Next Article in Journal
Improving the Scalability of the Magnitude-Based Deceptive Path-Planning Using Subgoal Graphs
Next Article in Special Issue
Non-Monogamy of Spatio-Temporal Correlations and the Black Hole Information Loss Paradox
Previous Article in Journal
Electromagnetically Induced Transparency in Media with Rydberg Excitons 2: Cross-Kerr Modulation
 
 
Font Type:
Arial Georgia Verdana
Font Size:
Aa Aa Aa
Line Spacing:
Column Width:
Background:
Article

A Note on the Hierarchy of Quantum Measurement Incompatibilities

1
School of Mathematical Sciences, Qufu Normal University, Qufu 273165, China
2
School of Mathematical Sciences, Capital Normal University, Beijing 100048, China
3
Max Planck Institute for Mathematics in the Sciences, 04103 Leipzig, Germany
*
Authors to whom correspondence should be addressed.
Entropy 2020, 22(2), 161; https://doi.org/10.3390/e22020161
Submission received: 12 January 2020 / Revised: 26 January 2020 / Accepted: 27 January 2020 / Published: 30 January 2020
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Quantum Entanglement)

Abstract

:
The quantum measurement incompatibility is a distinctive feature of quantum mechanics. We investigate the incompatibility of a set of general measurements and classify the incompatibility by the hierarchy of compatibilities of its subsets. By using the approach of adding noises to measurement operators, we present a complete classification of the incompatibility of a given measurement assemblage with n members. Detailed examples are given for the incompatibility of unbiased qubit measurements based on a semidefinite program.

1. Introduction

The incompatible measurements are one of the striking features in quantum physics, and can be traced back to Heisenberg’s uncertainty principle [1] and wave-particle duality [2,3]. There are observables like position and momentum, that are impossible to be exactly measured simultaneously, unless some amount of noise is added [4]. The existence of incompatible measurements [5,6,7] also implies the no-cloning theorem [8,9] and Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen (EPR) steering [10,11,12].
The incompatibility of quantum measurements is also known to be a powerful tool in many branches of quantum information theory [13,14,15,16,17,18,19]. As a resource for quantum information processing [20], quantum incompatibility has been the object of intense research [21,22,23,24,25,26,27,28,29,30,31,32,33,34,35,36,37,38]. In [39] Bell-like inequalities have been presented by using some partial compatible measurements.
Based on the investigation on the uncertainty relations of two measurements [15,16,17], the authors in [40] found that a triple measurement uncertainty relation deduced from uncertainty relations for two measurements is usually not tight. There exist genuinely incompatible triple measurements such that they are pairwise jointly measurable, as in the case of genuine tripartite entanglement or genuine nonlocal correlations. Based on statistical distance, Qin, et al. [41] formulated state-independent tight uncertainty relations, satisfied by three measurements, in terms of their triple joint measurability. Another way to quantify the joint measurability of a set of measurements is to add noise to the measurement operators, and numerically calculate the noise threshold for the measurements to be jointly measurable [21,25,26].
In this paper, similar to the quantum multipartite entanglement or non-locality, we classify the measurement incompatibility for a given set of measurements, and present a hierarchy of quantum measurement incompatibilities. We then study the transition between different types of incompatible measurements by using the semidefinite programm (SDP) [34]. We present a criterion to judge the incompatibility of a given multiple measurements. Detailed examples are given for unbiased qubit measurements.

