1. Introduction
Given a compact space
K, it is well known that the homeomorphism group
is a topological group with the compact-open topology [
1]. If
X is assumed to be only Tychonoff, then for every compact subset
, the group
of homeomorphisms supported in
K (i.e., identity on
) is a topological group with the compact-open topology; however, the full homeomorphism group
equipped with the compact-open topology need not be a topological group [
2]. Nevertheless,
can be turned into a topological group by embedding it into
, the homeomorphism group of the Stone-Čech compactification of
X. The latter topology has also been studied under the name of
zero-cozero topology [
3,
4].
For a Tychonoff space X, let denote the family of compact subsets of X. In light of the foregoing, the group of the compactly supported homeomorphisms of X admits three seemingly different topologies, listed from the finest to the coarsest:
- (a)
the finest topology making all inclusions continuous (i.e., the colimit in the category of topological spaces and continuous functions);
- (b)
the finest group topology making all inclusions continuous (i.e., the colimit in the category of topological groups and continuous homomorphisms); and
- (c)
the topology induced by .
Recall that the groups
are said to have the
Algebraic Colimit Property (
ACP) if the first and the second topologies coincide [
5,
6]. Recall further that a space
X is said to have the
Compactly Supported Homeomorphism Property (
CSHP) if the first and the last topologies coincide [
5]), in which case all three topologies are equal.
In a previous work, the authors gave sufficient conditions for a finite product of ordinals to have CSHP ([
5], Theorem D(c)).The main result of this paper is that the same conditions are also necessary, thereby providing a complete characterization of CSHP among such spaces.
Theorem A. Let equipped with the product topology, where are infinite limit ordinals and are successor ordinals. The space X has CSHP if and only if there is an uncountable regular cardinal κ such that and for every .
Example 1. By Theorem A, the spaces and (with the product topology) and (sum of ordinals with the order topology) do not have CSHP. Furthermore, the disjoint union (coproduct) does not have CSHP either (see Corollary 2).
The proof of Theorem A is based on results of general applicability about CSHP of products and coproducts of spaces. For an infinite cardinal , a subset S of a space X is said to be τ-discrete in X if every subset of S of cardinality less than is closed in X. If S is -discrete in X, then every subset of S of cardinality less than is discrete. Being -discrete in X is equivalent to being closed and discrete in a certain finer topology (Proposition 1). Recall that the cofinality of a partially ordered set is the smallest cardinal of a cofinal set contained in .
Theorem B. Let Y be a compact Hausdorff space, Z be a zero-dimensional locally compact Hausdorff pseudocompact space that is not compact, and . If contains a τ-discrete subset of cardinality τ that is not closed, then the product does not have CSHP.
Recall that the
support of a homeomorphism
h of a space
X is
Theorem C. Let Y be a compact Hausdorff space, Z a locally compact Hausdorff space, and a cofinal family in , where τ is an infinite cardinal. Suppose further that
- (I)
contains a τ-discrete subset of cardinality τ that is not closed; and
- (II)
contains a net of distinct elements such that and whenever .
Then the coproduct (disjoint union) does not have CSHP.
In order to invoke Theorems B and C, one needs to ensure that contains a -discrete subset of cardinality that is not closed. For spaces that are of interest to us in this paper, this is guaranteed by the next theorem.
Theorem D. Let α be an infinite limit ordinal with , and put with the order topology. Then contains a τ-discrete subset of cardinality τ that is not closed.
The paper is structured as follows. In
Section 2, we provide some preliminary results that are used throughout the paper. In
Section 3, we prove Theorems B and C, while the proof of Theorem D is presented in
Section 4. Lastly, Theorem A is proven in
Section 5.
2. Preliminaries
Let
be an infinite cardinal. For a topological space
, the subsets of
X of cardinality less than
form a directed system with respect to inclusion. We put
where the colimit is formed in the category
of topological spaces and their continuous maps.
Proposition 1. Let τ be an infinite cardinal and a topological space. A subset is τ-discrete in X if and only if S is closed and discrete in .
