Idealist Individualism or Indigenous Cosmology; Finding Entanglement across Species and Strata
Abstract
:1. Dualism and Pantheism
2. The Ravages of Colonialism
Warping indigenous ideas to suit modern purposes is not limited to early colonisation, but continues in the way ideas are ‘translated’ into contemporary scholarship for western purposes (Mika and Stewart 2017).Approaches to whakapapa, however, changed with the arrival of Europeans, whose incredulity of oral histories, belief in their own superiority, and desire to own indigenous culture not only undermined traditional experts but shifted whakapapa to print where it became subject to Pākehā scrutiny, legal interpretation, or displaced by colonisers as unreliable superstitions and myth.
3. Monotheistic Dualism
The perfection of God’s creation of the Universe is a fundamental principle that is essential to the modern development of a dualism between the appearance and the essential universal Truth, and thus, of the subjective interpretation of the appearance and the rational analysis of universal truths that hold, regardless of history or culture, across time and space. As outlined more fully below, Kant was so committed to this idea, along with Descartes’ argument that science as cause and effect demonstrates the perfection and consistency of God, that he was frightened that there was no room left for individual freedom.(the) concept of God is internally non-contradictory, a proof easily supplied since the concept of an all-perfect being contains nothing but positive determinations which cannot conflict with each other (see the third paragraph of Descartes’ Meditations on Knowledge, Truth and Ideas, originally published in 1684, as well as many later expositions of the claim).
4. Descartes
Descartes insists that the comprehension of objects using the senses is always informed by commonly held fallacies, or tricks of perception, and it is only with the rationality of the mind that social norms can be overcome and truth ascertained.Accordingly, I will suppose not a supremely good God, the source of truth, but rather an evil genius, supremely powerful and clever, who has directed his entire effort at deceiving me. I will regard the heavens, the air, the earth, colors, shapes, sounds, and all external things as nothing but the bedeviling hoaxes of my dreams, with which he lays snares for my credulity. I will regard myself as not having hands, or eyes, or flesh, or blood, or any senses, but as nevertheless falsely believing that I possess all these things. I will remain resolute and steadfast in this meditation, and even if it is not within my power to know anything true, it certainly is within my power to take care resolutely to withhold my assent to what is false, lest this deceiver, however powerful, however clever he may be, have any effect on me.
There are rules that govern the universe, where mathematical equations can discover the genealogy of forces acting upon other forces. Cartesian rationalism aims for a universal truth that can be deduced independently by each individual to create a classification at the level of Truth that enables each isolated self to communicate with other individual selves. The inclination towards cosmic order enables the individual to peer beyond the appearance and divine the ultimate rational truth.A certain basic disposition or leaning–which opens up a whole spectrum of scientific associations: from the geometry of conic sections, to the planetary orbits of the astronomers, to the geometer’s art of measurement made possible by the earth’s magnetism and the deviations of the quivering compass needle from the horizontal, in a word: inclination.
From here, Descartes announced his most famous epithet, “Cogito, ergo sum”–“I think, therefore I am”.On the one hand I have a clear and distinct idea of myself, in so far as I am simply a thinking, non-extended thing, and on the other hand I have a distinct idea of body, in so far as this is simply an extended, non-thinking thing. And accordingly, it is certain that I am really distinct from my body, and can exist without it.
5. Kant
Kant puts a great deal of time into considering what might be the a priori conditions for individuals to ascertain representations. The appearance of an object offers sensations to the sentient individual. However, they are still fundamentally alienated from the noumenal ‘thing-in-itself’. To comprehend anything at all, a priori conditions are needed as the materials or conduit for human cognition. These a priori are time and space (temporality, and extension and form), through which human beings intuit everything, albeit only as the object imposes on human sensibilities. We apprehend the appearance of the object only because these a priori conditions are in place. He explains the a priori of space as ‘extension and form’, which is a necessary precondition before someone can comprehend the tangible appearance of an object.takes place only insofar as the object is given to us; but this in turn, is possible only if it affects the mind in a certain way. The capacity (receptivity) to acquire representations through the way in which we are affected by objects is called sensibility. Objects are therefore given to us by means of sensibility, and it alone affords us intuitions; but they are thought through the understanding, and from it arise concepts. But all thought, whether straightaway (directe) or through a detour (indirecte), must ultimately be related to intuitions, thus, in our case, to sensibility, since there is no other way in which objects can be given to us.