2. Measurement Incompatibility Classification and Quantification

A general positive operator valued measure (POVM) is given by a collection of positive-semidefinite operators summing up to an identity. We consider a POVM with measurement operators { A a } a , { A a 0 , a A a = I } , where I stands for the identity operator. Given a state ρ , the probability of measurement outcome a is p ( a ) = tr A a ρ .
Given two POVMs, { A a } and { B b } , { A a } is called a coarsening of { B b } , or equivalently, { B b } is called a refinement of { A a } , if the former can be derived from the latter by data processing, A a = b p ( a | b ) B b , for every a, where p ( a | b ) 0 , and { p ( a | b ) } a is a probability distribution, for every b [35]. For a set of n POVMs, i.e., a POVM assemblage A = { { A a | x } a } x = 1 n , we say that the POVM assemblage is compatible (or jointly measurable) if and only if all the POVMs in the assemblage possess a common refinement. This common refinement is called the parent POVM [34]. Otherwise, A is incompatible.
The incompatibility of a POVM assemblage with n members implies that there does not exist a common refinement for all of the n measurements. However, some of the measurements of the assemblage may have a common refinement, that is, there might be some subassemblages which are jointly measurable. Obviously, if a subset of a POVM assemblage is incompatible, the whole assemblage is incompatible. However, the converse is not true. Therefore, it is of significance to characterize the measurement incompatibility of a POVM assemblage in a finer way, as in the separability classification in quantum entanglement [42,43]. To give a uniform description of the measurement incompatibility of a POVM assemblage with n measurements, we have the following classifications:
Given a POVM assemblage A = { { A a | x } a } x = 1 n and k n , we have
(1)
A is ( n , k ) -compatible, if all k-member subsets of A are compatible;
(2)
A is ( n , k ) -incompatible, if at least one k-member subset of A is incompatible;
(3)
A is ( n , k ) -strong incompatible, if all k-member subsets of A are incompatible;
(4)
A is ( n , k + 1 ) -genuinely incompatible, if A is ( n , k ) -compatible, and ( n , k + 1 ) -incompatible;
(5)
A is ( n , k + 1 ) -genuinely strong incompatible, if A is ( n , k ) -compatible, and ( n , k + 1 ) -strong incompatible.
From above classification, we have the following conclusions:
Proposition 1.
Given a set of POVMs A = { { A a | x } a } x = 1 n , we have
(1) 
A is compatible, if and only if, it is ( n , n ) -compatible;
(2) 
A is ( n , k + 1 ) -compatible implies that it is ( n , k ) -compatible;
(3) 
( n , k ) -strong incompatible is a special case of ( n , k ) -incompatible;
(4) 
( n , k ) -incompatible implies ( n , k + 1 ) -incompatible but not ( n , k + 1 ) -genuinely incompatible;
(5) 
( n , k + 1 ) -genuinely incompatible means that ( n , k + 1 ) -incompatible and ( n , k ) -compatible;
(6) 
( n , 2 ) -(strong) incompatible is equivalent to ( n , 2 ) -genuinely (strong) incompatible.
For a given POVM assemblage A with n members, an interesting problem is to judge if it is incompatible. If A is incompatible, we need to determine which kind of incompatibility it is. If A is ( n , k ) -incompatible or ( n , k ) -strong incompatible, it would become ( n , k ) -, ( n , k + 1 ) - or even ( n , n ) -compatible by adding more and more white noise.
