Why Kant’s Moral–Religious Project Was Bound to Unravel
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. How Morality Leads to Religion in Kant
3. Some Signs of Trouble
Admittedly, there is something dispiriting about the moral vision laid out in the second Critique, which demands us to strive for the highest good endlessly even though we can never completely attain this goal. And by the time of publishing the Religion, it seems that his worry about the bleakness of this second Critique vision got the best of him, as he explores whether a merely good disposition might be sufficient to make its bearers well-pleasing to God, even if it is always lacking in terms of strength.Even assuming a person’s moral-physical state here in life at its best—namely as a constant progression and approach to the highest good (marked out for him as a goal)—, he still… cannot combine it with the prospect of satisfaction in an eternally enduring alteration of his state (the moral as well as the physical). For the state in which he now is will always remain an ill compared with a better one which he always stands ready to enter; and the representation of an infinite progression toward the final end is nevertheless at the same time a prospect on an infinite series of ills which, even though they may be outweighed by a greater good, do not allow for the possibility of contentment; for he can think that only by supposing that the final end will at sometime be attained (EAT, 8:335).
4. Kant’s Selective Appropriation of Lutheran Tradition
According to Kant, Christianity based on alleged historical revelation represents a wider circle than a pure religion of reason, because the former contains tenets available solely through historical transmission.22 But the former can still be made up of elements that lead us back to the inner circle, which would mean that this historical religion, despite its particularity and contingency, can attach “itself to pure religion as its vehicle” (RBR, 6:115). Then, the Religion represents an investigation of whether this kind of unity obtains between reason on the one hand and revelation or scripture on the other hand, which essentially refers to the form of Christianity he is familiar with.Since… revelation can at least comprise also the pure religion of reason, whereas, conversely, the latter cannot do the same for what is historical in revelation, I shall be able to consider the first as a wider sphere of faith that includes the other, a narrower one, within itself (not as two circles external to one another but as concentric circles); the philosopher… must keep within the inner circle…. From this standpoint I can also… start from some alleged revelation or other and… to hold fragments of this revelation, as a historical system, up to moral concepts, and see whether it does not lead back to the same pure rational system of religion…. If this is the case, then we shall be able to say that between reason and Scripture there is, not only compatibility but also unity, so that whoever follows the one (under the guidance of moral concepts) will not fail to come across the other as well (RBR, 6:12–13).
So, the primary intended effect of the absolute holiness of the moral law in Luther is to convince people of their inability to achieve righteousness on their own. However, the same cannot be said for Kant, who has kicked out any serious commitment to the historical savior from his pure rational religion.30 Given this maneuver, his understanding of the moral law naturally leads him down a different trajectory—a path of endless moral progress. However, in The End of All Things, he reveals his anguish over the implications of this view. Traditional Lutheran Christians might say that this is exactly the moment when Kant should have realized his mistake and taken seriously the necessity of the historical redeemer. However, what he opts for instead is to consider whether the good disposition might be sufficient to meet the loftiest moral demand, but this direction leads to all the issues we have seen in Section 3.Therefore the proper use and aim of the Law is to make guilty those who are smug and at peace, so that they may be terrified and despairing…. For the Law requires perfect obedience toward God, and it damns those who do not yield such obedience. Now it is certain that no one yields this obedience or even can; nevertheless, this is what God wants.