He goes on to explain that “(t)ime is no discursive or, as one calls it, general concept, but a pure form of sensible intuition. Different times are only parts of one and the same time. That representation, however, which can only be given through a single object, is an intuition.” In contrast, space, or form and extension, are part of the objective field of the world.Time is therefore given a priori. In it alone is all actuality of appearances possible. The latter could all disappear, but time itself, as the universal condition of their possibility, cannot be removed.
Strangely, although empirical appearances are subject to the laws of cause and effect, Kant regards the thing-in-itself as unmodified by necessary causal relationships. The evolution of time and space has no impact on the thing in itself. This otherworldly apparition is conceptually important to Kant, to preserve the ideal of personal freedom. If a subject were defined in terms of cause and effect, there would be no free will. The only way he thinks it is possible to maintain free will is by creating a category that is outside the constraints of time and space.For in this case that which is originally itself only appearance, e.g., a rose, counts in an empirical sense as a thing in itself, which yet can appear different to every eye in regard to color. The transcendental concept of appearances in space, on the contrary, is a critical reminder that absolutely nothing that is intuited in space is a thing in itself, and that space is not a form that is proper to anything in itself, but rather that objects in themselves are not known to us at all, and that what we call outer objects are nothing other than mere representations of our sensibility, whose form is space, but whose true correlate, i.e., the thing in itself, is not and cannot be cognized through them, but is also never asked after in experience.
Having carefully examined the dualism set out by Descartes between subject and object, Kant proliferates schisms between the subject, the appearance of an object, the thing in itself, and the noumenon.(T)o prevent one from thinking of illustrating the asserted ideality of space with completely inadequate examples, since things like colors, taste, etc., are correctly considered not as qualities of things but as mere alterations of our subject, which can even be different in different people. For in this case that which is originally itself only appearance, e.g., a rose, counts in an empirical sense as a thing in itself, which yet can appear different to every eye in regard to color. The transcendental concept of appearances in space, on the contrary, is a critical reminder that absolutely nothing that is intuited in space is a thing in itself, and that space is not a form that is proper to anything in itself, but rather that objects in themselves are not known to us at all, and that what we call outer objects are nothing other than mere representations of our sensibility, whose form is space, but whose true correlate, i.e., the thing in itself, is not and cannot be cognized through them, but is also never asked after in experience.
Kant argues that he has made a conceptual revolution which is every bit as important as Copernicus, who realised that instead of the stars and sun orbiting the earth, the earth orbits the sun. This entails a profound shift in orientation that still makes sense of the way shadows fall and other evidence but fundamentally decentres the earth from an egoistic centre. As Kant explains it, his philosophy follows the radical inversion of orientation proposed by Copernicus:Since that within which the sensations can alone be ordered and placed in a certain form cannot itself be in turn sensation, the matter of all appearance is only given to us a posteriori, but its form must all lie ready for it in the mind a priori, and can therefore be considered separately from all sensation. I call all representations pure (in the transcendental sense) in which nothing is to be encountered that belongs to sensation. Accordingly the pure form of sensible intuitions in general is to be encountered in the mind a priori, wherein all of the manifold of appearances is intuited in certain relations. This pure form of sensibility itself is also called pure intuition. So if I separate from the representation of a body that which the understanding thinks about it, such as substance, force, divisibility, etc., as well as that which belongs to sensation, such as impenetrability, hardness, color, etc., something from this empirical intuition is still left for me, namely extension and form. These belong to the pure intuition, which occurs a priori, even without an actual object of the senses or sensation, as a mere form of sensibility in the mind. I call a science of all principles of a priori sensibility the transcendental aesthetic.