Adding noise to a POVM assemblage A = { { A a | x } a } x is to mix each measurement operator in A with white noise, so as to get a new set of POVMs A η ,
A a | x η = η A a | x + ( 1 - η ) tr A a | x I d .
As { { tr A a | x I d } a } x is a compatible assemblage, A η will eventually become jointly measurable for sufficient small η . The critical parameter η * , at which the transition from incompatible to compatible occurs, is called the noise robustness of A , which is a meaningful incompatibility quantifier [21,25,26]. The bigger η * , the weaker incompatibility of A . A is compatible if and only if η * = 1 . It is generally formidably difficult to obtain the accurate value of η * . The estimation of the upper or lower bound of η * is an interesting problem. In [34] Designolle et al. gave an expression of η * by using SDP (2) and its strong dual (3),
η * = max η s . t . { A a | x η } compatible 0 η 1 ,
η * = min { X a | x } a , x 1 + tr a , x X a | x A a | x s . t . 1 + tr a , x X a | x A a | x 1 d a , x tr X a | x tr A a | x , x X j x | x 0 , j i , i = 1 , 2 , , n ,
where any { X a | x } a , x that satisfies the constraints in (3) can give rise to an upper bound of η * .
The critical parameter η * can be also used to characterize the transition from general ( n , n ) -incompatible to ( n , n ) -compatible, as well as from ( n , k ) -incompatible to ( n , k ) -compatible, or ( n , k ) -strong incompatible to ( n , k ) -incompatible. We denote η ( n , k ) * the critical parameter at which the transition from ( n , k ) -incompatible to ( n , k ) -compatible occurs. The η * given in (2) and (3) is simply η ( n , n ) * . If A is ( n , k ) -compatible, then η ( n , k ) * = 1 . Otherwise, η ( n , k ) * < 1 . Since ( n , k ) -incompatible implies the ( n , k + 1 ) -incompatible, we have η ( n , k ) * η ( n , k + 1 ) * .
Denote [ n ] = { 1 , 2 , , n } . Let α k represent an arbitrary subset of [ n ] with k numbers. Given any k-member subset of A , A α k = { { A a | x } a | x α k } . If A α k is ( k , k ) -incompatible, by using the same SDP (2) and SDP-dual (3) procedure, we can get the critical number η α k * , at which the transition from ( k , k ) -incompatible to ( k , k ) -compatible occurs for A α k η ,
η α k * = max η s . t . { A a | x η } x α k compatible 0 η 1 ,
η α k * = min 1 + tr x α k a X a | x A a | x s . t . 1 + tr x α k a X a | x A a | x 1 d x α k a tr X a | x tr A a | x , x α k X j x | x 0 , j i , i α k .
For any subset with k members A α k of A , A α k η is ( k , k ) -compatible if η η α k * , and ( k , k ) -incompatible if η > η α k * . Set
η ( n , k ) m i n = min α k η α k * , η ( n , k ) m a x = max α k η α k * .
We have η ( n , k ) * = η ( n , k ) m i n . η ( n , k ) m i n and η ( n , k ) m a x can identify all kinds of incompatibilities of a POVM assemblage. If η ( n , k ) m i n = η ( n , k ) m a x = 1 , namely, A α k is compatible for all α k , then A is ( n , k ) - compatible. If η ( n , k ) m i n < 1 and η ( n , k ) m a x = 1 , A is ( n , k ) -incompatible but not strong incompatible. If η ( n , k ) m a x < 1 , we conclude that A is ( n , k ) -strong incompatible. If η ( n , k + 1 ) m i n < 1 and η ( n , k ) m i n = 1 , then A is ( n , k + 1 ) -genuinely incompatible. If η ( n , k + 1 ) m a x < 1 and η ( n , k ) m i n = 1 , then A is ( n , k + 1 ) -genuinely strong incompatible. Therefore, we have the following theorem.