Proof. Suppose that is -discrete. Then for every with , and thus is closed in X; in particular, is closed Y. Therefore, S is closed in . Let . Then is also -discrete, and consequently, by the previous argument, closed in . Hence, the singleton is open in S in the topology induced by . This shows that S is discrete in .
Conversely, suppose that is closed and discrete in . Let be such that . We show that A is closed in . Let , and put . Then , and so is closed and discrete in Y. If , then is discrete, and so is closed in Y. If , then is closed in Y. In both cases, , and therefore . This shows that A is closed in X, as desired. □
Proposition 2. Let τ be an infinite cardinal, be a continuous map between Hausdorff spaces, and S a subset of X such that is injective. If is τ-discrete in Y, then S is τ-discrete in X.
Proof. By Proposition 1, it suffices to show that
S is closed and discrete in
. Put
. Since the
-topology is functorial,
is continuous, and in particular,
is continuous and bijective. By Proposition 1,
is discrete and
is closed in
. Thus,
is discrete, and furthermore
To show that
S is closed in
, let
. Then there is a net
such that
, and so
. By (
1),
. Since
is discrete in
, the net
is eventually constant. Therefore,
is eventually constant, because
is injective. Hence,
, because
is Hausdorff, and in particular,
is Hausdorff. □
The next lemma allows one to show that a space does not have CSHP by constructing a suitable -discrete set in its homeomorphism group.
Lemma 1. Let X be a topological space and a directed system of subsets of X such that . Suppose that there is an infinite cardinal τ and a subset such that:
- (1)
S is τ-discrete in X;
- (2)
for every ; and
- (3)
S is not closed in X.
Then .
Proof. Let be a subset with properties (1)–(3). By (1) and (2), is closed in X for every ; in particular, is closed in for every . Thus, S is closed in . By (3), S is not closed in X. Therefore, the two topologies are distinct. □
Lastly, recall that CSHP is inherited by clopen subsets.
Lemma 2 ([
5], 5.3(b) and 5.6)
. Let X be a Tychonoff space. - (a)
If is a clopen subset and X has CSHP, then so does A.
- (b)
If X contains an infinite discrete clopen subset, then X does not have CSHP.
3. Products and Coproducts with Compact Spaces
In this section, we prove Theorems B and C. Before we prove Theorem B, we need a technical proposition about the existence of cofinal subsets with small down-sets.
Proposition 3. Let be a poset and put . Then every cofinal subset of contains a cofinal subset J of cardinality τ such that for every .
Proof. Let
be a cofinal subset. Without loss of generality, we may assume that
. Let
be an enumeration of
C. We define
inductively as follows. We put
. For
, suppose that
has already been defined for all
. We observe that
is not cofinal in
, because its cardinality is smaller than
. Thus,
is non-empty. Put
Put
. It follows from the construction of
that
In other words, if , then . Therefore, for every .
It remains to show that
J is cofinal in
. To that end, let
. Since
C is cofinal in
, the set
is non-empty. Put
. It follows from the construction of
that
It follows from the construction of the
that they are strictly increasing, and in particular,
. Thus,
is non-empty. Put
. For every
, one has
, and thus, by (
3),
. Consequently,
Therefore,
Hence,
, and
. □
Theorem B. Let Y be a compact Hausdorff space, Z be a zero-dimensional locally compact Hausdorff pseudocompact space that is not compact, and . If contains a τ-discrete subset of cardinality τ that is not closed, then the product does not have CSHP.
Proof. Since
Y is compact and
Z is pseudocompact, the product
is also pseudocompact ([
7], 3.10.27), and by Glicksberg’s Theorem ([
8], Theorem 1),
.
Let
be a cofinal family in
. Without loss of generality, we may assume that each
is open in
Z, and
. Using Proposition 3, one may pick a cofinal subfamily
of
such that
Since Y is compact, the family is cofinal in ; in particular, it is directed.
Put and . We construct a subset that satisfies the conditions of Lemma 1:
- (1)
S is -discrete in G;
- (2)
for all ; and
- (3)
.
