Sambandha as a ‘Śakti-of-Śaktis’: Bhartṛhari’s Influence on the Relational Realism of Pratyabhijñā
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Sphoṭa: Bhartṛhari and the Metaphysics of Language
3. Sambandha as a ‘Śakti-of-Śaktis’
There is no word that signifies the relation according to its specific property. Because it is extremely dependent (atyanta-paratantra), its form cannot be pointed out. Where this [relation] is, because some service is rendered [from one thing to another, or: from signifier to signified and vice versa], there one arrives at a property (viz. dependence) [but not at the relation itself]. It is even a capacity (i.e., something dependent) of capacities [which are themselves dependent upon the entity which possesses the capacity]; it is even a quality (i.e., something dependent) of qualities [which are themselves dependent upon the entity which possesses the quality] [so it is extremely dependent].28
That capacity (śakti), called samavāya, rendering service to capacities, beyond difference and identity (bhedābheda), being established otherwise, is assisted by saṃbandha (relation), which is beyond the attribute of all categories or objects (padārtha) and which is characterized by everything. This is the tradition from the ancients. By others it is taken for granted that saṃbandha be always made into a category or object. [But] with this, word meaning cannot be sorted out.34
4. The Buddhist Denial of Real Relations
5. Utpaladeva’s Pragmatic Elaboration of Sambandha-Śakti
6. Judgment and the Practical Determination of Relational Tokens
7. Conclusions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
Appendix A
1 | |
2 | |
3 | Aside from a chapter in Allport’s (1982) Oxford thesis on Utpaladeva, see MacCracken’s (2017, 2023) recent publications on the SS, which have contributed to this endeavor (none of these sources, though, focus exclusively on Bhartṛhari’s influence on the Pratyabhijñā theory of sambandha). |
4 | I should add that I have not yet seen MacCracken’s (2021) dissertation where he translates the SS in full; we were working on translations of the text at about the same time. My own dissertation (forthcoming in 2024) translates, analyzes and compares Dharmakīrti’s SP and Utpaladeva’s SS. |
5 | While the reality of sambandha indirectly impacts many of the arguments in the ĪPK, they are only an explicit object of discussion in section II.2.1–II.2.7. |
6 | My analysis of the SSam is heavily indebted to Houben’s comprehensive (1995) study of the text. |
7 | For Pratyabhijñā as transcendental philosophy see Lawrence (1999, 2019). Much of what I will say here vis-à-vis the appropriation of Bhartṛhari’s conception of sambandha can also contribute to comparative conversations around the semiotics of Peirce, in which the mediating function of ‘Threeness’ functions much like the Pratyabhijñā conception of recognitive śakti. (On Peircean semiotics and Pratyabhijñā, see Lawrence (2018a, 2018b) and MacCracken (2023)). |
8 | More specifically, the Pratyabhijñā thinkers add a fourth, more supreme stage—parāvāk—to Bhartṛhari’s three-fold scheme I will outline later in the paper. While the details are not important here, the addition of this fourth level, associated with the ultimate, undifferentiated essence of Śiva himself (cf. ĪPK 1.5.13), symbolizes how Utpala intended to both defend and subsume Bhartṛhari’s linguistic metaphysics into his own system. See Torella (2001, pp. 857–59) and Prueitt (2017, pp 80–83) for further discussion on these stages of speech in Pratyabhijñā, and Ferrante (2020c) and Torella (2001) on aspects of denotation (abhidhā) in the Pratyabhijñā system. |
9 | This is famously expressed in the opening four verses of the VP: anādinidhanaṃ brahma śabdatattvaṃ yad akṣaram/vivartate ‘rthabhāvena prakriyā jagato yataḥ//ekam eva yad āmnātaṃ bhinnaśaktivyapāśrayāt/apṛthaktve ‘pi śaktibhyaḥ pṛthaktveneva vartate//adhyāhitakalāṃ yasya kālaśaktim upāśritāḥ/janmādayo vikārāḥ ṣaḍ bhāvabhedasya yonayaḥ//ekasya sarvabījasya yasya ceyam anekadhā/bhoktṛbhoktavyarūpeṇa bhogarūpeṇa ca sthitiḥ (cf. translations in Reich (2021, p. 49) and Bronkhorst (1992)). I should note that Houben (1995a, pp. 16–8l; 1995b) argues that Bhartṛhari does not have any particularly strong religious or polemical commitments in the VP and employs a form of ‘perspectivalism’ whose primary aim is to systematize and describe the views of others. According to him, we should not necessarily read the opening theological kārikās as a personal statement of his own metaphysical position. Cardona (1999, pp. 92–93), on the other hand, contends that this interpretation is unwarranted and does a disservice to the grammatical tradition with which Bhartṛhari identifies (cf. Todeschini (2010, fn. 14)). |
10 | |
11 | The sacredness of sound and speech, of course, trace back to the Ṛg-Veda. Two hymns, 10.125 and 10.71, are dedicated to vāk. Pertinently, while the former verse personifies Vāk as a goddess, the latter discusses three stages in the development of language: (1) inarticulate speech (e.g., the sounds of animals and insects), (2) primitive articulate speech (i.e., nominal designation), and (3) discursive, or ‘proper’ language that represents the ‘refined’ (saṃskṛta) form of the Vedic sages and poets (Beck 1993, p. 37). |
12 | VP I.94: avikārasya śabdasya nimittair vikṛto dhvaniḥ/upalabdhau nimittatvam upayāti prakāśavat. |
13 | Bhartṛhari describes this progressive unfoldment of sphoṭa (VP 1.83–1.86 and svavṛtti) as a maturation of conceptual ‘seeds’ in the mind consisting of ‘memories, effects, and potentials’ (saṃskāra-bhāvanā-bījāni). The semantic determinacy of these inchoate realities intentionally resolves through a series of sounds and ultimately terminates with the utterance of the final sound that discloses the own-form of a word. (See, in particular, VP 1.86 and its svavṛtti: nādair āhitabījāyām antyena dhvaninā saha/āvṛttaparipākāyāṃ buddhau śabdo ‘vadhāryate. nādaiḥ śabdātmānamavadyotayadbhir yathottarotkarṣeṇādhiyante vyaktaparicchedānuguṇa saṃskāra-bhāvanā-bījāni/tataścāntyo dhvaniviśeṣaḥ pariccheda-saṃskāra-bhāvanā-bīja-vṛtti-lābhaprāptayogyatāpripākāyāṃ buddhāvupagraheṇa śabdasvarūpākāraṃ saṃniveśayati). |
14 | Quoted in Monier-Williams et al. (1970, p. 1270). Patañjali also characterized sphoṭa as possessing unity, indivisibly and eternality (Chakravarti 1930, p. 89). |
15 | See, e.g., Coward (71) and Matilal (85). |