Theorem 1.
The numbers η ( n , k ) m i n and η ( n , k ) m a x , defined in (6), can classify all kinds of incompatibility of a POVM assemblage A = { { A a | x } a } x = 1 n for k = 2 , 3 , , n .
From another point of view, in the case of η ( n , k ) m i n < η ( n , k ) m a x 1 , A η is ( n , k ) -strong incompatible for η > η ( n , k ) m a x , because every A α k η is incompatible. A η is ( n , k ) -compatible for η η ( n , k ) m i n , and ( n , k ) -incompatible but not strong incompatible for η ( n , k ) m i n < η η ( n , k ) m a x . In this sense, we can say that η ( n , k ) m i n is the critical parameter for the transition from ( n , k ) -compatible to general ( n , k ) -incompatible. η ( n , k ) m a x is the one for the transition to ( n , k ) -strong incompatible.
It is clear that η ( n , k ) m i n η ( n , k + 1 ) m i n and η ( n , k ) m a x η ( n , k + 1 ) m a x . Nevertheless, the general relation between η ( n , k ) m i n and η ( n , k + 1 ) m a x is not clear. If η ( n , k + 1 ) m a x < η ( n , k ) m i n , then A η is ( n , k + 1 ) -genuinely strong incompatible for η ( n , k + 1 ) m a x < η η ( n , k ) m i n . But if η ( n , k + 1 ) m a x < η ( n , k ) m i n , A η is not ( n , k + 1 ) -genuinely strong incompatible for all η .
By considering “maximally incompatible” measurements, the authors in [44,45,46,47] discussed the projective measurements on mutually unbiased bases (MUBs), the bases regarded as “maximally noncommutative” and “complementary” [44]. MUBs play a central role in quantum information processing [48], and have been used in a wide range of applications [49,50,51,52,53,54].
In the following, we give examples of different kinds of incompatibility by using projective measurements on mutually unbiased bases in qubit systems. Given three mutually unbiased bases { { | ψ a | x } a = 1 2 } x = 1 3 ,
| ψ a | x | ψ b | y | 2 = 1 2 , x y , a , b = 1 , 2 ,
and
ψ a | x | ψ b | x = δ a b , x = 1 , 2 , 3 , a , b = 1 , 2 .
We consider the projective measurements given by these bases, A = { { A a | x = | ψ a | x ψ a | x | } a } x = 1 3 . Correspondingly, there exist three unit real 3-dimensional vectors m x , such that
{ A a | x = | ψ a | x ψ a | x | } a = 1 , 2 = A ± | x = I ± m x · σ 2 , x = 1 , 2 , 3 .
The mutual unbiases of { | ψ a | x } a , x = 1 , 2 , 3 , gives that m 1 , m 2 , and m 3 are mutually orthogonal. Adding noise to A a | x , we find A η = { A ± | x η = η A ± | x + ( 1 - η ) I 2 } x = 1 3 , namely,
A η = { A ± | x η = I ± η m x · σ 2 } x = 1 3 .
Using the results in [31,34,36], we have critical parameters η ( 3 , 2 ) * = η ( 3 , 2 ) m i n = η ( 3 , 2 ) m a x = 1 2 , η ( 3 , 3 ) * = 1 3 . Hence, if η 1 3 , then A η is ( 3 , 3 ) -compatible. If 1 3 < η 1 2 , then A η is ( 3 , 2 ) -compatible, but ( 3 , 3 ) -incompatible, i.e., ( 3 , 3 ) -genuinely incompatible. If η > 1 2 , then A η is ( 3 , 2 ) -strong incompatible.
On the other hand, we can add different white noise to different POVMs in A . We have new POVM assemblage as { A ± | x η x } x = 1 3 , η x [ 0 , 1 ] . Then A ± | x η x and A ± | y η y , with 1 x < y 3 , are compatible if η x 2 + η y 2 1 [29]. If η 1 = η 2 η > 1 2 and η 3 2 + η 2 1 , then { A ± | 1 η 1 , A ± | 2 η 2 } are incompatible, but A ± | x η x and A ± | 3 η 3 are compatible ( x = 1 , 2 ). Hence { A ± | 1 η 1 , A ± | 2 η 2 , A ± | 3 η 3 } is an example for ( 3 , 2 ) -incompatible but not ( 3 , 2 ) -strong incompatible.

