of objects to space; the binding of experienced ‘retinotopic’ space with experienced ‘body space’ (where visual space is placed with respect to our body), likely mediated by parietal areas; and with experienced ‘environmental space’ (where the surrounding environment is placed with respect to our body and visual space), possibly mediated by retrosplenial cortex [
60].
4.8. Can Other Approaches Account for Spatial Experience?
The one-to-one correspondence proposed here, between properties of spatial experience and properties of the cause-effect structure specified by a grid-like substrate, means that all the phenomenal distinctions and relations that exist in our mind, and the sub-structures they compose, must exist as causal distinctions, relations, and sub-structures specified by grid-like substrates in our brain. Crucially, the correspondence is not with the physical substrate as such—the set of nerve cells one can operationally observe and manipulate—but with the cause-effect structure it specifies: its cause-effect powers, properly unfolded.
Because space is usually taken for granted, it is not easy to pinpoint explicit alternative accounts with which to compare the present one (see Note 20 in
Appendix B). Nevertheless, it may be instructive to consider whether or not the properties of spatial experience could be accounted for by appealing to representations of the environment, behaviors and functional capabilities, neural states, or neural substrates as such.
Consider representations of the environment first. One might envision that the spatial structure of the external world is the referent of spatial experience, hence topographically mapped cortical areas merely need to ‘represent’ the environment, as sampled through stimulus space, to inherit its spatial structure. However, leaving aside the nature of external space itself, it is not clear how the structure of phenomenal space, as experienced from the intrinsic perspective of our conscious mind, would be inherited from something extrinsic to it. This problem is especially obvious for spatial experiences that occur when we are disconnected from the environment, as when dreaming of the starry sky. If the experience feels spatial, it must feel so because it actually has spatial properties intrinsically, when it is dreamt, and not by inheriting spatial properties from an external environment to which the brain was exposed in the past. Of course, in the course of evolution, development, and learning, causal properties of the environment do mold the neural substrate of spatial experience (see Note 21 in
Appendix B), but at issue is what corresponds to the structure of experience here and now, not how it came about. It should also be clear that stimuli from the environment are not spatially organized in themselves: there is no extendedness, no region or location, no size, boundary or distance in a sensory stimulus unless one presupposes that space already exists intrinsically in the mind of an observer (see Note 22 in
Appendix B).
If an appeal to a representation of the environment tries to shift the burden to the input side—to upstream causes—an appeal to spatial behaviors and functions tries to shift it to the output side—to downstream effects. We can obviously report where something is, whether a larger spot includes a smaller spot or not, whether two stars are close or far, and so on. In functional terms, if one can account for all our spatial behaviors and functions by a series of ‘processing’ steps along topographically mapped regions of our brain, then nothing else would seem to need explaining. Such a functionalist approach, if it does not outright deny the reality of one’s experience, at best treats it as an ‘illusion’ [
61]. Even so, it certainly fails to provide a one-to-one account for the structural features that make the ‘illusion’ feel the particular way it does—in the present case, that it feels extended. In other words, it has nothing to say about the countless distinctions and relations that compose the experience of extendedness as it exists phenomenally, and focuses exclusively on the few functions that can be performed one at a time. Indeed, the dissociation between the richness of an experience—say, experiencing the starry sky or even a blank canvas—and the poverty of behavioral reports—say, reporting the position of a stimulus in the visual field—can lead to a paradoxical denial of the primary evidence of our own consciousness: rather than admit that the richness of what we experience cannot be explained by the poverty of what we do, some scientists insist that we cannot possibly experience so much given that we can report so little [
62]. Note also that, in strictly functional terms, there would be no fundamental difference between an embodied computer program simulating all our spatial behaviors and functions (functional equivalence) and the humans it is simulating, who actually experience space and don’t just behave as if they did (no phenomenal equivalence, Findlay, Marshall, et al., unpublished).