16 | Bhartṛhari makes this clear in the VP when he discusses the important idea of pratibhā (Tola and Dragonetti (1990, p. 97); Desnitskaya (2016, p. 330). This term is variously rendered as ‘intuition’ (Coward and Raja 1990 (144)) or ‘flash of understanding’ (Akamatsu 1992, pp. 37–40)), but, in any case, represents the apprehension of the holistic nature of the vākya-sphoṭa over and above its constitutive pada-sphoṭa: vicchedagrahaṇe ‘rthānāṃ pratibhānyaiva jāyate vākyārtha iti tām āhuḥ padārthair upapāditām//idaṃ tad iti sānyeṣām anākyeyā kathaṃ cana pratyātmavṛtti siddhā sā kartrāpi na nirūpyate//upaśleṣam ivārthānāṃ sā karoty avicāritā sārvarūpyam ivāpannā viṣayatvena vartate//sākśāc chabdena janitāṃ bhāvanānugamena vā iti kartavyatāyāṃ tāṃ na kaś cid ativartate//pramāṇatvena tāṃ lokaḥ sarvaḥ samanugacchati samārambhāḥ pratāyante tiraścām api tadvaśāt (VP 2.143–7; cf. translation in Akamatsu (1992, ibid.)). In this sense, it has been noted that Bhartṛhari advocates a theory of semantic holism similar to both Frege (1892) and Quine (1951), where the semantic content of propositions cannot be derived bottom-up from their constitutive elements (Chakrabarti (1989) presents an analysis of sentence-holism in the Indian context). It is noteworthy that Dharmakīrti rejects this idea when he reduces sentence meaning to its constitutive words (in, e.g., PV I.127.2–5), which aligns with the nominalist tendency to view sentence meaning as a conceptual entity whose distributed (anvaya) character entails that, ipso facto, it cannot be ultimately real (Dunne: 80–83). For a highly relevant description of pratibhā as a form of practical knowledge, see recent articles from David (2021) and Das (2022) (I must thank an anonymous reviewer for bringing my attention to these works). |
17 | dvāv upādānaśabdeṣu śabdau śabdavido viduḥ/eko nimittaṃ śabdānām aparo ‘rthe prayujyate (VP 1.44). |
18 | Cf. MBhD (49): karaṇasannipātāt. See Seneviratne (125–139) for an extended discussion of the dhvanis and, in particular, Bhartṛhari’s binary division of dhvanis: ‘[T]he “prākṛta”(original, therefore, “primary”) type of dhvani is what reveals sphoṭa, while the “vaikṛta” (evolved from another, therefore, “secondary”) type of dhvani maintains the continuity of the already revealed sphoṭa’ (Seneviratne, p. 126). |
19 | |
20 | This intermediate stage is technically characterized by internality (antaḥsaṃniveśa), mind-dependence (buddhimātropādāna) and sequentiality (parigṛhītakrama). Ferrante (2020a, pp. 149–50) suggests that these three qualities can be tentatively compared to a sort of Fodorian ‘mentalese’ (1975)—viz., a ‘Language-of-Thought’ (LoT) theory that posits a type of higher-order formal language, distinct from any determinate public language, that defines the universal syntactical structures of symbolic representation. Obviously, Fodor would likely have no truck with Bhartṛhari’s third level of paśyanti vāc that embraces a monistic vision of linguistic emanation. But one of the challenges that Bhartṛhari and the holism of sphoṭa can debatably present LoT theorists is to explain the experienced continuity between the higher-order LoT and the first-order diversity of public languages—and, metaphysically speaking, the continuity of the ‘intentional’ dimension of the LoT with the even lower-level domains of regular order present throughout the empirical world. |
21 | See vṛtti on VP 1.159: paraiḥ saṃvedyaṃ yasyāḥ śrotraviṣayatvena pratiniyataṃ śrutirūpaṃ sā vaikharī. śliṣṭā vyaktavarṇasamuccāraṇā prasiddhasādhubhāvā bhraṣṭasaṃskārā ca. tathā yā ‘kṣe yā dundubhau yā venau yā viṇāyām ity aparimāṇabhedā. madhyamā tv antaḥsaṃniveśinī parigṛhītakrameva buddhimātropādānā. sā tu sūkṣmaprāṇavṛttyanugatā kramasaṃhārabhāve ‘pi vyaktaprāṇaparigrahaiva keṣāñcit. pratisaṃhṛtakramā saty apy abhede samāviṣṭakramaśaktiḥ paśyantī. sā calācalā pratilabdhasamādhānā cāvṛtā ca viśuddhā ca, sanniviṣṭajñeyākārā pratilīnākārā nirākārā ca, paricchinnārthapratyavabhāsā saṃsṛṣṭārthapratyavabhāsā praśāntasarvārthapratyavabhāsā cety aparimāṇabhedā (cf. Ferrante (2020a, p. 149, f.5)). |
22 | The circular nature of encoding and decoding sphoṭa is evocative of Bohm’s process metaphysics of implicate wholeness (1980). In these terms, we might say that a semantic whole internally ‘unfolds’ into a diversity of particular dhvani, which, in turn, ‘enfold’ this implicate whole in the external act of communication. The potential comparison here might be theoretically fruitful for a metaphysics of wholeness, particularly insofar as Bohm (1980) bases his theory primarily on modern physics, while Bhartṛhari, of course, focuses on the intentional, or phenomenological, dimensions of language use. |
23 | This is among the positions he cites, but does not necessarily overtly endorse, in the VP: anekavyaktyabhivyaṅgyā jātiḥ sphoṭa iti smṛtā/kaiś cit vyaktaya evāsya dhvanitvena prakalpitāḥ (VP 1.93; cf. Bronkhorst (1992, p. 10), who lists this verse as I.96). Even though he does not explicitly commit to this position, I would view this as fairly consistent with his own relational project, as will become clear. |
24 | These two relational axes map onto Utpala’s disjunction between non-sequential and sequential forms of action (see, on this point, Ratié’s recent study on the ĪPKVv II.1, Ratié (2021, pp. 115–21)). In future publications, I plan to explore the way this Pratyabhijñā model can contribute to Kimhi’s (2018) and Rödl’s (2018) recent analytical attempts to recuperate absolute idealism. Consider Kimhi’s claim that ‘judgment belongs to a certain context of activity: the activity whose unity is the same as the consciousness of its unity, or self-consciousness’ (Kimhi: 52). Due to the intrinsic self-consciousness of the activity of judgment, Kimhi insists that what is expressed by ‘something of the form ‘S thinks that p’ should not be logically assimilated to that which is expressed by sentences such as ‘S is doing φ’ or ‘S is φ-ing’….The ‘thinks’ in ‘S thinks’ is an activity in what is logically a fundamentally different sense of ‘activity’ from any expressed by verbs in predicative propositions of the form ‘S is φ-ing.’…We misunderstand this uniqueness if we construe it in terms of the exceptional nature of either the substance or attributes involved in a nexus of predication’ (ibid., 15–16). Depending upon how you interpret Kant, the Pratyabhijñā may be said to diverge in their conviction that nothing outside the determinative activity of self-consciousness could appear as anything within it unless its nature is ontologically continuous with this activity. In other words, a reified interpretation of the noumenal is discredited merely by virtue of the intrinsically self-illuminating structure of self-conscious cognition, whose sentience consists in the fact that it cannot illuminate anything fundamentally other than itself (on this point, see Arnold (2008) and Ratié (2011b, 2014)). This is also, of course, precisely where Hegel disembarks from Kant’s dichotomous system of thought into a triadic metaphysics. |