Kant argues his theory is just as revolutionary: an “anthropocentric procedure in philosophy and Copernicus’s heliocentric revolution in astronomy” (1990: fn.715). He fails to notice though that the a priori conditions required for the Transcendental Aesthetic are the opposite of the profound decentering conceptualised by Copernicus. The a priori of time and space recentre the individual subject and make the apprehension of the appearance of the sensible object utterly dependent on ‘synthetic’ understanding and subjective apprehension. Far from positioning the earth in relative motion to the stars, or the subject in relative motion to other objects, Kant succeeds in making all objects relative to the individual thinking subject. He maintains the concept of ‘appearance’ so that the alienation between subject and object, and then the appearance and representation of the thing-in-itself, is upheld; even while at the level of appearance, the deductive logic of cause and effect maintains a synthesis to (God’s) laws of nature.(T)he first thoughts of Copernicus, who, when he did not make good progress in the explanation of the celestial motions if he assumed that the entire celestial host revolves around the observer, tried to see if he might not have greater success if he made the observer revolve and left the stars at rest. Now in metaphysics we can try in a similar way regarding the intuition of objects. If intuition has to conform to the constitution of the objects, then I do not see how we can know anything of them a priori; but if the object (as an object of the senses) conforms to the constitution of our faculty of intuition, then I can very well represent this possibility to myself.
Copernicus recognised that inevitably, all angles and information must be understood from the ‘viewpoint’ of earth, but he importantly resituates the ‘centre’ of motion away from the earth, making complex calculations about the relative speed and direction of all cosmic objects in relation to each other, where earth (from where measurements must inevitably be made) is merely one celestial object orbiting around the sun, and the solar system may be orbiting or moving around other gravitational forces. It seems that Kant grasped these subtleties, but he did not like the philosophical consequences.All apprehended change of place is due to movement either of the observed object or of the observer, or to differences in movements that are occurring simultaneously in both. For if the observed object and the observer are moving in the same direction with equal velocity, no motion will be detected. Now it is from the earth that we visually apprehend the revolution of the heavens. If, then, any movement is ascribed to the earth, that motion will generate the appearance of itself in all things which are external to it, though as occurring in the opposite direction, as if everything were passing across the earth. This will be especially true of the daily revolution. For it seems to seize upon the whole universe, and indeed upon everything that is around the earth, though not the earth itself … As the heavens, which contain and cover everything, are the common locus of things, it is not at all evident why it should be to the containing rather than to the contained, to the located rather than to the locating, that motion is ascribed (Nicolaus Copernicus [1473–1543], De revolutionibus orbium coelestium [Nuremberg, I S43] 1:5).
6. Interconnection and a Decentred Cosmology
7. Contradiction, Cause, and Effect
8. Whakapapa
Māori have been at the forefront of understanding the consequences of copyright and ownership of knowledge, partly because in Māori culture, access has never been egalitarian or a free for all. “Whakapapa prior to the arrival of Europeans was a lived experience taught orally through schools of learning or wānanga that were reserved for individuals selected because of their social rank and perceived skills and abilities to memorise and retain information” (Mahuika 2019, p. 4). My intentions are not to ‘own’ whakapapa, nor to encroach in some sort of cultural usurpation (Stewart 2020). Yet, my relationship to whakapapa is not simply as an ally. I further need to acknowledge, that as an Irish Pakeha settler in Aotearoa, my knowledge of both the Gaelic and Māori languages is at beginner level.Before the impact of colonialism, whakapapa experts held important positions in their tribes, but these people and their knowledge were displaced as Pākehā sought to control and assimilate Māori culture and history. Pākehā researchers, for a very long time, set themselves up as experts in Māori history and genealogy, and encouraged Māori to apply the genealogical method of dating to whakapapa and to situate their history and genealogy within Western methodological traditions and epistemologies.
9. Radical Ontological Relationality
10. Onto-Epistemology
In the grander scheme of things, traditional Te Reo are the voices of nature; the jolt of an earthquake, the song of a bird, the rustling of leaves, the rumbling of thunder before a storm, the piercing bolt of lightning in the night sky, the rushing waves of a tsunami, the cry of a whale, the fresh smell of rain on the earth.(Delamere in Mika 2014, p. 49)
11. Celtic Animism
Neul a’ snàmh air an speur,duilleach eadar è ’s mo shùil;ùr bàrr-uaine gruag a’ bheithe,leug nan leitir cas mun Lùib.Oiteag ’tighinn bhàrr an tuim,a’ toirt fuinn às do dhos,cruit na gaoithe do bhàrr teudach,cuisleannan nan geug ri port.A cloud swimming in the sky, aleaf between it and my eye;new crop-green hair of the birch,read the casual letters about LùibA breeze coming from the tree,bringing tunes from you,the wind’s harp from the top of a string,the pulses of the branches to a tune.