This will show that , and thus does not have CSHP.
Let
be a
-discrete subset such that
and
is not closed. Without loss of generality, we may assume that
. Let
be an injective enumeration of
. For
, put
Since is a homeomorphism on the clopen set and is the identity on the clopen set , one has in for every .
Put . We verify that S satisfies properties (1), (2), and (3).
(1) Let
and
denote the respective projections and put
Since
H is a closed subgroup of
G, it suffices to show that
S is
-discrete in
H. Fix
, and define
by
. The composite
is continuous ([
7], 3.4.2), where the function spaces are equipped with the compact-open topology. Thus, its restriction to
H,
is a continuous group homomorphism. The restriction
is injective (because
), and
is
-discrete in
. Therefore, by Proposition 2,
S is
-discrete in
H.
(2) For
,
if and only if
, or equivalently,
(
because
). Therefore, by (
4),
(3) Since
for every
, it follows that
, and thus
. It remains to show that
. To that end, let
W be an entourage of the diagonal in
. Then
for some entourage
U of the diagonal in
and entourage
V of the diagonal in
([
7], 8.2.1). Since
, there is
such that
for every
. Therefore,
for every
. Hence,
. □
Theorem C. Let Y be a compact Hausdorff space, Z a locally compact Hausdorff space, and a cofinal family in , where τ is an infinite cardinal. Suppose further that:
- (I)
contains a τ-discrete subset of cardinality τ that is not closed; and
- (II)
contains a net of distinct elements such that and whenever .
Then the coproduct (disjoint union) does not have CSHP.
Proof. Since Y is compact, one has . The family is cofinal in ; in particular, it is directed.
Put and . We construct a subset that satisfies the conditions of Lemma 1:
- (1)
S is -discrete in G;
- (2)
for all ; and
- (3)
.
This will show that , and thus does not have CSHP.
Let be a -discrete subset such that and is not closed. Without loss of generality, we may assume that . Let be an injective enumeration of . For , put . Clearly, , because Y and Z are clopen subsets of .
Put . We verify that S satisfies properties (1), (2), and (3).
(1) Put
. Since
Y is a compact-open subset of
, the subgroup
H is open (and in particular, closed) in
G, and so it suffices to show that
S is
-discrete in
H. Let
denote the canonical embedding. The composite
is continuous, where the function spaces are equipped with the compact-open topology. Thus, its restriction to
H and corestriction to
,
is a continuous group homomorphism. The restriction
is injective (because
), and
is
-discrete in
. Therefore, by Proposition 2,
S is
-discrete in
H.
(2) For
,
if and only if
, or equivalently,
. By the assumptions on
, the latter is possible only if
. Therefore,
(3) Since
for every
, it follows that
, and thus
. It remains to show that
. To that end, let
W be an entourage of the diagonal in
. Then there is an entourage
U of the diagonal in
and an entourage
V of the diagonal in
such that
. Since
, there is
such that for
for every
and
. One has
and thus
is closed, because
is
-discrete. Therefore,
In particular, there is
such that
for every
. Hence,
for every
, as desired. □
4. Construction of -Discrete Subsets
Theorem D. Let α be an infinite limit ordinal with and put with the order topology. Then contains a τ-discrete subset of cardinality τ that is not closed.
The proof of Theorem D is broken down into several lemmas. First, the special case where the ordinal has countable cofinality is proven. Then, the theorem is reduced to the case where for an infinite limit ordinal . (Here, and throughout this paper, means ordinal exponentiation, not cardinal exponentiation.)
Proposition 4. Let α be an infinite limit ordinal and put with the order topology. Suppose that is a net satisfying that for every there is such that for every . Then in .
Proof. Let
U be an entourage of the diagonal
in
. Then
U is a neighborhood of the point
, and so there is
such that
. Let
be such that
for every
. Then, for every
and
,
as desired. □
Lemma 3. Let α be an infinite limit ordinal with countable cofinality and put with the order topology. Then contains a countable subset that is not closed.