25 | jñānaṃ prayoktur bāhyo ‘rthaḥ svarūpaṃ ca pratīyate/śabdair uccaritais teṣāṃ saṃbandhaḥ samavasthitaḥ//pratipattur bhavaty arthe jñāne vā saṃśayaḥ kvacit/svarūpeṣūpalabhyeṣu vyabhicāro na vidyate (VP III.3.1–2). (See Houben (1995a, pp. 149–53) and Biardeau (1964, p. 423) for expositions of these two verses, and, in particular, how the three-fold relational factors mentioned in the first two verses collapse into a dyadic śabda-artha relation in the subsequent verses). |
26 | asyāyaṃ vācako vācya iti ṣaṣṭhyā pratīyate/yogaḥ śabdārthayos tattvam apy ato vyapadiśyate (VP III.3.1.3). |
27 | Houben notes that Bhartṛhari’s method of ‘proof’ in this section is like those given in the Vaiśeṣikasūtra, where some very commonplace understanding serves to substantiate their categorical analysis of cognition (172, f. 280). |
28 | nābhidhānaṃ svadharmeṇa saṃbandhasyāsti vācakam/atyantaparatantratvād rūpaṃ nāsyāpadiśyate//upakārāt sa yatrāsti dharmas tatrānugamyate/śaktīnām api sā śaktir guṇānām apy asau guṇaḥ (VP III.3.4–5; translation in Houben: 170). |
29 | Note that this picture roughly corresponds to Dharmakīrti’s inferential explanation of the causal ‘relation’ in the SP (v. 13): ‘Upon observing one [thing]—i.e., when something [that was] unseen is seen, and is not seen when that [other] is not seen—a person infers ‘effect’ even without the explanation of another’. paśyann ekam adṛṣṭasya darśane tadadarśane/apaśyan kāryam anveti vināpy ākhyātṛbhir janaḥ. |
30 | Whether Bhartṛhari considers vācyavācakabhāvas eternal or created is unclear (cf. VP 1.28: nityatve kṛtakatve vā teṣām ādir na vidyate/prāṇinām iva sā caiṣā vyavasthā nityatocyate). In any case, he states that the relation is ‘permanent’ (nitya) insofar as its ‘beginning cannot be found’ (ādir na vidyate). To the extent that the relation between universals is eternal in the same way that universals are, one can advance the potential connection between sphoṭa and logos (Śāstrī 1959, pp. 102–3; Beck 1993, pp. 14–15). Consider Gerson’s interpretation of Plotinus’s statement, ‘That the Intelligibles are not Outside the Intellect and on the Good’ in the Enneads: ‘[Plotinus] seems to want to argue not only that eternal Forms exist, but that these are somehow connected eternally. This is so presumably because it is owing precisely to such eternal connections that instances of Forms are necessarily connected. Thus, if x is f entails that x is g, this is because of the necessary connectedness of F-ness and G-ness. And here we must add that the eternal connection is ontologically on a par with the eternity of each Form in the connection, that is, the condition for the possibility of x being f is no more eternal than the condition for the possibility that if x is f, x must be g. At this point, Plotinus seems to be arguing that the eternal “link” between eternal, immaterial entities must be one thing which is capable of simultaneously being identified with both F-ness and G-ness so that the partial identity of these is grounded in reality…This one thing is what Intellect is supposed to be. Intellect must be eternal because any judgment made by an individual mind depends for its truth on eternal reality, including eternal interconnectedness of Forms, hence eternal Intellect which grounds the interconnectedness’ (Gerson 1994, pp. 48–49). |
31 | This observation relates to arguments put forward by Dharmakīrti in the SP and F. H. Bradley (1893) against the reality of relation. Specifically, they both observed that when we try and make any token of ‘relation’ into a substantive term with a capacity for genitive predication, we wind up with a regress, for we will always require a further relation to relate this independent relation to its own properties, ad infinitum: dvayor ekābhisambandhāt sambandho yadi taddvayoḥ/kaḥ sambandho ’navasthā ca na sambandhamatis tathā (SP v. 4). |
32 | See, e.g., Classical Indian Metaphysics: Refutations of Realism and the Emergence of “New Logic”. (Phillips 1995), The Lost Age of Reason: Philosophy in Early Modern India, 1450–1700. (Ganeri 2011) and Ascription of Linguistic Properties and Varieties of Content: Two Studies on Problems of Self-Reference. (Oetke 2012). |
33 | ihedam iti yataḥ kāryakāraṇayoḥ sa samavāyaḥ (VS 7.2.26). |
34 | tāṃ śaktiṃ samavāyākhyāṃ śaktīnām upakāriṇīm/bhedābhedāv atikrāntām anyathaiva vyavasthitām//dharmaṃ sarvapadārthānām atītaḥ sarvalakṣaṇaḥ/anugṛhṇāti saṃbandha iti pūrvebhya āgamaḥ//padārthīkṛta evānyaiḥ sarvatrābhyupagamyate/saṃbandhas tena śabdārthaḥ pravibhaktuṃ na śakyate (VP II.3.10–12; translation in Houben: 183–84). |
35 | MacCracken (2023, p. 6) makes a similar point: ‘Relatedness, or relation in its absolute sense, is what orders phenomena into the distinct and unmuddled. Relation is thus not something objectifiable, but rather is indicative of phenomena as having the nature of vimarśa (reflective awareness), a core feature of divine subjectivity itself’. |
36 | While I am inclined to take the Buddhist as the pūrvapakṣin in the SS, one might also view the Buddhist as more of an uttarapakṣa, given the way in which Utpala appropriates and adopts Dharmakīrti’s points rather than directly contradicts them. |
37 | See, e.g., SP (v. 1): pāratantryaṃ hi sambandhaḥ siddhe kā paratantratā/tasmāt sarvasya bhāvasya sambandho nāsti tattvataḥ (cf. also Torella ([1994] 2013, p. 95, f. 21)). |
38 | dviṣṭhasyānekarūpatvāt siddhasyānyānapekṣaṇāt pāratantryādyayogāc ca tena kartāpi kalpitaḥ. The vṛtti reads: sambandho dviṣṭho na caikenātmanobhayatrāvasthitir yuktā na ca dvayoḥ siddhayor anyonyāpekṣātmā nāpi svātmamātraniṣṭhayoḥ pāratantryarūpaḥ saṃbandhaḥ/tato yathā jñātṛtvaṃ kalpitaṃ tathā kartṛtvam apīti katham ātmā sarveśara iti? (cf. translation in Torella ([1994] 2013, pp. 96–97)). |
39 | See SP 11ab: dviṣṭho hi kaścit sambandho nāto ʼnyat tasya lakṣaṇam. |
40 | See PV 40: ‘Since all existents essentially abide in their own essence, they partake in the exclusion between [themselves and other] similar and dissimilar things’. sarve bhāvāḥ svabhāvena svasvabhāva-vyavasthiteḥ/svabhāva-parabhāvābhyāṃ yasmād vyāvṛtti-bhāginaḥ. |
41 | Cf. Lawrence (1999, pp. 133–38), who discusses this similarity, and Ratié’s recent (2021) study on the ĪPVv, where the nature of action as a form of unity-in-diversity is thoroughly addressed. |