3. Conclusions

We have investigated the measurement incompatibility of a general measurement assemblage. We have classified such quantum into ( n , k ) -compatible, ( n , k ) -incompatible and ( n , k ) -strong incompatible. By using the approach of mixing with noises, detailed examples are presented. Incompatibility and compatibility of measurements play profound roles not only in the fundamental research of quantum physics, but also in quantum information processing, raging from uncertainty relations to the detection of Bell nonlocality and device-independent certification of entanglement. Finer characterization of the incompatibility of measurement assemblages can give rise to better applications. Our results may highlight further researches on jointly measurability and applications of incompatible measurements in quantum information processing.

Author Contributions

Investigation, B.-Z.S.; Writing–review and editing, Z.-X.W., X.L.-J. and S.-M.F. All authors have read and agreed to the published version of the manuscript.

Funding

This work is supported by the NSF of China under Grant No. 11701320 and 11675113, Shandong provincial NSF of China Grant no. ZR2016AM04, Beijing Municipal Commission of Education under grant No. KZ201810028042, and Beijing Natural Science Foundation (Z190005).

Acknowledgments

B.-Z.S. gratefully acknowledges the hospitality of the Max-Planck Institute of Mathematics in the Sciences, Leipzig, Germany.

Conflicts of Interest

The authors declare no conflict of interest.

