The Unity and Fragmentation of Being: Hölderlin’s Metaphysics of Life
Abstract
:1. Kant on the Fragmentation of Human Reason
2. Fichte’s Attempt at Reunification
3. Hölderlin
3.1. Hölderlin’s Response to Fichte
- The absolute I is conscious.
- Everything that is conscious is conscious of something other than itself.
- The absolute I contains everything there is.
3.2. The Existentialist Answer
3.3. The Logical–Metaphysical Answer
3.4. Life and Freedom
3.5. Neo-Platonism and Beauty
4. An Objection and Resolution: Hölderlin’s Planetary Dimension
- Der Frühling
- Wenn neu das Licht der Erde sich gezeiget,
- Von Frühlingsreegen glänzt das grüne Thal und munter
- Der Blüthen Weiß am hellen Strom hinunter,
- Nachdem ein heitrer Tag zu Menschen sich geneiget.
- Die Sichtbarkeit gewinnt von hellen Unterschieden,
- Der Frühlingshimmel weilt mit seinem Frieden,
- Daß ungestört der Mensch des Jahres Reiz betrachtet,
- Und auf Vollkommenheit des Lebens achtet.
- Spring
- When new the light of Earth shows itself,
- After spring’s rain shines the green valley, and merrily
- The blooms’ whiteness at the bright stream,
- After a serene day offered itself to the humans.
- Visibility grows through bright differences,
- The spring sky lingers with its peace,
- So that the human being views the year’s charm,
- And respects/pays attention to/cares for life’s perfection.32
Funding
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | See (Kant 1992) for the English translation. |
2 | This Kantian insight was rediscovered by Wittgenstein in his later work. He, too, pointed out, based on somewhat different arguments, that philosophers have the tendency to construct castles in the air, figments of their unchecked grammatical imagination. The advice of both philosophers went unheeded. The result is that today, metaphysics is considered, again, a serious discipline. It has a Leibnizian underpinning in terms of possible worlds and is based on the naïve assumption that we can discover de re necessities by taking the symbols of modal logic to be terms referring to the essence of things. Both claims have been refuted by Kant and Wittgenstein, implicitly or explicitly, and neither Kant’s nor Wittgenstein’s refutations of metaphysics thus understood have been refuted, but merely ignored. I speak of metaphysics (of life) in a more loose, poetical sense, as will transpire below. |
3 | An anonymous reviewer objects that ‘Kant’s unity of apperception ensures a subjective coherence across faculties, and what is divided is not reason itself but the relation between experience and metaphysical ideas’. This is problematic. As Kant puts it, not only in the opening lines of the Critique, but especially also in the “Dialectic”, it is the structure of reason itself which raises certain questions and tells us they are unanswerable. However, as the questions remain intelligible, because they rest on the ideas of reason, they also remain tempting. The unity of apperception does not resolve this conflict either. The unity of apperception is neither intuitive nor conceptual (B130ff.), as it is that which unites sensory intuitions and concepts in their combination in judgment. What is it then? Either it is both intuitive and conceptual, which would at least allow us to make sense of the idea that it is unifying two disparate things. However, then, it would be itself hybrid, fragmented. Or it is a third mysterious something, of which we can have no knowledge (as Kant does not allow for intellectual intuition), a mere postulate that apparently satisfies our desire for completion, when in fact, it only expresses this desire, leaving it wanting for more. No wonder that the German idealists fastened on this notion and made it the starting point of new metaphysical theories (or phantasies). |
4 | I have explored some of these issues in (Kanterian 2016). |
5 | The three principles combined gave him the general categories of reality, negation and limitation, from which everything else could be derived, including, eventually, nature itself. Every concept is thus unified under, because derived from, the principle of I = I. See (Fichte [1794] 1988, p. 12ff.). |
