Introduction to the Special Issue «Justice Based on Truth»
1. Why Truth and Justice Still Matter
2. A Word on Methodological Historical Scholarship
3. Dworkin as a Contemporary Reference Author
4. The Structure of the Special Issue «Justice Based on Truth»
- Dworkin’s epistemology of ethics and personal responsibility in the search for truth and justice;
- Dworkin’s philosophy of law in comparison with historically important authors such as Thomas, Spinoza, Leibniz, and Fuller;
- Dworkin’s theory in contemporary application and its possible development with a view to the future (Transitional Justice in Civil War and the perspective of traditional Chinese Moluë).
5. Conclusions
Conflicts of Interest
References
- Dworkin, Ronald. 1977. Taking Rights Seriously. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Dworkin, Ronald. 2011. Justice for Hedgehogs. Harvard: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Fuller, Lon. 1958. Positivism and Fidelity to Law—A Reply to Professor Hart. Harvard Law Review 71: 630–72. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Hart, Herbert Lionel Adolphus. 1958. Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals. Harvard Law Review 71: 593–629. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Holenstein, Elmar. 2004. Philosophie-Atlas, Orte und Wege des Denkens. Zürich: Ammann-Verlag. Available online: https://www.researchcollection.ethz.ch/handle/20.500.11850/359415 (accessed on 22 April 2023).
- Holenstein, Elmar. 2023. Fortsetzung der europäischen Tradition der Philosophie mit einem nicht-europäischen Hintergrund. In Polylog als Aufklärung? Interkulturell Philosophische Impulse. Edited by Franz Gmainer-Pranzl and Lara Hofner. Wien: Facultas, pp. 215–35. [Google Scholar]
- Radbruch, Gustav. 1945. Fünf Minuten Rechtsphilosophie. Dreier: Paulson, pp. 209–10. [Google Scholar]
- Radbruch, Gustav. 1946. Gesetzeliches Unrecht und übergesetzliches Recht. Dreier: Paulson, pp. 211–19. [Google Scholar]
- Radbruch, Gustav. 2003. Rechtsphilosophie, Leipzig: Quelle & Meyer. 2. Auflage. Edited by Stanley L. Paulson. Heidelberg: C.F. Müller, 3. Auflage 1932, neu herausgegeben v. Ralf Dreier. [Google Scholar]
- Santayana, George. 1980. Reason in Society [1905/06]. In The Life of Reason. New York: Dover Publications, vol. II. [Google Scholar]
- Senn, Marcel. 2014. Law and Authority. A Political and Legal Paradigm by Thomas Hobbes. Comparative Legal History 2: 30–44. First published in: Comparative Legal History 2: 30–44. Republished in: Marcel Senn, Rechtphilosophisches und rechtshistorisches Selbstverständnis im Wandel, Zürich, pp. 17–33. Available online: https://www.zora.uzh.ch/id/eprint/142002/ (accessed on 22 April 2023). [CrossRef]
- Senn, Marcel. 2017. Rechts-und Gesellschaftsphilosophie. Historische Fundamente der europäischen, nordameri-kanischen, indischen sowie chinesischen Rechts-und Gesellschaftsphilosophie. Eine Einführung mit Quellenmaterialien. Mit einem Gastbeitrag zum «Sinomarxismus» von Harro von Senger. Zürich and St. Gallen: Dike, 2. A. 615p, [Chinese translation of the first edition (2012) by Prof. Liu Yi. 2012. 法哲学与社会哲学. 北京: 中国政法大学出版社. Rechts-und Gesellschaftsphilosophie. Beijing: China University of Political Science and Law Press. ISBN 9787562066378]. [Google Scholar]
- Senn, Marcel. 2022. Naturrechtstheorie und Gottesverständnis bei Baruch de Spinoza vor dem Hintergrund des Begriffs säkularer Modernität. In Matthias Armgardt/Hubertus Busche (Hg.), Naturrechtsdenken von Leibniz vor dem Hintergrund der Säkularisierung. Berlin: Erich Schmidt, (=Abhandlungen zur rechtswissen-schaftlichen Grundlagenforschung Münchener Universitätsschriften. Juristische Fakultät, Bd. 102). pp. 34–58. [Google Scholar]
1 | With good reason, we may then believe in the youth and their ideals of serious thinking and morality, if these youth have not been indoctrinated by the old. Then this youth also has the power to free the spirits that serve ideological interests from their shackles. That is why George Santayana, a philosopher of the early 20th century, born in Madrid, died in Rome, but who also lived in North America for many years and taught as a professor, and who presented a philosophy of the rationality of society and man, should be explicitly quoted here with his wise words about a globalised humanity (1905/06, pp. 41–46): «Young men escape as soon as they can, at least in fancy, into the wide world; all prophets are homeless and all inspired artists; philosophers think out some communism or other, and monks put it in practice. There is indeed no more irrational ground for living together than that we have sprung from the same loins. They say blood is thicker than water; yet similar forces easily compete while dissimilar forces may perhaps cooperate. It is the end that is sacred, not the beginning. A common origin unites reasonable creatures only if it involves common thoughts and purposes; and these may bind together individuals of the most remote races and ages, when once they discovered one another. It is difficulties of access, ignorance, and material confinement that shut in the heart to its narrow loyalties; and perhaps greater mobility, science, and the mingling of nations will one day reorganise the moral world. It was a pure spokesman of the spirit who said that whosoever should do the will of his Father who was in heaven, the same was his brother and sister and mother» (Santayana 1980). |