42 | See SP v 6: tāmeva cānurundhānaiḥ kriyākārakavācinaḥ/bhāvabhedapratītyarthaṃ saṃyojyante ‘bhidhāyakāḥ |
43 | na ca anekasyānekatā-sahabhāvinī ekatā yujyate bhāvābhāva-rūpatvena viruddhatvāt।anekasmād upādānād ekam ekasmād vā anekam anyonyāsaṃsṛṣṭam evātmamātra-paryavasitam udbhavet (SS: 4). |
44 | This is just the ‘identity principle’ of classical Buddhist logic (cf. Eltschinger and Ratié 2013, p. 195). |
45 | yathā vijñāna-santatau vyavasthā keṣāṃcit; tatra hi śabda-sparśādi-jñāna-lakṣaṇebhyaḥ samanantara-pratyayebhya ekam aindriyakaṃ vikalpajñānam।ekasmād vā samanantara-pratyayāt pañcāpi śabdādi-viṣayāṇi jāyante।yā punar-ekatā anekatā ca samānāśrayā sā pramāṇabādhitā, bhāvasya vābhāvatā. kevalam-itthaṃ rūpayaiva anayā kalpanāpratītyā sāṃsārika-vyavahāra-nirvartanārtham arthāḥ paraspara-vyāvṛttā api kāryakāraṇarūpatvena avāstavenaiva pratipādyante।rāja-puruṣayor anyonyaṃ svarūpa-viśeṣa-kriyaiva evaṃ nirūpyate sthālyāṃ kāṣṭhair ityādau ca. ‘Accordingly (yathā), there is a distinction (vyavasthā) of some things (keṣāṃcit) in the continuum of awareness. For here the unified sensory cognition is a conceptualization (vikalpa) resulting from immediately antecedent conditions (samanantara-pratyaya) characterized by awareness of such [sense-fields] as sound and touch; or, sound and all five sense-fields are produced from a single preceding cognition. However, a state of unity and state of multiplicity which share the same locus (āśraya), or the non-existence of what is existent, is contradicted by pramāṇas. It’s just that objects—though mutually distinguished by such a conceptualization to accomplish conventional life in saṃsāra—are bestowed with a form of cause and effect that is entirely unreal. Thus, an action with a specific nature is indicated with respect to the both the king and servant, and likewise “in a cauldron with firewood,” etc…”’ (SS: 4). |
46 | ata eva pratītikāla eva sāmānyasyeva saṃbandhasyābhyupagamaḥ (SS: 4). |
47 | As Dunne (2004) notes, Dharmakīrti’s critique of temporal extension suggests that a mereological analysis of wholes represents the paradigm critique of any and all entities that are ‘whole-like: that is, they exhibit ‘distribution’ (anvaya). A whole is a distributed entity in that it is a single real thing that is somehow instantiated in other single real things that are its parts. The same may be held of a perdurant entity that allegedly endures over time: to be real, it must be a single thing distributed over numerous temporal instances’ (42). |
48 | iha bhāvānāṃ saṃbandho vicārtyate: kastāvat-saṃbandha-śabdārthaḥ saṃsargaḥ saṃparkaḥ saṃśleṣaḥ saṃbandha ityapyukte na vivṛtaḥ saṃbandhārthaḥ pratīyate।kiṃ nairantaryaṃ saṃśleṣaḥ utānyat kiṃcit? nairantaryaṃ cet dūrasthayoḥ pitāputrayoḥ sa na syāt, ayaḥśalākayoḥ saṃnikṛṣṭayor vibhudravyayor api ca syāt (SS: 1). Note that ‘dependence’ (pāratantrya), ‘fusion’ (saṃśleṣa) and ‘requirement’ (apekṣā) are addressed in the three opening verses of the SP, respectively. |
49 | ‘Therefore, ‘relation’ (saṃbandha) should be emphatically designated as primary (mukhya). In this regard, it is said that these—relation, combination, [and] fusion—are in the first place ‘synonyms’ (paryāya). And that meaning of ‘fusion’ is regarded as the unity of what is multiple (aneka). However, there is neither being only multliple, nor being only unitary; rather this referent, i.e., sambandha, requires both conditions.’ tasmān muktakaṇṭham eva mukhyaḥ saṃbandho ‘bhidhātavya iti।tatrocyate saṃbandhaḥ saṃparkaḥ saṃśleṣa ity ete paryāyās tāvad bhavanti. sa ca saṃśleṣārtho ‘nekasyaikatā kathyate, na tv anekataiva nāpi ekataiva api tu ubhayāvasthāpekṣo ‘yam arthaḥ saṃbandhaḥ (SS: 2). |
50 | tatrocyate pratītis tāvad-anekaika-rūpatāyāṃ saṃbandhābhidhānāya bhavadbhir apy abhyupagantaiva yenoktam “ity amiśrāḥ svayaṃ bhāvāstān yojayati kalpanā” [SP v.5cd] iti kalpanā-rūpatvaṃ ca nāsyā doṣaḥ।ghaṭo ‘yaṃ paṭo ‘yam ity api vikalpaḥ kalpanaiva (SS:4-5). |
51 | See ĪPK II.2.1: kriya-saṃbandha-sāmānya-dravyadik-kāla-buddhayaḥ/satyāḥ sthairyopayogābhyām ekānekāśrayā matāḥ. ‘The concepts of action, relation, universal, substance, space and time, which are based on unity-in-diversity, are to be considered real (satya) because of their permanence and efficacy’. |
52 | athātra pratyakṣāvabhāso ‘pi tathā ghaṭapaṭādirūpa eveti na kalpanātvam (SS: 5). |
53 | ihāpi rājñaḥ puruṣaḥ sthālyāmodana ity ādāv api pratyakṣāvabhāso; na tatheti kuto ‘vagatam?।avaśyam eva ca pratyakṣāvabhāso ‘py atra tathaivābhyupagantavyaḥ. abhyupagata eva vā bhavadbhiḥ yenoktam “arthākārapratibhāsa-saṃlagnatvābādhakenāpi duruddharo ‘yaṃ bhramaḥ” iti. ‘However, here as well—i.e., in cases such as ‘the king’s servant’ and ‘rice in a pot,’ etc.—there is also a perceptual appearance; why are [these] not understood accordingly [i.e., as perceptual]? Moreover (ca), these perceptual appearances should also necessarily be acknowledged in just this way; or rather (vā), it is accepted by you, such that you yourself have said, ‘insofar as it is closely connected with the appearance of aspects of objects, this confusion is difficult even for a defeater (bādhaka) to uproot [viz., to the extent that the cognition is perceptual]’ (SS: 5). Try as I might, I was unable to locate the primary source of Utpala’s citation. Assuming it is from Dharmakīrti, it is not from the PV or the PVS (lamentably, Eltschinger (2021, p. 115, f.14) and Allport (230) also apparently could not locate it). |
54 | The language of ‘internal’ and ‘external’ is, of course, an etic distinction. MacCracken (2023, p. 15) deliberately avoids talk of ‘internal’ and ‘external’ relations in the Indian context because it is ‘confusing enough between Russell and Bradley without adding what Indian philosophy means by internal and external into the muddle.’ While it is true that the use of ‘internal’ is contested in the Russell/Bradley debate, I still maintain that the dichotomy is an indispensable hermeneutic for dissecting Dharmakīrti and Utpaladeva on relations, not to mention vital for a fruitful cross-cultural analysis. That is, some talk of internal and external relations is necessary to compare the relational realism of Pratyabhijñā with the pragmatism of C.S. Peirce, the radical empiricism of William James, and/or the process philosophy of A. N. Whitehead (my forthcoming dissertation (2024) discusses these issues in depth). |