6 | In the practical part III of the Foundations, Fichte conceives of the I not as a deed-action, but as a striving, indeed a striving for the impossible, the ‘completed infinite’ (vollendete Unendlichkeit). Cf. (Fichte [1794] 1988, p. 187). |
7 | Unless otherwise indicated, the English translations of Hölderlin are mine. |
8 | Hölderlin seems to have had some doubts about Fichte even before Jena. See (Hölderlin 1992, vol. II, p. 569). |
9 | It seems strange to speak of God as an idea, as opposed to the idea of God, especially as this would grant, trivially, existence to God (as the existence of the idea of God is not disputed here). However, the ambiguity, or incoherence, is really Kant’s. Ideas are concepts without objective reality, and an ideal is an individual entity determined by an idea. A wise man is such an ideal, determined by the idea of wisdom (and not to be found in experience). God, then, would be another such ideal. However, as Kant says that every ideal is an idea, which is determined as an individual entity by the idea, we seem to be moving around in a circle. Cf. B596f., also B371ff. |
10 | Against this, an anonymous reviewer writes, ‘The claim that Hölderlin refutes Fichte by showing the absolute I to be ‘nothing’ (for me) overlooks Fichte’s distinction between the absolute I as a transcendental principle and the empirical I as its manifestation. Fichte could counter that the absolute I’s self-positing does not require an external object in the same way empirical consciousness does, as it is an act of pure spontaneity’. However, an act of pure spontaneity is still an act, whether understood as a deed or event, and so it requires time. Moreover, as we cannot make sense of deeds or events without ascribing them to agents, which must have bodies, it requires space as well. Hence, Hölderlin’s reasoning remains valid. What is the absolute I anyway? Why do we refer to it as an ‘I’, as opposed to a ‘You’ or ‘He/She’, and not by means of any other random expression? The absolute I is surely just a metaphysical sublimation of our ordinary first-person pronoun and of the fact that we can refer to and talk about ourselves, which in turn requires the possibility of reference to other agents and the world. See (Strawson 1993, Part I). |
11 | I leave aside here the fact that the early Hölderlin is more enthusiastic about Fichte’s infinite striving of the I than the later Hölderlin is, who begins to view this titanic striving as a danger. See below. |
12 | Hölderlin’s text was discovered in 1931 and published as “Urteil und Sein” (“Judgment and Being”) in 1961 by Friedrich Beißner. It is a philosophical jewel. At the time of its writing, it was the most advanced reflection on the possibility of absolute idealism, and in fact, it already points beyond idealism. The text brings together metaphysical, epistemological and logical considerations, as they emerged in Kant, Fichte and other contemporaries (such as the young Schelling). The text is divided into three parts, “Being”, “Judgement” and “Reality and possibility”, i.e., modality. It suffices to focus on “Being” and “Judgment”. (The part about modality is more difficult to make sense of and would require discussion of Kant’s Analytic and Dialectic). For commentaries, see e.g., (Henrich 1965/1966, 1992; Franz 1986/1987, 2011, pp. 228–232). For a recent challenge to Henrich’s influential interpretation, see Josifović 2018. While Josifović makes some valid points against Henrich, his claim that Hölderlin did not reject Fichte in 1795 seems incorrect to me, as is especially his contention that Hölderlin identifies Being with some original I (distinct from self-consciousness) as the content of intellectual intuition (Josifović 2018, p. 329). The text does not warrant these claims, especially not the claim that the I is the content of Hölderlinian intellectual intuition. Josifović simply declares, without argument, that this claim is an external ‘presupposition’ (‘Vorwissen’). Moreover, ‘content’ is surely just another word for ‘object’, in which case Josifović’s interpretation self-destructs, as what he calls intellectual intuition cannot be that intellectual after all, if it has an object. As my interpretation below suggests, Being is life for Hölderlin, and life is not an original I of any kind, especially not a Fichtean one. |