Proof. Let
be a strictly increasing cofinal sequence in
. Let
denote the transposition
Since is the identity for all but two isolated points, it is a homeomorphism of Y. Furthermore, in by Proposition 4, because the are cofinal and increasing. Therefore, is a countable subset that is not closed. □
Lemma 4. Let β be an infinite limit ordinal with a strictly increasing cofinal family , put , and put with the order topology. Then contains a family of non-trivial homeomorphisms such that
- (a)
for every , and
- (b)
for every and distinct ,
Proof. Fix an ordinal
. Since
, there is an ordinal
such that
. Then
, and every
may be uniquely represented in the form
where
,
, and
. Indeed, let
be the Cantor’s normal form of
x, that is,
and
are non-zero natural numbers ([
9], 2.26). Put
, where the sums are formed in the same order as in the Cantor’s normal form. Clearly,
. For every
i such that
, there is an ordinal
such that
. Thus,
where
if
for any
i and
if
. (The uniqueness of this representation follows from the uniqueness of the Cantor’s normal form.)
We construct now
. Let
be a bijection such that
. Put
It is clear that . We show that . First, we note that is a bijection, whose inverse is of the same form with replaced with . Thus, it suffices to show that is continuous. Let be an infinite limit ordinal, and let be a net converging to x. Without loss of generality, we may assume that for every j and that the are non-decreasing. We distinguish the cases used to define .
Case 1. If
, where
, then without loss of generality, we may assume that
, and thus
, where
and
converges to
. Therefore,
Case 2. If
, where
, then without loss of generality, we may assume that
, and thus
, where
and
converges to
. Therefore,
Cases 3 and 4. If
where
, then
where
. Since
are non-decreasing, the
are non-decreasing. Put
. Clearly,
. If
, then
, and
; hence,
. If
, then
and thus
. Since
eventually, without loss of generality, we may assume that
for all
j, and
and
. Since
is a bijection, it follows that
and
. Therefore,
This shows that and are continuous, and therefore .
Property (a) follows directly from the definition and the more general property of that for every , if , then .
Lastly, we prove property (b). Let
and
be distinct. There are ordinals
such that
(for
). By the definition,
Since and , it follows that . Therefore, one obtains , as desired. □
Lemma 5. Let β be an infinite limit ordinal with a strictly increasing cofinal family , put , and put with the order topology. Let denote the homeomorphism defined by . For , define by - (a)
for every and .
- (b)
If and are such that , then for every .
- (c)
For every family , the net converges to in .
Proof. (a) Let . Since is continuous on the clopen sets and , it is continuous on Y. Furthermore, it is easily seen that , and thus .
(b) Let
. Then
for some
, and so
Thus, , and . Therefore, , because by our assumption.
(c) Since is a strictly increasing cofinal family in and is the identity on , it follows by Proposition 4 that . □
Proof of Theorem D. By Lemma 3, we may assume that
. Let
be the Cantor’s normal form of
, that is,
and
are non-zero natural numbers ([
9], 2.26). Since
, it follows that
, and so
The space
embeds as a clopen subset into
Y, and so
embeds as a closed subgroup into
. Therefore, without loss of generality, we may assume that
, where
is an ordinal of uncountable cofinality.
Let
be a strictly increasing cofinal family in
, and let
be a family in
as provided by Lemma 4. Put
, where
is as in Lemma 5, and set
. By Lemma 4(a),
for every
, and thus by Lemma 5(b),
We show that S is -discrete but not closed. (Since by the construction, follows from these two.) By Lemma 5(c), converges to . Since , it follows that . Thus, S is not closed.
Let
be a subset such that
. Put
. Since
itself is a regular cardinal,
. Suppose that
is a net in
that converges to
. Then, in particular,
. Thus, by (
33),
Since
is an isolated point, so is its homeomorphic image
. Therefore, the net is eventually constant, and so there is
such that
Hence, by Lemma 4(b),
for every
. It follows that
, as desired. □
Corollary 1. Suppose that , where α is an ordinal, is an infinite limit ordinal, and . Then does not have CSHP.