Duilleach an t-Samhraidh, tuil an Dàmhair, na cuithean ’s an àrdghaoth Earraich i;dùrd na coille, bùirich eas, ùire ’n t-sneachda ’s an fhalaisg i;tlàths is binneas, àrdan, misneach, fàs is sileadh nam frasan i;anail mo chuirp, àrach mo thuigse, mo làmhan, m’uilt is m’anam i.Fad na bliadhna, rè gach ràithe, gach là ’s gach ciaradh feasgair dhomh,is i Alba nan Gall ’s nan Gàidheal is gaire, is blàths, is beatha dhomh.The summer leaves, the October flood, the winds and the high wind Spring is she;the thunder of the forest, the roar of a waterfall, the fresh snow and the darkness is she;mildness and sweetness, pride, courage, the growth and rain of the showers is she;the breath of my body, the nurture of my understanding, my hands, my tears and my soul is she.Throughout the year, during every season, every day and every evening for me,It is Scotland, Highland and Lowland that is laughter and warmth and life for me.(Deòrsa 2000) (translated by Joyce Bríghde Gilbert, pers.comm.)
The trees are not a personification of human girls. Birch is a nursery tree. The rest of the forest follows birch as it transforms the land back into native forest. As the birch inhabit the villages that were cleared by the greedy Lairds, they lay the groundwork for the renewal of the land, and that proliferation supports communities.Mura tig ’s ann theàrnas mi a Hallaiga dh’ionnsaigh Sàbaid nam marbh,far a bheil an sluagh a’ tathaich,gach aon ghinealach a dh’fhalbh.Tha iad fhathast ann a Hallaig,Clann Ghill-Eain ’s Clann MhicLeòid,na bh’ ann ri linn Mhic Ghille Chaluim:chunnacas na mairbh beò.Na fir ’nan laighe air an lèanaigaig ceann gach taighe a bh’ ann,na h-igheanan ’nan coille bheithe,dìreach an druim, crom an ceann.I will go down to Hallaig,to the Sabbath of the dead,where the people are frequenting,every single generation gone.They are still in Hallaig,MacLeans and MacLeods,all who were there in the time of Mac Gille Chaluim:the dead have been seen alive.The men lying on the greenat the end of every house that was,the girls a wood of birches,straight their backs, bent their heads.
These simple stories and praise poems present a world where animals, plants, fish, and geology are constantly present in daily life. They are a significant part of shaping fate; they hold the future, as well as the past. Different species or ocean and geology hold a character that resonates with the ways that people behave and what they have endured. Like all indigenous people, the Celts are highly contextual and poetic. Rationality is an aspect of thinking and communication, but thought also needs to consider the character, courage, and entrails; it is defined by political and ecological fate, which constrains the parameters of freedom.(A)n origin story of the four septs of Glenmoriston Macdonalds, in Coire Dho. The four sons of the chief are there accosted in Coire Dho by a white fawn and a raven, that drops a bone between them and seals their fate.(Macdonald, 270 in Gauld and Langhorne 2021, p. 18)
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | Undoubtedly I am skating over many nuanced and important interpretations of these significant issues, I hope the reader will bear with me, as this common Scholastic interpretation forges insight into the dualism that has dominated Enlightenment thinkers such as Descartes and Kant. |
References
- Aeschylus. 1926. Orig. 5th Century BCE. Herbert Weir Smyth (trans) Prometheus Bound, Loeb Classical Library, Volumes 145 & 146. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Available online: https://www.theoi.com/Text/AeschylusPrometheus.html (accessed on 6 May 2022).