13 | See (Kanterian 2012), following Frege. |
14 | As said, Hölderlin is not the only one to commit this fallacy. Hegel is another example. He writes, ‘Vereinigung und Seyn sind gleichbedeutend; in jedem Saz drükt, das Bindewort: ist, die Vereinigung des Subjekts und Prädikats aus—ein Seyn’ (‘Joining and being mean the same; in each sentence the conjunction: is, expresses the joining of the subject and the predicate—a being’; (Hegel 2020, p. 10)). The fallacy is particularly evident in this statement of the matter, because Hegel draws the ultimate and clearly false conclusion: if the copula ‘is’ is expressing the joining of the subject and the predicate (at an ontological level), then ‘is’ must be a conjunction. However, verbs are not conjunctions. These are simply different grammatical categories. |
15 | See Pfau’s translation in (Hölderlin 1988, p. 37), also Mariña’s in (Hölderlin 2018). |
16 | And, of course, in the understanding of much of the tradition. The realisation that nature too is vulnerable, not least to our own unconscionable destruction of it, only began to emerge in the later part of the 19th century. I have explored this in my paper “Heidegger and the Earth Myth” (MS) (see Kanterian n.d). |
17 | For a documentation of these years, see the documents collected in (Franz 2004). |
18 | Letter to Neuffer, October 1794; (Hölderlin 1992, vol. II, p. 551). |
19 | For Hölderlin’s various geometrical analogies, see (Franz 2012, p. 95ff.). |
20 | See (Franz 2012, p. 103f.) for more details. Hayden-Roy suggests some additional possible sources of Hölderlin’s chiliastic model, in particular Kant’s essay “Idea for a Universal History with a Cosmopolitan Purpose” and Herder’s “The Oldest Document of the Human Race”. She also argues, very plausibly, ‘Offensichtlich liegt diesem Modell eine säkularisierte Auffassung der biblischen Heilsgeschichte (Paradies–Sündenfall–Wiederherstellung des Gottesreiches) zugrunde [.] Den unmittelbaren Impuls, ein neues Zeitmodell zu entwickeln, gab [Hölderlin] ohne Zweifel die Französische Revolution. Erst angesichts dieses historischen Ereignisses entstand bei ihm das Bedürfnis, die Zeit in einem “freie[n] kommende[n] Jahrhundert” auf Erden anstatt im jenseitigen Himmelreich kulminieren zu lassen’ (‘Obviously this model is based on a secularized view of the biblical history of salvation (paradise - fall - restoration of the kingdom of God) [.] The immediate impulse to develop a new model of time was undoubtedly given to [Hölderlin] by the French Revolution. It was only in view of this historical event that he felt the need to let time culminate in a “free coming century” on earth instead of in the kingdom of heaven beyond’; (Hayden-Roy 2007, p. 63f.). |
21 | See (Franz 2012, p. 150ff.). His discussion of the differences between Schelling and Hölderlin seem to me to be of great importance, but I need to leave this topic for some other occasion. |
22 | As Franz (2012, p. 153f.) points out, Hegel picked up the notion of ‘the one differentiated in itself’, first in the guise of ‘the connection of the connection and the non-connection’ (‘die Verbindung der Verbindung und der Nichtverbindung’; see “Systemfragment von 1800”, (Hegel 1978, p. 520)), and then, in the Differenzschrift, by characterizing the absolute as ‘the identity of the identity and the nonidentity’ (Hegel 1986, p. 96), a notion that will make up the foundation of his mature system. |
23 | (Hölderlin 1992, vol. I, p. 685). The passage in the Symposium is in 187a (Plato 1925, p. 127). See also (Hippocrates/Heracleitus 1931, p. 484, frg. XLV). |
24 | This interpretation was proposed by Dilthey in Das Erlebnis und die Dichtung (Dilthey 1906). See (Franz 2012, p. 95). |