5. Divine Assistance Coming to the Rescue?
6. Conclusions
Funding
Institutional Review Board Statement
Informed Consent Statement
Data Availability Statement
Conflicts of Interest
1 | e.g., CPR, A797–819/B825–47; CPrR, 5:110–34; O, 8:136–42; CPJ, 5:442–59; RBR, 6:3–7; TP, 8:279–80n. I use the following abbreviations for citing Kant’s works:
Citations for Critique of Pure Reason follow the standard A/B pagination, where A denotes the first-edition page number and B the second-edition number. For other works of Kant, citations refer to the Akademie-Ausgabe volume and page. English translations of the following works are taken from the revised editions in the Cambridge Texts in the History of Philosophy series: CPrR, EAT, G, MM, MPT, O, RBR. Other English translations are from the Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant Series. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
2 | See also CPR A812–14/B840–42; CPrR, 5:4, 113–14, 129, 145–46; CPJ, 5:450–53. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
3 | e.g., CPR, A819/B847; CPrR, 5:129; CPJ, 5:481; RBR, 6:84, 99, 110, 152–54, 192; MM, 6:440, 443, 487; CF, 7:36, 64, 74; OP, 22:104, 117–22, 125–31. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
4 | I agree with the interpretation by John Hare (2000, pp. 463–68) that the passages in Kant that might first strike us as indicating his categorical opposition to a divine command theory in general turn out to target a particular kind of divine command theory. More specifically, Kant has in mind Christian August Crusius, who thinks we can discern what God wills without the practical use of reason, while also holding that whatever God wills just becomes a moral obligation for us, regardless of how it pertains to the goal set before us by reason. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
5 | Thus, belief in God is not a condition for morality’s applicability to us in Kant, as moral obligations are imposed on theists and non-theists alike, e.g., O, 8:139; CPrR, 5:125–29; CPJ, 5:450–51. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
6 | Arguably, Kant’s second Critique talk of our “consciousness” of the moral law as “a fact of reason” that just “forces itself upon us of itself” betrays his inability to explain why or how the practical use of reason really obligates us (CPrR, 5:31). So, divine command theorists might take this as a sign that Kant should have assigned to God’s command the role of turning the results of rational deliberations into moral obligations. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
7 | This position is based on Kant’s rejection of eudaimonism that equates virtue with happiness. It is only because these two are distinguishable ends in Kant—that morality as a practical enterprise is, at least in theory, not the same as prudence, the business of pursuing self-interested happiness—that combining these two ends harmoniously becomes a task to be accomplished. Of course, prudence is a legitimate part of our practical agency, and Kant (CPrR, 5:93) even allows that “it can… in certain respects be a duty to attend to one’s happiness”. But, in Kant, there is always lurking the possible scenario in which the two ends of virtue and happiness come to oppose each other, in which case it is our duty to prioritize the call of morality. For more on the place of self-interest in Kant’s practical philosophy, see (Tönissen 2024). | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
8 | e.g., MPT, 8:257–58; RBR, 6:140–41n. This point is also emphasized in (Beiser 2006, pp. 596–98). Some Kant readers argue that his later understanding of the highest good is no longer concerned with the proportionality between happiness and moral virtue; for instance, see (Reath 1988). However, I interpret this proportionality as an abiding feature of his concept of the highest good, as there are hints in his later texts—including MM, 6:480–82; OP, 21:13, 22:125—suggesting that he sees this correspondence as a desirable state of affairs. A similar interpretation is advanced in (Pasternack 2017). | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
9 | In Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, a maxim is defined as “the subjective principle of willing” contrasted with “the objective principle [of] the practical law” (G, 4:400n). The former is a principle adopted by an individual subject, which may or may not align with the objective moral law. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
10 | Admittedly, Kant, especially in his later texts, does not always seem comfortable describing God as a being that exists independently of human reason. This is particularly pronounced toward the end of The Metaphysics of Morals, where he writes the following: “the formal aspect of all religion… belongs to philosophic morals, since this definition expresses only the relation of reason to the idea of God which reason makes for itself; and this does not yet make a duty of religion into a duty to (erga) God, as a being existing outside our idea, since we still abstract from his existence” (MM, 6:487). See also OP, 21:17, 20, 30, 22:116, 120, 125, 129. However, in his earlier theology based on the moral argument, finding a way to justify affirming divine existence is very much Kant’s concern (e.g., CPrR, 5:124–34; O, 8:137–42), and my analysis and assessment will be focused on this earlier Kant, as my aim is to point out the issues in this moral-religious project. In fact, I think these issues help explain why we see this changed attitude in the later Kant, although I will not argue for this explicitly in this paper. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