References

  1. Heisenberg, W. Über den anschaulichen Inhalt der quantentheoretischen Kinematik und Mechanik. Z. Phys. 1927, 43, 172. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  2. Englert, B.-G. Fringe visibility and which-way information: An inequality. Phys. Rev. Lett. 1996, 77, 2154. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  3. Coles, P.J.; Kaniewski, J.; Wehner, S. Equivalence of wave–particle duality to entropic uncertainty. Nat. Commun. 2014, 5, 1–8. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  4. Arthurs, E.; Kelly, J. BSTJ briefs: On the simultaneous measurement of a pair of conjugate observables. Bell Syst. Tech. J. 1965, 44, 725–729. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  5. Coles, P.J.; Berta, M.; Tomamichel, M.; Wehner, S. Entropic uncertainty relations and their applications. Rev. Mod. Phys. 2017, 89, 015002. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  6. Hirsch, F.; Quintino, M.T.; Brunner, N. Quantum measurement incompatibility does not imply Bell nonlocality. Phys. Rev. A 2018, 97, 012129. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  7. Styliaris, G.; Zanardi, P. Quantifying the incompatibility of quantum measurements relative to a basis. Phys. Rev. Lett. 2019, 123, 070401. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
  8. Wootters, W.K.; Zurek, W.H. A single quantum cannot be cloned. Nature 1982, 299, 802–803. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  9. Dieks, D. Comunication by EPR devices. Phys. Lett. A 1982, 92, 271. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  10. Quintino, M.T.; Vértesi, T.; Brunner, N. Joint measurability, einstein-podolsky-rosen steering, and bell nonlocality. Phys. Rev. Lett. 2014, 113, 160402. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  11. Uola, R.; Moroder, T.; Gühne, O. Joint measurability of generalized measurements implies classicality. Phys. Rev. Lett. 2014, 113, 160403. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
  12. Jones, S.J.; Wiseman, H.M.; Doherty, A.C. Entanglement, einstein-podolsky-rosen correlations, bell nonlocality, and steering. Phys. Rev. A 2007, 76, 052116. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  13. Heinosaari, T.; Miyadera, T.; Ziman, M. An invitation to quantum incompatibility. J. Phys. A Math. Theor. 2016, 49, 123001. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  14. Gühne, O. Characterizing entanglement via uncertainty relations. Phys. Rev. Lett. 2004, 92, 117903. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  15. Busch, P.; Lahti, P.; Werner, R.F. Colloquium: Quantum root-mean-square error and measurement uncertainty relations. Rev. Mod. Phys. 2014, 86, 1261. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  16. Busch, P.; Lahti, P.; Werner, R.F. Proof of Heisenberg’s error-disturbance relation. Phys. Rev. Lett. 2013, 111, 160405. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  17. Ma, W.; Ma, Z.; Wang, H.; Chen, Z.; Liu, Y.; Kong, F.; Li, Z.; Peng, X.; Shi, M.; Shi, F. Experimental test of Heisenberg’s measurement uncertainty relation based on statistical distances. Phys. Rev. Lett. 2016, 116, 160405. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  18. Wolf, M.M.; Perez-Garcia, D.; Fernandez, C. Measurements incompatible in quantum theory cannot be measured jointly in any other no-signaling theory. Phys. Rev. Lett. 2009, 103, 230402. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  19. Brunner, N.; Cavalcanti, D.; Pironio, S.; Scarani, V.; Wehner, S. Bell nonlocality. Rev. Mod. Phys. 2014, 86, 419. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  20. Heinosaari, T.; Kiukas, J.; Reitzner, D.; Schultz, J. Incompatibility breaking quantum channels. J. Phys. A Math. Theor. 2015, 48, 435301. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  21. Heinosaari, T.; Kiukas, J.; Reitzner, D. Noise robustness of the incompatibility of quantum measurements. Phys. Rev. A 2015, 92, 022115. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  22. Pusey, M.F. Verifying the quantumness of a channel with an untrusted device. J. Opt. Soc. Am. B 2015, 32, A56–A63. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  23. Skrzypczyk, P.; Navascués, M.; Cavalcanti, D. Quantifying einstein-podolsky-rosen steering. Phys. Rev. Lett. 2014, 112, 180404. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
  24. Uola, R.; Budroni, C.; Gühne, O.; Pellonpää, J.-P. One-to-one mapping between steering and joint measurability problems. Phys. Rev. Lett. 2015, 115, 230402. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  25. Cavalcanti, D.; Skrzypczyk, P. Quantitative relations between measurement incompatibility, quantum steering, and nonlocality. Phys. Rev. A 2016, 93, 052112. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  26. Cavalcanti, D.; Skrzypczyk, P. Quantum steering: A review with focus on semidefinite programming. Rep. Prog. Phys. 2016, 80, 024001. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  27. Busch, P.; Heinosaari, T. Approximate joint measurements of qubit observables. Quantum Inf. Comput. 2008, 8, 0797. [Google Scholar]
  28. Busch, P. Unsharp reality and joint measurements for spin observables. Phys. Rev. D 1986, 33, 2253. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  29. Yu, S.; Oh, C. Quantum contextuality and joint measurement of three observables of a qubit. arXiv 2013, arXiv:1312.6470. [Google Scholar]