25 | On the eccentric path, see Franz (2012, p. 95ff.). |
26 | On this commemorative aspect in Hölderlin, in relation to Heidegger’s (selective) interpretation of him and to Paul Celan’s somewhat different poetics that denies us having access to the sacred, see (Kanterian 2022). See also (Bambach 2013) for discussion. |
27 | Or maybe even an incoherent one, as one anonymous reviewer points out. There are two lines of defence here. First, no other notion of intellectual intuition, not even Kant’s, is coherent. Second, the verdict of incoherence must not overlook that some incoherent terms are more fruitful and important than others. The phrase ‘hölzernes Eisen’ (‘wooden iron’) is not coherent, but not particularly interesting. Whereas ‘intellectual intuition’ is quite different, given its intellectual history and the fact that important aspects of our cognition are forged into it. |
28 | For an example, see (Sala 2020). |
29 | Against this misconception of our experience, promoted by Kant, see (Hacker 2012). |
30 | It is of course true, as an anonymous reviewer points out, that Kant conceives of the experience of the sublime as a process that ultimately makes us assert our freedom in terms of our independence from the realm of nature (‘unsere Unabhängigkeit gegen die Natureinflüsse’, Ak 5:269). Note, however, the agonistic, almost sado-masochistic terms in which Kant frames this struggle (‘die Vernunft der Sinnlichkeit Gewalt anthun muß’, ‘Gefühl der Beraubung der Freiheit der Einbildungskraft durch sie selbst’, ‘Verwunderung, die an Schreck gränzt, das Grausen und der heilige Schauer’), only to then conclude, in a typical Kantian move of self-soothing, that it is all not that dramatic (‘nicht wirkliche Furcht’) and merely a reflection of the faculty of aesthetic judgment in its relation to reason, so really just a purely subjective storm in a teacup. This is not just a profoundly ambivalent and unstable position, but it fails to account for the possibility of the (aesthetic!) experience of real horror caused by natural events, such as tsunamis or life-threatening asteroid impacts, and also by manmade cataclysmic events, e.g., Hiroshima, inconceivable as these may have been in Kant’s time. It is precisely this Promethean understanding of freedom which the later Hölderlin (see next footnote) takes issue with. The idea that we are independent of Natureinflüsse and can take refuge to a mere faculty of ours (‘reason’) strikes me as particularly illusory in our age, indeed has led to the predicament of our age. Faced with the possibility of manmade climate catastrophe, I do not see how any subjectivist Kantian reflection of this sort can assert our autonomy against die Natureinflüsse, nor how it can even dissuade us from feeling genuine, and not just make-believe, fear about the future. |
31 | I cannot discuss here the crucial notion of the Earth, as treated by Hölderlin. Hölderlin became increasingly aware of the dangers posed to the Earth by the Promethean or ‘Titanic’ tendencies of history and especially of the Enlightenment. As Franz (2007, p. 116) so insightfully puts it, ‘Das “Titanische” wird nun als “Gefahr” erkannt, weil die Titanen, solange sie unangebunden sind, insbesondere auch Feinde der “Erde” sind, deren “Gaaben” sie rauben in ihrem Drang, den Himmel zu erobern. Das zerstörerische Wesen der “Titanenfürsten” läßt sich eben auch als ein “Hinwegstreben” von dieser Erde beschreiben. Die Titanen sind “die Vertreter [ … ] des Ungebundenen schlechthin”, aber sie sind in einem philosophischen Sinn eben auch diejenigen, deren Emblem für die “einseitige” Überbetonung der menschlichen “Selbstthätigkeit” steht’ (‘The “Titanic” is now recognized as a “danger” because as long as the Titans are untethered, they are enemies of the “Earth”, whose “gifts” they steal in their urge to conquer the sky. The destructive nature of the “Titan Princes” can also be described as a “striving away” from this earth. The Titans are “the representatives […] of the unbound par excellence,” but in a philosophical sense they are also the ones whose emblem stands for the “one-sided” overemphasis on human “self-activity”). See also (Hayden-Roy 2007). |