55 | In the ĪPK, Utpala claims that the appearance of cognitive overturning itself presupposes a relation between cognitions established by the synthetic power of the ātman: bādhyabādhakabhāvo ‘pi svātmaniṣṭhāvirodhinām/jñānānām udiyād ekapramātṛpariniṣṭhiteḥ. ‘Even the overturning-overturned relation between cognitions, which are self-contained and do not contradict one another, obtains [solely] in virtue of their resting on a single knower’ (ĪPK I.7.6; translation, with slight changes, in Torella ([1994] 2013, p. 139)). See Rastogi (1986) and Nemec (2012) for an analysis of Abhinavagupta’s theory of error and its relation to Utpaladeva’s. (Please see the Appendix A). |
56 | na hi artha-pratibhāsa-saṃlagnatvād bādhakena api tv artha-pratibhāsa-sādṛśya-sadbhāva-mātrāt. rajata-bhrame ‘pi śuktikā-sādṛśya-sadbhāvo ‘py asty eva, sādṛśya-viṣayā eva hi sarvā bhrāntayaḥ sādṛśya-vyatirekeṇa cānyā artha-pratibhāsa-saṃlagnatayaiva yuktāḥ (SS: 5). |
57 | |
58 | |
59 | We must view this commitment as motivated by the epistemic doctrine of intrinsic validity (svataḥ prāmāṇya), in which the property of a cognition’s appearing valid is internally related to the appearance of a cognition itself. Thus, all cognitions must be considered valid insofar as they are not practically overturned. See Abhinava’s formulation: satya eva yataḥ sthiro bādhakenānunmūlyamāna-vimarśaḥ saṃvādavāṃś ca abhisaṃhitāyāṃ grāmaprāptilakṣaṇāyāṃ kriyāyām upayogī. ‘Truth is just that which is (i) permanent, viz., a judgment’s not being uprooted by a countervailing cognition, and (ii) manifests (saṃvāda) as efficacious in conventional activity characterized by the cognition of many’ (ĪPVV III: 29; see also Torella ([1994] 2013, p. 157, f.4)). This definition of cognitions as intrinsically valid until overturned was famously developed by Kumārila (cf. Immerman (2018), Arnold (2001) and Taber (1992)). |
60 | Cf. also ĪPK (I.5.13–14): citiḥ pratyavamarśātmā parāvāk svarasoditā/svātantryam etan mukhyaṃ tad aiśvaryaṃ paramātmanaḥ. sā sphurattā mahāsattā deśakālāviśeṣinī/saiṣā sāratayā proktā hṛdayaṃ parameṣṭhinaḥ (cf. translation in Torella ([1994] 2013, p. 120)). |
61 | svātmaniṣṭhā viviktābhā bhāvā ekapramātari anyonyānvayarūpaikyayujaḥ saṃbandhadhīpadam. vṛtti: rājñaḥ puruṣa ityādisaṃbandhadhiyo ‘ntaḥsamanvayād aikyaṃ bahiḥ saṃbandhibhedaṃ cālambante (ĪPK(V) II.2.4; translation in Torella ([1994] 2013, p. 159)). |
62 | yadi ekatāmātram eva saṃbandhaḥ syāt, yāvatānekatāṃśād aṃśenaikatā saṃbandhaḥ।tataś ca rāja-puruṣoparaktaikatānyaḥ saṃbandhaḥ pitā-putroparāgopalakṣaṇa-vilakṣaṇa eva (SS: 6). |
63 | Cf. MacCracken (2023, p. 10). Being Is Relating: Continuity-in-Change in the Sambandhasiddhi of Utpaladeva. |
64 | In another portion of the text, he equates this same process of grammatical unification to the distinct words (e.g., the ‘elephant-horses’ that belong to the king) that function like letters of a compound (i.e., hastyādi-śabdā varṇa-tulyāḥ): ‘For, insofar as it is situated in a single judgement, a word is [itself] singular. Then, due to the application (adhyāsa) of a single word, the referent (artha) is also just singular.’ eka-parāmarśa-sthito hi śabda eko bhavati । tad-eka-śabdādhyāsād artho ‘py eka eva (SS:7). There is thus a ‘self-similarity’ to the ‘chunking’ capacities of language, where semantic properties always coincide with discerning a holistic unity in a diversity of elements. (For an interesting parallel to this in cognitive science and computation, see Hofstadter (1979, p. 294) on the process of ‘chunking’ syntactic information). |
65 | dvayoś caikye ‘pi viśeṣaṇaṃ viśeṣyīkṛta-svarūpaṃ viśeṣyātmanā cakāsti svarūpeṇāpi cāvabhāti ‘rājñaḥ puruṣa’ iti।‘rājapuruṣa’ iti tu viśeṣaṇa-bhūto rājā sarvathā parihārita-svarūpo viśeṣyātmatām evaikāntenāpannaḥ prathate—iti na tatra saṃbandhavāco yuktiḥ (SS: 8–9). |
66 | nīlam-utpalam ity atrāpi utpalāntaḥ praviṣṭaṃ nīlam iti nīlavad utpalaṃ pradhānam।sthālyāṃ kāṣṭhair ity atrāpi kartrāśritāṃ kriyām upalīnāḥ sthālyādayaḥ prakāśante।‘ghaṭasyābhāva’ ity atrāpi abhāvo vikalpabuddhāv antarnīta-ghaṭaḥ prādhānyenāvabhāti।‘ayamasmādanya’ ity anyārtho ‘nyatvāparityāgena ivāntarnītāparāny-ārtho viśeṣya iti । evaṃ sarvatrānumantavyam. ‘In the case of “blue lotus” as well, the blue is subsumed within (praviṣṭa) the lotus, and thus the blossom that possesses blueness is the principal member (pradhāna). Here also with respect to “in the pot with firewood”, things such as pots, insofar as they are absorbed into (upalīnāḥ) an action, appear as dependent upon the agent. In the case of “the absence of a pot” as well, an absence, in which a pot is included within the conceptualization, appears as primary. “This is other than this”—in this case, without at all (eva) relinquishing the sense of otherness, the meaning of ‘other’ is ‘something (artha) different from another that includes [the former],’ [which is the thing] to be characterized. This should be acknowledged in all cases’ (SS: 9). |
67 | This is why Utpala affirms that, even though a sequence of objects is determined by the conventional subject, ‘there is no sequence of understanding [i.e., with respect to the disclosure of Śiva]; just the single manifestation of an object at just one moment—precisely this discloses (āviśkaroti) the nature (svarūpam) that consists only in the fact that Śiva is relation (saṃbandhaśivatā).’ na ca saṃvidaḥ kramo ’sti ekaivaikatraiva kṣaṇe ‘rtha-prakāśanā, saiva saṃbandha-śivatā-mayam eva svarūpam āviṣkaroti (SS: 9) (cf. MacCracken 2023, p. 13). |
68 | On the nature of the agential unity of the kārakas in the Pratyabhijñā system, see Lawrence (1998): ‘[A]ll of the kārakas are understood to function in accomplishing the overall action or process (vyāpāra) expressed by the verb. They do this through their own subordinate processes. The pan holds the rice, the fire heats it, and so forth. Where are all the subordinate processes synthesized into the larger one? This is understood to be accomplished by the agent, who is the locus of the overall process (vyāpārāśraya)’ (597). |
69 | Note that these relations must be ‘figurative’ because the insentient nature of particular objects is not self-illuminating, and thus they cannot literally instantiate the relational properties of ‘dependence’ or ‘requirement,’ which require the synthetic perspective of an ‘intentional’ level of description. On this point, see ĪPK (II.4.14–15): asmin satīdam astīti kāryakāraṇatāpi yā/sāpy apekṣāvihīnānāṃ jāḍānāṃ nopapadyate. na hi svātmaikaniṣṭhānām anusandhānavarjinām/sadasattāpade ‘py eṣa saptamyarthaḥ prakalpyate. ‘The relation of cause and effect as well, i.e., ‘when this exists, this comes to be,’ is not admissible for realities that are insentient and as such incapable of ‘requiring.’ In fact, the meaning of the locative case [i.e., ‘when this exists’] may not be applied to self-contained entities, incapable of intentional synthesis (anusaṃdhāna) whether [cause and effect] are considered existent or non-existent’ (translation, with slight adjustments, in Torella ([1994] 2013, pp. 183–84)). (See Bronner 2016 (95) for the semantics of guṇavṛtti and its development in the context of Kashmiri poetics). |