11 | e.g., CPR, A810–11/B838–39; CPrR, 5:125. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
12 | See also CPR, B375; G, 4:405, 408–10; CPrR, 5:31–33, 87, 128. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
13 | This shift in Kant’s eschatology has been recognized in many readings, including (Perovich 1991, pp. 165–71; von der Ruhr 2000, pp. 217–30; Ameriks 2019, pp. 78–81). | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
14 | In this vein, Kant (RBR, 6:45) writes in the Religion that “in spite of that fall, the command that we ought to become better human beings still resounds unabated in our souls; consequently, we must also be capable of it, even if what we can do is of itself insufficient and, by virtue of it, we only make ourselves receptive to a higher assistance inscrutable to us”. Thus, despite adopting the evil disposition initially, it must be the case that humans remain capable of producing some positive moral value on their own. In Section 5, I discuss Kant’s treatment of divine assistance more extensively. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
15 | Kant (RBR, 6:44–45) admits the inability to offer a satisfying account of this possibility in the following Religion passage: “how is it possible that a naturally evil human being should make himself into a good human being surpasses every concept of ours. For how can an evil tree bear good fruit?” | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
16 | This should be clear from note 9. See also the following line in the Religion: “granted that some supernatural cooperation is also needed to his becoming good or better, …the human being must nonetheless make himself antecedently worthy of receiving it” (RBR, 6:44). | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
17 | According to Kant, this severity of our moral judgment does not change even if we treat God’s judgment as merely the verdict of conscience. This is because “reason is incorruptible just because it is free”, which means that it “must pass judgment on him (the human being) precisely as reason” (RBR, 6:70n). So we cannot resort to the move of interpreting religious concepts as reflexive descriptions of practical self-consciousness. This does nothing to close the infinite gap between the moral ideal and our actual practice, which seems to call for a life of endless strivings. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
18 | These questions are supported by the analysis of Kant’s practical ethics in (Hare 1996), which holds that the gap between the moral requirement and our capacity becomes particularly pronounced in Kant. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
19 | This point is supported by CPrR, 5:123, 160–61; RBR, 6:23n, 47, 68. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
20 | See also RBR, 6:48, 61, 71, 173–74, 183, 190n, 191. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
21 | The shift in how our moral vocation is understood in these two different works is also noted in (Pasternack 2014, pp. 141–48), where a more positive assessment of Kant’s revision is advanced. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
22 | In the first Critique, Kant (CPR, B3) calls a cognition pure when “nothing empirical is intermixed”. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
23 | While Pietists were heavily critical of the Lutheran orthodoxy of their time for being mired in overly complex and lifeless formalisms, their attitude toward the founder of this tradition was different given that their intention was to return to his focus on living and personal faith. Thus, Pietists never decisively departed from Luther’s core convictions such as the imputation of Jesus’ righteousness to believers and the worthlessness of human works in terms of salvation, even though they were seriously worried about the potential practical effects of these doctrines. For more on Pietists’ complex and evolving attitudes toward the enlightenment as well as Lutheran orthodoxy, see (Gawthrop 1993). | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
24 | A more comprehensive account of the departures from the traditional Lutheran soteriology in these strands is found in (McGrath 2020, pp. 268–75, 348–52). | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
25 | This religious background of Kant is covered in more detail in (Reardon 1988, pp. 1–26). | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
26 | This view is also advanced in (Hare 1996, pp. 7–68). | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
27 | Kant details his opposition to these ways of understanding salvation in RBR, 6:116–21, 180–82. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
28 | Arguably, Augustine’s original doctrine had gone through notable modifications by the time of Kant. Even in Luther, an Augustinian friar who does describe the original sin as inherited, humans do not just take on the sinfulness of Adam through the process of procreation. Rather, as Ľubomír Batka (2014, p. 245) explains, “even if a person was passive in the moment of conception and peccatum radicale was something foreign, it became a sin that belonged to his person… each person has his own original sin”. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
29 | The closest biblical verse is Matt. 5:48, which is part of the Sermon on the Mount. Basically the same idea is also expressed in Lev. 19:2 and 1 Pet. 1:15–16. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