2 | Prof. Elmar Holenstein contextualised this chain of tradition to European philosophy as follows: What is called European philosophy cannot be understood without including the non-European environment (Holenstein 2004, pp. 84, 73; Holenstein 2023, p. 217). Without knowledge of Islamic-Arabic and Jewish authors, the cultural flowering that has taken place in Europe since the High Middle Ages could not have been in this way, or as the well-known sociologist of law and religion, Max Weber, put it: there is absolutely nothing in the field of thinking about the meaning of the world and of life that has not already been thought in Asia in one form or another (Holenstein 2004, pp. 90–94). Elmar Holenstein, Philosophie-Atlas, Orte und Wege des Denkens, Zürich: Ammann-Verlag, 3. Auflage, 2004; free download: https://doi.org/10.3929/ethz-b-000359415, accessed on 22 April 2023. |
3 | «... our conclusion ought to be that no philosopher from the past or from another cultural tradition can ever be so readily adapted to needs of the present. A good philosopher’s writing is meant to challenge our individual minds in reading and understanding. It is not intended to be an authority on the basis of its thoughts, which, in the end, were created under circumstances not comparable to those of the present. Therefore, we have to be well educated so as to know how to deal with a current problem critically by ourselves, without relying on the advice of opinion-leaders and lobbying intelligencia. In my opinion, this is the only intellectual way in which we can show our respect to all of these great and profound philosophers» (Senn 2014, p. 44). |
4 | Lon Fuller (1902–1978), an US-American jurist, who was since 1940 Professor of Law at Harvard University, engaged in 1958 as a representative of natural law, in the famous debate with Herbert Lionel Adolphus Hart (1907–1992), the Anglo-Saxon representative of legal positivism at Oxford University, Great Britain (Senn 2017, p. 187). Hart’s article in the Harvard Law Review from 1958 was entitled with “Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals” (Hart 1958, Harvard Law Review. 71 (4): 593–629), the answer by Fuller read “Positivism and Fidelity to Law—A Reply to Professor Hart” (Fuller 1958, Harvard Law Review. 71 (4): 630–72). Hart pleaded for a separation from morality and law, Fuller argued for morality as the [authentic] source of law’s binding power. In fact, this debate between the Anglo-Saxon and North American runs through the entire tradition on legal philosophy in the 20th century, especially against the backdrop of the Second World War between Americans and the Nazi Germans. The key question was: what can effectively legitimate a law, make it binding and ultimately enforce it? The famous German Kantian philosopher of law, Gustav Radbruch (1878–1949), had commented on this in his first edition of the Philosophy of Law from 1914 until the third edition in 1932 (Radbruch 2003, p. 82 original german, transl. Senn): “He who is able to enforce law proves that he is called upon to he is called upon to establish law. Conversely: whoever does not have power enough to protect each of the people against the other, has not the right to command him (Kant).” Immediately after the war, Radbruch revised this position and professed his belief in natural law (Radbruch 1945, Fünf Minuten Rechtsphilosophie). It is true that he was never a legal positivist, but at the beginning a strict and then perhaps an open Kantian, who nevertheless increasingly turned to non-legitimised principles of law (Radbruch 1946, Gesetzliches Unrecht und übergesetzliches Recht), a position that a Fuller also subsequently represented to Hart. |
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2023 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Senn, M. Introduction to the Special Issue «Justice Based on Truth». Laws 2023, 12, 43. https://doi.org/10.3390/laws12030043
Senn M. Introduction to the Special Issue «Justice Based on Truth». Laws. 2023; 12(3):43. https://doi.org/10.3390/laws12030043
Chicago/Turabian StyleSenn, Marcel. 2023. "Introduction to the Special Issue «Justice Based on Truth»" Laws 12, no. 3: 43. https://doi.org/10.3390/laws12030043
APA StyleSenn, M. (2023). Introduction to the Special Issue «Justice Based on Truth». Laws, 12(3), 43. https://doi.org/10.3390/laws12030043