70 | Cf. SS(6): ‘Furthermore, in these terms, sometimes the referent of relation could possess a secondary sense (gauṇavṛtti) because it refers to an inferior aspect (aparabhāga) of the inferior-superior state (parāpara). And (ca) this [relation] of two terms is distinguished simply as assister and assisted, and this must necessarily occur (pratipādanīya); if this [relation] does not occur, then a determination (pratīti) of these two sequential [relata] (i.e., assister and assisted) as simultaneous for the sake of acquisition and relinquishment could not otherwise be effective (ghaṭeta)—and therefore there would be a disruption (lopa) of conventional life.’ tatrāpi kadācit parāparadaśāyām aparabhāgāpekṣaṇād gauṇavṛttyā saṃbandhārthaḥ saṃbhavet, upakāryopakārakayor eva ca viśiṣṭayoḥ saṃbandhaḥ viśiṣṭarūpaḥ, sa ca pratipādanīyo ‘vaśyam eva; tad apratipādane tayor upakāryopakārakayoḥ kramikayor yaugapadyena pratītir hānopādānārtham anyathā na ghaṭeta, tataś ca vyavahāra-lopaḥ syāt. |
71 | See MacCracken (2023, p. 6), Ratié (2021, pp. 95–96) and Torella ([1994] 2013, p. 125, f.42) on this point. Note that despite his general repudiation of Bhartṛhari (cf. Nemec 2011), the example of running and recollection is also used by Somānanda in his ŚD (1.9–11ab). |
72 | ‘For even with respect to one moving along a path (mārgagati), appearances such as those consisting of the sensations of things—e.g., like the grass (tṛna) situated (vartin) on the side (pārśva) [of the path]—are not admitted as existents (sattvena) apart from judgment, due to not being remembered (smaryamāṇa) [later]. Neither, in that case (tadā), does it make sense to establish the existence of those entities (sattā) by inference (from the presence of the collection of sense organs such as sight), because of the absence of the attention of mind. When that is present [i.e., attention], there will necessarily be a judgment at that time (tadānīṃ) of such things as “grass” etc., and that is now a memory.’ na hi mārgagatipravṛttasyāpi pārśvavartitṛṇādivastusparśarūpādipratibhāsāḥ parāmarśarahitāḥ sattvenābhyupagantuṃ pāryante smaryamāṇatvābhāvāt।nāpi teṣāṃ tadā cakṣurādikāraṇasāmagrīsadbhāvenānumānasiddhā sattā yujyate manovadhānābhāvāt।tadbhāve’vaśyaṃbhāvī tadānīṃ tṛṇādiparāmarśa idānīṃ ca smaraṇam (SS:9). |
73 | See ĪPK I.5.19: ‘Even at the moment of the direct perception there is a reflective awareness. How otherwise could one account for such actions as running and so on, if they were thought of as being devoid of determinate awareness?’ sākṣātkārakṣaṇe ‘py asti vimarśaḥ katham anyathā//dhāvanādy upapadyeta pratisaṃdhānavarjitam? (translation in Torella [1994] 2013, pp. 125–26). MacCracken (2023, p. 6) likewise notes that ‘[i]ncipient interpretability is present and real even in what is common-sensically called perception, that is, perceptual as opposed to conceptual cognition’. |
74 | Most notably in this regard, see Peirce (1871), where he claims that the medieval opposition between realism and nominalism partly inspires misguided subjectivist strains of modern ‘idealism’ (i.e., chiefly exemplified in the nominalism of Berkeley’s idealistic philosophy). I hope to say more about this Peircean observation in future publications on the ‘objective’ idealism of Pratyabhijñā as a corrective to the epistemic idealism of Dharmakīrtian Sautrāntika Buddhism. |
References
- Abhyankar, K. V. 1983. Mahābhāṣyadīpikā of Bhartṛhari. Bhandarkar Oriental Research Institute Postgraduate and Research Department Series; Poona: Bhandarkar Oriental Research Institute. [Google Scholar]
- Akamatsu, A. F. 1992. Pratibhā and the Meaning of the Sentence in Bhartṛhari’s Vākyapadīya. In Bhartr̥hari, Philosopher and Grammarian: Proceedings of the First International Conference on Bhartr̥hari (University of Poona, January 6–8, 1992). 1st Indian ed. Edited by Saroja Bhate and Johannes Bronkhorst. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass Publishers. [Google Scholar]
- Allport, David. 1982. Utpaladeva’s Doctrine of Recognition. Ph.D. thesis, Oxford University, Oxford, UK. [Google Scholar]
- Arnold, D. 2001. Intrinsic Validity Reconsidered: A Sympathetic Study of the Mīmāṃsaka Inversion of Buddhist Epistemology. Journal of Indian Philosophy 29: 589–675. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Arnold, D. 2008. Buddhist Idealism, Epistemic and Otherwise: Thoughts on the Alternating Perspectives of Dharmakīrti. Sophia 47: 3–28. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Beck, G. L. 1993. Sonic Theology: Hinduism and Sacred Sound. Columbia: University of South Carolina Press. [Google Scholar]
- Biardeau, M. 1964. Théorie de la Connaissance et Philosophie dans le Brahmanisme Classique. Paris and La Haye: Mouton & Co. [Google Scholar]
- Bohm, David. 1980. Wholeness and the Implicate Order. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. [Google Scholar]
- Bradley, Francis Herbert. 1893. Appearance and Reality: A Metaphysical Essay. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Bronkhorst, J. 1992. Études sur Bhartṛhari, 4: L’absolu dans le Vākyapadīya et son lien avec le Madhyamaka. Asiatische Studien/Etudes Asiatiques 46: 56–80. [Google Scholar]
- Bronner, Yigal. 2016. Understanding Udbhaṭa: The Invention of Kashmir Poetics in the Jayāpīḍa Moment. In Around Abhinavagupta: Aspects of the Intellectual History of Kashmir from the Ninth to the Eleventh Century. Edited by Eli Franco and Isabelle Ratié. Berlin: LIT. [Google Scholar]
- Cardona, G. 1999. Approaching the Vākyapadīya. Journal of the American Oriental Society 119: 88–125. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Chakrabarti, A. 1989. Sentence-Holism, Context-Principle and Connected-Designation “Anvitabhidhāna”: Three Doctrines or One? Journal of Indian Philosophy 17: 37–41. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Chakrabarty, D. 2003. Vaiśeṣika-sūtra of Kaṇāda. New Delhi: D.K. Printworld. [Google Scholar]
- Chakravarti, P. C. 1930. The Philosophy of Sanskrit Grammar. Calcutta: University of Calcutta. [Google Scholar]
- Coward, H. G. 1997. The Sphota Theory of Language: A Philosophical Analysis. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. [Google Scholar]