Alternatively, one could maintain that properties of experienced space are properties of certain neural states, irrespective of what those states may represent or of what functional consequences they might have. And indeed, it is possible to ‘decode’ spatial properties from patterns of neural activity in topographically organized cortical areas, whether stimuli are experienced left or right, close or far, and so on, with increasing reliability and precision [
63]. However, leaving aside that one can decode spatial properties just as well from the retina and, for that matter, from the sensor of a digital camera, a neural state by itself cannot provide a one-to-one correspondence—an isomorphism—with the distinctions and relations that compose extended spots, regions, locations, sizes, boundaries, distances, and so on (see Note 23 in
Appendix B). When we decode and interpret a neural activity pattern in a topographically mapped cortical area as spatially meaningful, it is because we presuppose a spatial organization, but that organization is already in our mind—the mind of the beholder—not in the activity pattern as such (see Note 24 in
Appendix B). Without a causal context, a neural state is just as meaningless as an array of 0s and 1s in a computer chip (see Note 25 in
Appendix B).
Finally, one could propose that the properties of experienced space might be associated not with a neural state, but with a neural substrate—not just a pattern of neural activity, but also the underlying connectivity as it evolved by exposure to the environment. For example, the multiscale receptive field organization along the cortical hierarchy may seem well-suited to implementing a partial ordering [
64,
65]. Thus, if two neural units are neighbors in a grid-like network, their neighborhood could be ‘encoded’ by a unit higher-up in the visual hierarchy to which their outputs converge, and so on recursively across multiple scales. From a functional perspective, the set of multiscale receptive fields orders the units in the first level such that output units at higher levels of the hierarchy encode contiguous regions of visual space, and their own outputs can be combined to guide spatial behaviors. Along similar lines, one could propose that the lateral connections among units in grid-like areas might ‘encode’ neighborhood relations. Thus, if two stars look close together, one would find that their point images in the cortex are separated by few synaptic steps, but by many synaptic steps if they look far apart. However, neither the hierarchical organization of receptive fields, nor a grid-like connectivity as such, can provide a one-to-one correspondence with the structure of spatial experience. In the case of the hierarchy, for instance, the fact that unit A at the lowest level is 2 units away from C and 6 units away from G is not directly ‘encoded’ by any unit at the next level up. Similarly, there are no neural units that could ‘encode’ every distance relation present in phenomenology (see Note 26 in
Appendix B). The same applies to inclusion relations corresponding to phenomenal regions and locations (see Note 27 in
Appendix B).
4.9. The Extraordinary Richness of Space and Its Unfolded Physical Correspondent
In this paper, the proposal that the properties of spatial phenomenology correspond one-to-one to the properties of cause-effect structures specified by grid-like cortical substrates could only be formulated in a bare-bones, rudimentary manner (see Note 28 in
Appendix B). Nevertheless, if this account is pointing in the right direction, it should make us reconsider the extraordinary richness of both phenomenal experience and its physical correspondent. We often take space for granted because it seems easy to describe: what could be simpler than a blank, empty canvas extending in all directions? But as we have tried to illustrate, to experience empty space as such requires the existence of a multitude of distinctions and relations, composing a multitude of extended spots, regions, locations, and distances (see Note 29 in
Appendix B). Cortical grids, the proposed substrate of spatial experiences, also seem remarkably easy to describe—a 2D array of units linked by near-neighbor connections. But when a simple grid is unfolded to reveal its cause-effect powers—all the causal distinctions and relations it supports—the richness of the cause-effect structure it specifies boggles the mind (see Note 30 in
Appendix B). And so it should be, because the richness of spatial experience should be matched one-to-one by the richness of its physical correspondent (see Note 31 in
Appendix B). Usually, we don’t stop in amazement at the sheer numerosity of the phenomenal distinctions and relations that exist, ‘right in front of our eyes’, when we look at the night sky. Perhaps, on occasion, we should.