  30. Liang, Y.-C.; Spekkens, R.W.; Wiseman, H.M. Specker’s parable of the overprotective seer: A road to contextuality, nonlocality and complementarity. Phys. Rep. 2011, 506, 1–39. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  31. Carmeli, C.; Heinosaari, T.; Toigo, A. Informationally complete joint measurements on finite quantum systems. Phys. Rev. A 2012, 85, 012109. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  32. Haapasalo, E. Robustness of incompatibility for quantum devices. J. Phys. A Math. Theor. 2015, 48, 255303. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  33. Kunjwal, R.; Heunen, C.; Fritz, T. Quantum realization of arbitrary joint measurability structures. Phys. Rev. A 2014, 89, 052126. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  34. Designolle, S.; Skrzypczyk, P.; Fröwis, F.; Brunner, N. Quantifying measurement incompatibility of mutually unbiased bases. Phys. Rev. Lett. 2019, 122, 050402. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  35. Zhu, H.; Hayashi, M.; Chen, L. Universal steering criteria. Phys. Rev. Lett. 2016, 116, 070403. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  36. Uola, R.; Luoma, K.; Moroder, T.; Heinosaari, T. Adaptive strategy for joint measurements. Phys. Rev. A 2016, 94, 022109. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  37. Heinosaari, T. A simple sufficient condition for the coexistence of quantum effects. J. Phys. A Math. Theor. 2013, 46, 152002. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  38. Zhu, H. Information complementarity: A new paradigm for decoding quantum incompatibility. Sci. Rep. 2015, 5, 1–12. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  39. Tassius, T.; Rafael, R.; Marcelo, T.C. Measurement compatibility in Bell nonlocality tests. Phys. Rev. A 2019, 99, 042120. [Google Scholar]
  40. Ma, W.; Chen, B.; Liu, Y.; Wang, M.; Ye, X.; Kong, F.; Shi, F.; Fei, S.-M.; Du, J. Experimental demonstration of uncertainty relations for the triple components of angular momentum. Phys. Rev. Lett. 2017, 118, 180402. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  41. Qin, H.-H.; Zhang, T.-G.; Jost, L.; Sun, C.-P.; Li-Jost, X.; Fei, S.-M. Uncertainties of genuinely incompatible triple measurements based on statistical distance. Phys. Rev. A 2019, 99, 032107. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  42. Gao, T.; Hong, Y.; Lu, Y.; Yan, F. Efficient k-separability criteria for mixed multipartite quantum states. Europhys. Lett. 2013, 104, 20007. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  43. Gabriel, A.; Hiesmayr, B.C.; Huber, M. Criterion for k-separability in mixed multipartite systems. Quantum Inf. Comput. 2010, 10, 829–836. [Google Scholar]
  44. Schwinger, J. Unitary operator bases. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 1960, 46, 570. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  45. Ivonovic, I. Geometrical description of quantal state determination. J. Phys. A Math. Gen. 1981, 14, 3241. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  46. Kraus, K. Complementary observables and uncertainty relations. Phys. Rev. D 1987, 35, 3070. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  47. Wootters, W.K.; Fields, B.D. Optimal state-determination by mutually unbiased measurements. Ann. Phys. 1989, 191, 363–381. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  48. Durt, T.; Englert, B.-G.; Bengtsson, I.; Życzkowski, K. On mutually unbiased bases. Int. J. Quantum Inf. 2010, 8, 535–640. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  49. Maassen, H.; Uffink, J.B. Generalized entropic uncertainty relations. Phys. Rev. Lett. 1988, 60, 1103. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  50. Calderbank, A.R.; Rains, E.M.; Shor, P.W.; Sloane, N.J. Quantum error correction and orthogonal geometry. Phys. Rev. Lett. 1997, 78, 405. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  51. Cerf, N.J.; Bourennane, M.; Karlsson, A.; Gisin, N. Security of quantum key distribution using d-level systems. Phys. Rev. Lett. 2002, 88, 127902. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
  52. Rehacek, J.; Hradil, Z.; Klimov, A.; Leuchs, G.; Sánchez-Soto, L. Sizing up entanglement in mutually unbiased bases with Fisher information. Phys. Rev. A 2013, 88, 052110. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  53. Maccone, L.; Bruss, D.; Macchiavello, C. Complementarity and correlations. Phys. Rev. Lett. 2015, 114, 130401. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
  54. Costa, A.C.; Uola, R.; Gühne, O. Steering criteria from general entropic uncertainty relations. Phys. Rev. A 2018, 98, 050104. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]

Share and Cite

MDPI and ACS Style

Sun, B.-Z.; Wang, Z.-X.; Li-Jost, X.; Fei, S.-M. A Note on the Hierarchy of Quantum Measurement Incompatibilities. Entropy 2020, 22, 161. https://doi.org/10.3390/e22020161

AMA Style

Sun B-Z, Wang Z-X, Li-Jost X, Fei S-M. A Note on the Hierarchy of Quantum Measurement Incompatibilities. Entropy. 2020; 22(2):161. https://doi.org/10.3390/e22020161

Chicago/Turabian Style

Sun, Bao-Zhi, Zhi-Xi Wang, Xianqing Li-Jost, and Shao-Ming Fei. 2020. "A Note on the Hierarchy of Quantum Measurement Incompatibilities" Entropy 22, no. 2: 161. https://doi.org/10.3390/e22020161

Note that from the first issue of 2016, this journal uses article numbers instead of page numbers. See further details here.

Article Metrics

Back to TopTop