- Coward, H. G., and K. K. Raja. 1990. Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophies, Volume V: The Philosophy of theGgrammarians. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. [Google Scholar]
- Das, Nilanjan. 2022. Pratibhā, intuition, and practical knowledge. British Journal for the History of Philosophy 31: 630–56. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- David, Hugo. 2021. Pratibhā as Vākyārtha? Bhartr̥hari’s Theory of “Insight” as the Object of a Sentence and Its Early Interpretations. Journal of Indian Philosophy 49: 827–69. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Desnitskaya, E. 2016. Paśyantī, Pratibhā, Sphoţa and Jāti: Ontology and Epistemology in the Vākyapadīya. Journal of Indian Philosophy 44: 325–35. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Dunne, John. 2004. Foundations of Dharmakīrti’s Philosophy. Boston: Wisdom Publications. [Google Scholar]
- Dwivedi, R. C. 1991. Bhartṛhari and Kashmir Saivism. Annals of the Bhandarkar Research Institute 72–73: 95–107. [Google Scholar]
- Eltschinger, V. 2021. A Note on Śaṅkaranandana’s Sambandhaparīkṣānusāriṇī. In Illuminating the Dharma: Buddhist Studies in Honour of Venerable Professor KL Dhamma Joti. Edited by T. Endo. Hong Kong: Centre of Buddhist Studies, The University of Hong Kong, pp. 99–119. [Google Scholar]
- Eltschinger, V., and I. Ratié. 2013. Self, No Self, and Salvation. Dharmakīrti’s Critique of the Notions of Self and Person. Wien: Austrian Academy of Sciences Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ferrante, Marco. 2017. Studies on Bhartṛhari and the Pratyabhijñā: The Case of svasaṃvedana. Religions 8: 145. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ferrante, Marco. 2020a. Studies on Bhartṛhari and the Pratyabhijñā: Language, Knowledge and Consciousness. Journal of Indian Philosophy 48: 147–59. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ferrante, Marco. 2020b. Indian Perspectives on Consciousness, Language and Self: The School of Recognition on Linguistics and Philosophy of Mind. Hindu Studies Series; London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Ferrante, Marco. 2020c. The Place of Language in the Philosophy of the Recognition. In The Bloomsbury Research Handbook of Indian Philosophy of Language. Edited by A. Graheli. Great Britain: Bloomsbury Academic. [Google Scholar]
- Frauwallner, Erich. 1934. Dharmakīrtis Saṃbandhaparīkṣā. Text und Übersetzung. Wiener Zeitschrift für die Kunde des Morgenlandes 41: 261–300. [Google Scholar]
- Frege, Gottlob. 1892. Uber sinn und bedeutung. Zeitschrift für Philosophie und Philosophische Kritik 100: 25–50. [Google Scholar]
- Ganeri, Jonardon. 2011. The Lost Age of Reason: Philosophy in Early Modern India, 1450–1700. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Gerson, L. P. 1994. Plotinus. London and New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Hofstadter, D. R. 1979. Gödel, Escher, Bach: An Eternal Golden Braid. New York City: Basic Books. [Google Scholar]
- Houben, J. E. M. 1995a. The Saṃbandha-Samuddeśa (Chapter on Relation) and Bhartṛhari’s Philosophy of Language. Groninghen: Egbert Forsten. [Google Scholar]
- Houben, J. E. M. 1995b. Bhartŗhari’s perspectivism (2): Bhartŗhari on the primary unit of language. In History and Rationality: The Skovde Papers in the Historiography of Linguistics. Edited by K. D. Dutz and K.-A. Forsgren. Munster: Nodus Publikationen. [Google Scholar]
- Immerman, Daniel. 2018. Kumārila and Knows-Knows. Philosophy East and West 68: 408–22. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Iyer, K. A. S., ed. 1963. Vākyapadīya of Bhartŗhari with the Commentary of Helārāja. Kāņḍa III, Part I. Poona: Deccan College. [Google Scholar]
- Iyer, K. A. S., ed. 1966. Vākyapadīya of Bhartŗhari with the Commentaries Vŗtti and Paddhati, Kāņḍa I. Poona: Deccan College. [Google Scholar]
- Iyer, K. A. S., ed. 1969. Bhartṛhari: A Study of the Vākyapadīya in the Light of the Ancient Commentaries. Pune: Deccan College. [Google Scholar]
- Jha, V. N. 1990. The Philosophy of Relations: Containing the Sanskrit Text and English Translation of Dharmakīrti’s Sambandhaparīkṣā with Prabhācandra’s Commentary. Delhi: Sri Satguru Publications. [Google Scholar]
- Kimhi, I. 2018. Thinking and Being. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Lawrence, David P. 1998. The Mythico-Ritual Syntax of Omnipotence. Philosophy East and West 48: 592–622. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lawrence, David P. 1999. Rediscovering God with Transcendental Argument: A Contemporary Interpretation of Monistic Kashmiri Śaiva Philosophy. Albany: State University of New York Press. [Google Scholar]
- Lawrence, David P. 2018a. Pratyabhijñā Apoha Theory, Shannon–Weaver Information, Saussurean Structure, and Peircean Interpretant Agency. Religions 9: 191. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lawrence, David P. 2018b. Pratyabhijñā Philosophy and the Evolution of Consciousness: Religious Metaphysics, Biosemiotics, and Cognitive Science. In Tantrapuṣpāñjali Tantric Traditions and Philosophy of Kashmir. Studies in Memory of Pandit H.N. Chakravarty. Edited by Bettina Baumer and Hamsa Stainton. Delhi: Indira Ghandi National Centre for the Arts. [Google Scholar]
- Lawrence, David P. 2019. Pratyabhijñā Inference as a Transcendental Argument about a Nondual, Plenary God. In Handbook of Logical Thought in India. New Delhi: Springer. [Google Scholar]
- MacCracken, Sean K. 2017. Recognizing Recognition: Utpaladeva’s Defense of Śakti in His “Proof of Relation” (Sambandhasiddhi). Religions 8: 243. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- MacCracken, Sean K. 2021. The Grammarian, The Skeptic, and the Nondualist: The Proof of Relation (Sambandhasiddhi) of Utpaladeva and the Place It Deserves in Contemporary Theories of Language and Cognition. Ph.D. dissertation, California Institute of Integral Studies, San Francisco, CA, USA. [Google Scholar]
- MacCracken, Sean K. 2023. Being Is Relating: Continuity-in-Change in the Sambandhasiddhi of Utpaladeva. Religions 14: 57. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Matilal, B. K. 1990. The Word and the World: India’s Contribution to the Study of Language. Delhi: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Monier-Williams, M., E. Leumann, and C. Cappeller. 1970. A Sanskrit-English Dictionary. Edited by E. Leumann and C. Cappeller. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Nemec, J. 2011. The Ubiquitous Śiva: Somānanda’s Śivadṛṣṭi and His Tantric Interlocutors. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Nemec, J. 2012. The Two Pratyabhijñā Theories of Error. Journal of Indian Philosophy 40: 225–57. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Oetke, Claus. 2012. Ascription of Linguistic Properties and Varieties of Content: Two Studies on Problems of Self-Reference. Stockholm: Stockholm University. [Google Scholar]