- Alley, Elizabeth, and Mark Williams, eds. 1992. Tuwhare Interview with Bill Manhire. In The Same Room: Conversations with New Zealand Writers. Auckland: Auckland University Press, pp. 175–96. [Google Scholar]
- Barad, Karen. 2007. Meeting the Universe Half Way: Quantum Physics and the Entanglement of Matter and Meaning. Durham: Duke University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Braidotti, Rosi. 2013. Posthuman Ecologies. Cambridge: Polity Press. [Google Scholar]
- Deleuze, Gilles, and Felix Guattari. 1999. A Thousand Plateaus; Capitalism & Schizophrenia. Translated by Brian Massumi. London: Athlone Press. First published 1980. [Google Scholar]
- Deòrsa Mac Iain Deòrsa George Campbell Hay. 2000. Fuaran Sleibh: Irish Rhymes Included in Collected Poems and Songs of George Campbell Hay. Edited by Michael Byrne. Edinburgh: EUP Lorimer Trust. Available online: https://www.scottishpoetrylibrary.org.uk/poem/ceithir-gaothan-na-h-albann/ (accessed on 1 December 2022).
- Descartes, René. 1980. Discourse on Method and the Mediations. Translated by F. E. Sutcliffe. London: Penguin Books. [Google Scholar]
- Duffy, Fearghal. 2015. Metamorphosis in Irish Myths. Available online: http://metamorphosisproject.org/fearghal-duffy-metamorphosis-in-irish-myths/ (accessed on 1 December 2022).
- Elsbach, Alfred. 1924. Kant und Einstein; Untersuchingen über das Verhältnis der modernen Erkenntnistheorie. Berlin and Leipzig: Walter de Gruyter and Co. [Google Scholar]
- Farnes, Jamie S. 2018. A unifying theory of dark energy and dark matter: Negative masses and matter creation within a modified LamdaCDM framework. Astronomy and Astrophysics 620: A92. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Finocchiaro, Maurice A. 1997. Galileo on the World Systems: A New Abridged Translation and Guide. Berkeley: University of California Press. [Google Scholar]
- Freter, Björn. 2022. Decolonial Philosophical Praxis Exemplified Through Superiorist and Adseredative Understandings of Development. In Essays on Contemporary Issues in African Philosophy. Edited by Jonathan O. Chimakonam, Edwin E. Etieyibo and Ike Odimegwu. Cham: Springer, pp. 209–26. [Google Scholar]
- Gauld, Munro, and Ceit Langhorne. 2021. The Glen of the Bards: The Musical Heritage of Glenmoriston: A Scoping Exercise. NatureScot: Buidheann Nadair na h-Alba. [Google Scholar]
- Graves, Robert. 1981. Greek Myths. Bilbao: Cassell Ltd. [Google Scholar]
- Grünbein, Durs. 2010. Descartes Devil; Three Meditations. New York: Upper West Side Philosophers, Inc. [Google Scholar]
- Howard, Don, and Marco Giovanelli. 2019. Einstein’s Philosophy of Science. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Edited by (Fall) Edward Zalta. Stanford: Metaphysics Research Lab Philosophy Department Stanford University Stanford. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/cgi-bin/encyclopedia/archinfo.cgi?entry=einstein-philscience (accessed on 1 December 2022).
- IPCC. 2021. Summary for policymakers. In Climate Change: 2021 The Physical Science Basis. Contribution of Working Group I to the Sixth Assessment Report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change. Edited by Valérie Masson-Delmotte, Panmao Zhai, Anna Pirani, Sarah L. Connors, Clotilde Péan, Yang Chen, Leah Goldfarb, Melissa I. Gomis, J. B. Robin Matthews, Sophie Berger and et al. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Intergovernmental Panel on Science (IPBES). 2019. Global Assessment Report on Biodiversity and Ecosystem Services. Bonn: IPBES. [Google Scholar]
- Irwin, Ruth. 2015. Ecological ethics in the context of climate change: Feminist and indigenous critique of modernity. International Social Science Journal 64: 1–13. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Irwin, Ruth, and Te Haumoana White. 2021. Negentropy and the Accelerating Anthropocene; Stiegler, Māori, and Exosomatic Memory. In Educational Philosophy and Theory. Edited by Joff Bradley. Special edition in memory of Bernhard Stiegler. London: Francis & Taylor. [Google Scholar]
- Kaku, Michio. 2006. Parallels Worlds: A Journey Through Creation, Higher Dimensions, and the Future of the Cosmos. Hamburg: Anchor Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kant, Immanuel. 1998. The Critique of Pure Reason. Translated and Edited by Paul Guyer, and Alan Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- MacGill-Eain, Somhairle. 2022. Hallaig. In Scottish Poetry Library. Translated by Sorley MacLean. Edinburgh: Scottish Poetry Library. Available online: https://www.scottishpoetrylibrary.org.uk/poem/hallaig/ (accessed on 1 December 2022).