Proof. Put
. Without loss of generality, we may assume that
. (If
, then
contains an increasing cofinal sequence
, and thus
is an infinite discrete clopen subset of
X, and so by Lemma 2(b),
X does not have CSHP.)
Since is an infinite ordinal, , and so . Thus, , and embeds into X as a clopen subset. Therefore, by Lemma 2(a), it suffices to show that does not have CSHP.
Put and . We verify that the conditions of Theorem C are satisfied. Clearly, Y is compact Hausdorff and Z is locally compact Hausdorff. Let be cofinal and increasing in . Put for . Then is cofinal in .
(I) By Theorem D, contains a -discrete subset of cardinality that is not closed.
(II) For
, let
denote the transposition that interchanges
and
, and leave every other point fixed. Clearly,
and
for every
. Since
, one has
(cf. [
10], 5N1). For every
, there is
such that
for every
, and so
. Therefore, by Proposition 4,
. □
5. Products of Ordinals
In this section, we prove Theorem A, which provides necessary and sufficient conditions for a product of ordinals to have CSHP.
Theorem A. Let equipped with the product topology, where are infinite limit ordinals and are successor ordinals. The space X has CSHP if and only if there is an uncountable regular cardinal κ such that and for every .
Sufficiency was proven in the authors’ previous work ([
5], Theorem D(c)), and so it is only necessity that has to be shown. We first prove a special case of Theorem A.
Theorem 1. Let λ be an infinite limit ordinal, and let X be λ equipped with the order topology. If the space X has CSHP, then λ is an uncountable regular cardinal.
Proof. If had countable cofinality, then it would contain an infinite discrete clopen subset. It would follow then by Lemma 2(b), that does not have CSHP, contrary to our assumption. Thus, .
Next, we show that
for some ordinal
. Let
be the Cantor’s normal form of
, that is,
and
are non-zero natural numbers ([
9], 2.26). Put
and
. It follows from
that either
or
. Since
is an infinite limit ordinal, one has
, and so
and
is a limit ordinal. Thus, by Corollary 1 applied to
, one obtains that
. Therefore,
. In other words,
and
, and
.
We show that is a regular cardinal by proving that . Put . One has (ordinal exponentiation), because is an uncountable cardinal, and for every ordinal , one has (where is ordinal exponentiation).
If
, then
, and so
([
11], Theorem 1 from XIV.6 and Theorem 1 from XIV.19). Thus, by Corollary 1,
cannot have CSHP, contrary to our assumption. Hence,
, and
as desired. □
We proceed now to prove Theorem A.
Proof of Theorem A. Suppose that X has CSHP. Without loss of generality, we may assume that . Put . Since embeds as a clopen subset of X, by Lemma 2(a), has CSHP. Thus, by Theorem 1, is an uncountable regular cardinal.
Put and with the order topology. By Theorem D, contains a -discrete subset of cardinality that is not closed. The space Z is zero-dimensional, locally compact, pseudocompact, and . Therefore, by Theorem B, the product does not have CSHP.
Assume that there is an i such that or . Then or , respectively, and thus, by Lemma 2(a), has CSHP, being homeomorphic to a clopen subset of X. This contradiction shows that all are equal and for every i. □
Corollary 2. Let be infinite ordinals. The disjoint union (coproduct) has CSHP if and only if one of the following conditions hold:
- (a)
α and β are successor ordinals, or;
- (b)
β is an uncountable regular cardinal, and in addition, or α is a successor ordinal.
Proof. Suppose that has CSHP. By Lemma 2(a), and both have CSHP. Thus, by Theorem 1, and are either successor ordinals or uncountable regular cardinals. If , then we are done. On the other hand, if , then is a clopen subset of , and thus, by Lemma 2(a), has CSHP, being a clopen subset of . By Theorem 1, is a successor ordinal, because is not a cardinal.
Conversely, if and are successor ordinals, then is compact, and we are done. So, we confine our attention to case (b). Suppose that is an uncountable regular cardinal. If , then has CSHP by Theorem A. If and is a successor ordinal, then , which has CSHP by Theorem 1. □