- Peirce, C. S. 1871. Fraser’s The Works of George Berkeley. In The Real Metaphysical Club: The Philosophers, Their Debates, and Selected Writings from 1870 to 1885. Edited by Frank X. Ryan. Albany: SUNY Press. [Google Scholar]
- Phillips, Stephen H. 1995. Classical Indian Metaphysics: Refutations of Realism and the Emergence of “New Logic”. Chicago: Open Court. [Google Scholar]
- Prueitt, C. 2016. Carving Out Conventional Worlds: The Work of Apoha in Early Dharmakīrtian Buddhism and Pratyabhijñā Śaivism. Ph.D. thesis, Emory University, Atlanta, GA, USA. [Google Scholar]
- Prueitt, C. 2017. Shifting Concepts: The Realignment of Dharmakīrti on Concepts and the Error of Subject/Object Duality in Pratyabhijñā Śaiva Thought. Journal of Indian Philosophy 45: 21–47. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Quine, W. V. 1951. Main Trends in Recent Philosophy: Two Dogmas of Empiricism. The Philosophical Review 60: 20–43. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rastogi, N. 1986. Theory of Error According to Abhinavagupta. Journal of Indian Philosophy 14: 1–33. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rastogi, N. 2009. Vāk as Pratyavamarśa: Bhartṛhari from Abhinavan Perspective. In Bhartṛhari: Language, Thought and Reality. Proceedings of the International Seminar. Edited by M. Chaturvedi. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, pp. 301–34. [Google Scholar]
- Ratié, I. 2011a. Le Soi et l’Autre. Identité, Différence et al.térité Dans la Philosophie de la Pratyabhijñā. Leiden-Boston: Brill. [Google Scholar]
- Ratié, I. 2011b. Can One Prove that Something Exists beyond Consciousness? A Śaiva Criticism of the Sautrāntika Inference of External Objects. Journal of Indian Philosophy 39: 479–501. [Google Scholar]
- Ratié, I. 2014. On the Distinction Between Epistemic and Metaphysical Buddhist Idealisms: A Śaiva Perspective. Journal of Indian Philosophy 42: 353–75. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ratié, I. 2018. On the Ṣaḍdhātusamīkṣā, a lost work attributed to Bhartṛhari: An examination of testimonies and a list of fragments. Journal of the American Oriental Society 138: 709–41. [Google Scholar]
- Ratié, I. 2021. Utpaladeva on the Power of Action: A First Edition, Annotated Translation, and Study of Īśvarapratyabhijñavivṛti, Chapter 2.1. Cambridge: Harvard University Department of South Asian Studies. [Google Scholar]
- Rau, W. 1988. Bhartṛharis Vākyapadīya Vollständiger Wortindex zu den mūlakārikās. Mainz: Akademie der Wissenschaften und der Literatur. [Google Scholar]
- Reich, J. D. 2021. To Savor the Meaning: The Theology of Literary Emotions in Medieval Kashmir. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Rödl, S. 2018. Self-Consciousness and Objectivity: An Introduction to Absolute Idealism. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Śāstrī, G. 1959. The Philosophy of Word and Meaning: Some Indian Approaches with Special Reference to the Philosophy of Bhartṛhari. Calcutta: Sanskrit College. [Google Scholar]
- Seneviratne, R. P. 2015. The Revival of Sphoṭa in Early Modern Benares: Śeṣakṛṣṇa’s Sphoṭatattvanirūpaṇa. Ph.D. thesis, Pembroke College, University of Oxford, Oxford, UK. [Google Scholar]
- Sinha, N. 1910. The Vaiśeṣika sûtras of Kaṇâda, with the commentary of Śaṅkara Miśra and extracts from the gloss of Jayanârâyaṇa, together with notes from the commentary of Chandrakânta and an introduction by the translator. Allahabad: Pâṇini Office. [Google Scholar]
- Steinkellner, E. 2021. Dharmakīrti’s Sambandhaparīkṣā and Devendrabuddhi’s Sambandhaparīkṣāvṛtti. Sanskrit Texts from the Tibetan Autonomous Region, 23. Vienna: Austrian Academy of Science. [Google Scholar]
- Taber, J. 1992. What did Kumārila Bhaṭṭha Mean by Svataḥ Prāmāṇya? Journal of the American Oriental Society 112: 204–21. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Todeschini, A. 2010. Bhartṛhari’s View of the Pramāṇas in the Vākyapadīya. Asian Philosophy 20: 97–109. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tola, Fernando, and Carmen Dragonetti. 1990. Some Remarks on Bhartṛhari’s Concept of Pratibhā. Journal of Indian Philosophy 18: 95–112. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Torella, R. 2001. The Word in Abhinavagupta’s Bṛhad-Vimarśinī. In Le Parole E I Marmi: Studi in Onore Di Raniero Gnoli Nel Suo 70o Compleanno. Edited by Raffaele Torella. Roma: Ist. Italiano per l’Africa e l’Oriente, pp. 853–74. [Google Scholar]
- Torella, R. 2008. From an Adversary to the Main Ally: The Place of Bhartṛhari in the Kashmirian Śaiva Advaita. In The Linguistic Traditions of Kashmir: Essays in Memory of Pandit Dinanath Yaksha. Edited by Mrinal Kaul and Ashok Aklujkar. Delhi: D.K. Printworld. [Google Scholar]
- Torella, R. 2013. The Īśvarapratyabhijñā kārikā of Utpaladeva with the Author’s Vṛtti: Critical Edition and Annotated Translation. New Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. First published 1994. [Google Scholar]
- Vergiani, Vincenzo. 2016. Helārāja on Omniscience, āgama, and the Origin of Language. In Around Abhinavagupta. Aspects of the Intellectual History of Kashmir from the Ninth to the Eleventh Century. Edited by Eli Franco and Isabelle Ratié. Zurich: Lit Verlag, pp. 531–608. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2023 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Berger, J. Sambandha as a ‘Śakti-of-Śaktis’: Bhartṛhari’s Influence on the Relational Realism of Pratyabhijñā. Religions 2023, 14, 836. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14070836
Berger J. Sambandha as a ‘Śakti-of-Śaktis’: Bhartṛhari’s Influence on the Relational Realism of Pratyabhijñā. Religions. 2023; 14(7):836. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14070836
Chicago/Turabian StyleBerger, Jesse. 2023. "Sambandha as a ‘Śakti-of-Śaktis’: Bhartṛhari’s Influence on the Relational Realism of Pratyabhijñā" Religions 14, no. 7: 836. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14070836
APA StyleBerger, J. (2023). Sambandha as a ‘Śakti-of-Śaktis’: Bhartṛhari’s Influence on the Relational Realism of Pratyabhijñā. Religions, 14(7), 836. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel14070836