32 | This essay is dedicated to the memory of Michael Franz (1947–2023). His friendship and writings have been invaluable to me. The ideas developed in this essay owe much to his lifelong engagement with Hölderlin. I would also like to thank Ian Cooper, Priscilla Hayden-Roy, Hans Maes and the audience of a talk on Hölderlin I gave at Canterbury, UK, in the happier pre-Brexit, pre-Trump days of the year 2012. |
33 | Note: All references to Kant’s works are to Kant’s Gesammelte Werke, published by the Königlich Preußische Akademie der Wissenschaften, Berlin 1900ff., specified by ‘Ak’, followed by volume and page number. The only exceptions are references to the Critique of Pure Reason, cited by the A or B edition, as is the standard in the literature. |
References
- Bambach, Charles. 2013. Thinking the Poetic Measure of Justice: Hölderlin. New York: State University of New York Press. [Google Scholar]
- Dilthey, Wilhelm. 1906. Das Erlebnis und die Dichtung: Lessing, Goethe, Novalis. Göttingen: Teubner. [Google Scholar]
- Fichte, Johann Gottlieb. 1845. Zweite Einleitung in die Wissenschaftslehre. Berlin: Veit & Comp. First published 1797. [Google Scholar]
- Fichte, Johann Gottlieb. 1988. Grundlage der gesamten Wissenschaftslehre. Hamburg: Meiner. First published 1794. Revised in 1975. [Google Scholar]
- Frank, Manfred. 1995. Eine Einführung in Schellings Philosophie. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag. [Google Scholar]
- Frank, Manfred. 1997. Unendliche Annäherung: Die Anfänge der philosophischen Frühromantik. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag. [Google Scholar]
- Franz, Michael. 1986/1987. Hölderlins Logik. Zum Grundriß von ‚Seyn Urtheil Möglichkeit’. Hölderlin-Jahrbuch 25: 93–124. [Google Scholar]
- Franz, Michael. 1996. Schellings Tübinger Platon-Studien. Göttingen: Vandenhoek & Ruprecht. [Google Scholar]
- Franz, Michael. 2004. Materialien zum bildungsgeschichtlichen Hintergrund von Hölderlin, Hegel und Schelling. Tübingen: Hölderlin-Gesellschaft. [Google Scholar]
- Franz, Michael. 2007. ‘nemlich immer jauchzet die Welt/Hinweg von dieser Erde’.‘Welt’ und ‘Erde’ als Kontrastbegriffe in Hölderlins Dichten und Denken. Hölderlin-Jahrbuch 2006–2007: 99–119. [Google Scholar]
- Franz, Michael. 2011. Theoretische Schriften. In Hölderlin Handbuch: Leben—Werk—Wirkung. Edited by Johann Kreuzer. Stuttgart: Metzler, pp. 99–119. [Google Scholar]
- Franz, Michael. 2012. Tübinger Platonismus: Die gemeinsamen philosophischen Anfangsgründe von Hölderlin, Schelling und Hegel. Tübingen: Francke Verlag. [Google Scholar]
- Hacker, Peter. M. S. 2012. Kant’s Transcendental Deduction—a Wittgensteinian Critique. In Knowledge, Language and Mind. Edited by António Marques and Nuno Venturinha. Berlin: De Gruyter, pp. 11–35. [Google Scholar]
- Halfwassen, Jens. 1999. Hegel und der Spätantike Neuplatonismus: Untersuchungen zur Metaphysik des Einen und des Nous in Hegels Spekulativer und Geschichtlicher Deutung, Hegel-Studien, Beiheft Band, 40.
- Halfwassen, Jens. 2004. Plotin und der Neuplatonismus. München: C. H. Beck. [Google Scholar]
- Halfwassen, Jens. 2019. No Idealism Without Platonism: On the Origins of German Idealism at the Tübinger Stift. In Mystik und Idealismus: Eine Lichtung des Deutschen Waldes. Edited by Andrés Quero-Sánchez. Freiburg: Verlag Karl Alber, pp. 144–159. [Google Scholar]
- Hayden-Roy, Priscilla. A. 2007. Zwischen Himmel und Erde: Der junge Friedrich Hölderlin und der württembergische Pietismus. Hölderlin-Jahrbuch 2006/2007: 30–66. [Google Scholar]
- Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. 1978. Der Geist des Christentums: Schriften 1796–1800. Edited by Werner Hamacher. Frankfurt am Main: Ullstein Verlag. [Google Scholar]
- Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. 1986. Jenauer Schriften 1801–1807. Edited by E. Modenhauer and K. M. Michel. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag. [Google Scholar]
- Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. 2020. Frühe Schriften. Frankfurter Manuskripte und Druckschriften. Edited by Walter Jaeschke. Hamburg: Meiner Verlag. [Google Scholar]
- Henrich, Dieter. 1965/1966. Hölderlin über Urteil und Sein. Eine Studie zur Entwicklungsgeschichte des Idealismus. Hölderlin-Jahrbuch 14: 73–96. [Google Scholar]
- Henrich, Dieter. 1992. Der Grund im Bewusstsein: Untersuchungen zu Hölderlins Denken in Jena (1794–1795). Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta. [Google Scholar]
- Henrich, Dieter. 1997. Hegel im Kontext. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag. [Google Scholar]
- Henrich, Dieter. 2003. Between Kant and Hegel: Lectures on German Idealism. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hippocrates/Heracleitus. 1931. Hippocrates: Nature of Man, Regimen in Health, Humours, Aphorisms, Regimen 1–3, Dreams, Heracleitus: On the Universe. Translated by William Henry Samuel Jones. Loeb Classical Library 150. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hölderlin, Friedrich. 1988. Essays and Letters on Theory. Translated and Edited by Thomas Pfau. Berkeley: University of California Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hölderlin, Friedrich. 1990. Hyperion and Selected Poems. Edited by Eric L. Santner. New York: Continuum. [Google Scholar]
- Hölderlin, Friedrich. 1992. Sämtliche Werke und Briefe in drei Bänden. Edited by Michael Knaupp. Frankfurt am Main and Wien: Büchergilde Gutenberg. [Google Scholar]
- Hölderlin, Friedrich. 2018. Judgment and Being. Translated by Jacqueline Mariña. Available online: https://www.academia.edu/37072870 (accessed on 1 April 2025).
- Josifović, Saša. 2018. Lag Henrich falsch? Eine Fichte-konforme Interpretation von Hölderlins Urteil und Sein. Fichte-Studien 23: 325–338. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kant, Immanuel. 1787. Critique of Pure Reason. Translated by Norman Kemp Smith. New York: Macmillan. First published 1781. [Google Scholar]
- Kant, Immanuel. 1992. Theoretical Philosophy, 1755–1770. Edited by David Walford. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kanterian, Edward. 2012. Frege: A Guide for the Perplexed. London: Continuum. [Google Scholar]
- Kanterian, Edward. 2016. Reason’s Disunity with Itself: Adrian Moore on Kant’s Dialectic of Human Reason. Kantian Review 21: 483–493. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kanterian, Edward. 2022. The Desolation of Our Time: Celan’s Struggle with Heidegger. In Heidegger and his Anglo-American Reception: Contributions to Phenomenology. Edited by Pietro d’Oriano and James Rogove. Cham: Springer, pp. 331–365. [Google Scholar]
- Kanterian, Edward. n.d. Heidegger and the Earth Myth (MS).
- Plato. 1925. Lysis. Symposium. Gorgias. Translated by Walter Rangeley Maitland Lamb. Loeb Classical Library 166. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Plato. 1929. Timaeus. Critias. Cleitophon. Menexenus. Epistles. Translated by Robert Gregg Bury. Loeb Classical Library 234. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Plotinus. 1973. [Plotin]. Ausgewählte Schriften. Edited by Walter Marg. Stuttgart: Reclam. [Google Scholar]
- Sala, Enric. 2020. The Nature of Nature: Why We Need the Wild. Washington, DC: National Geographic. [Google Scholar]
- Strawson, Peter. F. 1993. Individuals: An Essay in Descriptive Metaphysics. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2025 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Kanterian, E. The Unity and Fragmentation of Being: Hölderlin’s Metaphysics of Life. Humanities 2025, 14, 92. https://doi.org/10.3390/h14040092
Kanterian E. The Unity and Fragmentation of Being: Hölderlin’s Metaphysics of Life. Humanities. 2025; 14(4):92. https://doi.org/10.3390/h14040092
Chicago/Turabian StyleKanterian, Edward. 2025. "The Unity and Fragmentation of Being: Hölderlin’s Metaphysics of Life" Humanities 14, no. 4: 92. https://doi.org/10.3390/h14040092
APA StyleKanterian, E. (2025). The Unity and Fragmentation of Being: Hölderlin’s Metaphysics of Life. Humanities, 14(4), 92. https://doi.org/10.3390/h14040092