- Mahuika, Nēpia. 2019. A Brief History of Whakapapa: Māori Approaches to Genealogy. Genealogy 3: 32. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Marsden, Māori. 1992. God, man and universe: A Māori view. In Te Ao Hurihuri: Aspects of Maoritanga. Edited by Michael King. Auckland: Reed, pp. 118–38. [Google Scholar]
- Merchant, Carolyn. 1980. The Death of Nature: Women, Ecology, and the Scientific Revolution. San Francisco: Harper Collins. [Google Scholar]
- Mika, Carl. 2014. The enowning of thought and whakapapa: Heidegger’s fourfold. Review of Contemporary Philosophy 13: 48–60. [Google Scholar]
- Mika, Carl, and Georgina Stewart. 2017. Lost in translation: Western representations of Maori knowledge. Open Review of Educational Research 4: 134–46. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Ngata, Apirana Turupa. 1972. Rauru-nui-ā-Toi Lectures and Ngati-Kahungunu Origin. Second ‘Introductory Address’ (pp. 4–7). Wellington: Victoria University, [Reprint Edition of Original Lectures from 1944]. [Google Scholar]
- Nicholson, Alexander, ed. 1882. A Collection of Gaelic Proverbs and Familiar Phrases, Based on MacIntosh’s Collection. Edinburgh: MacLachland and Stewart. [Google Scholar]
- Ramose, Mogobe B. 2002. African Philosophy through Ubuntu, Rev. ed. Harare: Mond Books. [Google Scholar]
- Ripple, William J., Christopher Wolf, Thomas M. Newsome, Phoebe Barnard, and William R. Moomaw. 2020. World Scientists’ Warning of a Climate Emergency. BioScience 70: 8–12. Available online: https://academic.oup.com/bioscience/article/70/1/8/5610806 (accessed on 20 January 2020). [CrossRef]
- Roberts, Mere. 2015. Ways of Seeing: Whakapapa. Sites 10: 93–120. [Google Scholar]
- Ross, Daniel, and Ouyang Man. 2021. Towards a Metacosmics of Shame. In Shame, Temporality and Social Change. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Smith, Cherryl Waerea-I-Te-Rangi. 2000a. Straying beyond the boundaries of belief: Maori epistemologies inside the curriculum. Educational Philosophy and Theory 32: 43–51. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Smith, Takirirangi. 2000b. Nga Tini Ahuatanga o Whakapapa Korero. Educational Philosophy and Theory 32: 53–60. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Stewart, Georgina. 2020. Māori Philosophy: Indigenous Thinking from Aotearoa. London: Bloomsbury. [Google Scholar]
- Te Awa Tupua Bill. 2017. Whanganui River Claims Settlement Act. Available online: https://www.legislation.govt.nz/act/public/2017/0007/latest/whole.html (accessed on 1 December 2022).
- Te Urewera Act. 2014. Available online: https://www.legislation.govt.nz/act/public/2014/0051/latest/whole.html (accessed on 1 December 2022).
- Weber, M. 1948. Weber, Max: Essays in Sociology. Edited by H. H. Gerth and C. W. Mills. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd. First published 1919. [Google Scholar]
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. |
© 2022 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Irwin, R. Idealist Individualism or Indigenous Cosmology; Finding Entanglement across Species and Strata. Religions 2022, 13, 1193. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13121193
Irwin R. Idealist Individualism or Indigenous Cosmology; Finding Entanglement across Species and Strata. Religions. 2022; 13(12):1193. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13121193
Chicago/Turabian StyleIrwin, Ruth. 2022. "Idealist Individualism or Indigenous Cosmology; Finding Entanglement across Species and Strata" Religions 13, no. 12: 1193. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13121193
APA StyleIrwin, R. (2022). Idealist Individualism or Indigenous Cosmology; Finding Entanglement across Species and Strata. Religions, 13(12), 1193. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13121193