30 | Given this context, it is not surprising that Kant’s moral–religious project has often led to the comment that it is Pelagian in its character, e.g., (Barth 1959, pp. 185–88; Pasternack 2020, pp. 112–14). For an attempt at rebutting this characterization, see (Mariña 1997; Palmquist 2019, pp. 288–89). | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
31 | e.g., RBR, 6:45, 52–53, 174, 191. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
32 | See also TP, 6:362n. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
33 | See also RBR, 6:120. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
34 | What complicates this picture is Kant’s willingness to grant the possibility of divine concurrence with our exercise of freedom, even though he refuses to explain how this is possible. This agnostic openness to divine assistance, betraying his willingness to tolerate the tension between human freedom and divine creative causality, is best captured in the following comment in Kant’s philosophy of religion lecture notes published by Karl Pölitz: “as regards a concursum moralem or God’s free cooperation in the free actions of human beings, such a thing cannot be comprehended in the nature of freedom, but at the same time it cannot be regarded as impossible…. It is indeed possible that God, in order to make rational creatures use their freedom in a manner agreeable to his highest will, could cooperate as a concausa” (LR, 28:1110). I would argue that this view of divine concurrence aligns better with the second Critique moral vision; what we see in his later texts is not so much God’s activity of supplementing our continuous strivings but more decisive determination of our moral status. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
35 | As John Silber (1960, p. cxxxi) aptly puts it, in Kant, “even God cannot help the guilty individual without violating the moral law”. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
36 | At this point, some readers interpret Kant as capable of and even actually, albeit implicitly, turning to God’s forgiveness of sin to deal with this question in the Religion, e.g., (Stevenson 2014, pp. 132–36; Wood 2020, pp. 140–42). However, given the nearly complete absence of this term in the text, this interpretation seems difficult to maintain. So I agree with the following reading by Michel Despland (1973, p. 202): “the notion of forgiveness is kept at arm’s length…. The divine judge in a crunch will always be just rather than good”. Also crucial is the following passage in Georg Ludwig Collins’ lecture notes of Kant (LEC, 27:330–31): “because men are exceedingly frail in all acts of morality, … they are quite unable to confront a holy and just judge, who cannot forgive evil-doing simpliciter. The question is, can we, by our vehement begging and beseeching, hope for and obtain through God’s goodness the forgiveness of all our sins? No, we cannot without contradiction conceive of a kindly judge; as ruler he may well be kindly, but a judge must be just. For if God could forgive all evil-doing, He could also make it permissible and if He can grant it impunity, it rests also on His will to make it permitted; in that case, however, the moral laws would be an arbitrary matter, though in fact they are not arbitrary, but just as necessary and eternal as God…. Hence we cannot hope that because of our begging and beseeching God will forgive us everything, for in that case it would be a matter, not of well-doing, but of begging and beseeching”. Later in the lecture, Kant moderates this stark position in the following way: “the goodness of God consists, rather, in the aids whereby He can make up for the deficiencies of our natural frailty…. If, for our part, we do everything we can, we may hope for a supplementation, such that we may stand before God’s justice and be found adequate to the holy laws. How God brings about this supplementation, and what sort of means He employs for it, we know not, nor do we have any need to know” (LEC, 27:331). These two passages incline me to think that forgiveness should not be treated as the heart of divine assistance that fills the gap between the moral ideal and our actual practice. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
37 | This feature of the Religion is particularly interesting because Kant (RBR, 6:174) also claims that “the persuasion that we can distinguish the effects of grace from those of nature (virtue)… is enthusiasm”. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
38 | This interpretation is also advanced in (Adams 2018, pp. xvi–xvii). | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
39 | For a more positive assessment of Kant’s situation here, see (Mariña 2017). | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
40 | This is why Andrew Chignell (2014, p. 110) wonders whether Kant ends up “ascrib[ing] to God an odd sort of overestimation or self-deception” in the Religion. It is also telling that Stephen Palmquist (2019, p. 459), another generally sympathetic reader of Kant, makes the following admission: “interpreters who expect Kant to provide incontrovertible proofs to dispel these difficulties once and for all are bound to be highly dissatisfied with [his] ‘solution’. If instead we understand Kant’s purpose here as being not to provide anything like a proof, but only to demonstrate the possibility of a rationally acceptable solution, then his efforts deserve to be evaluated more positively”. My stance is that, while this bare possibility may not be ruled out, it remains rather puzzling how God could be satisfied with our state of moral imperfection, given the holiness Kant ascribes to God. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
41 | Kant’s inability to make himself rely on the historical savior is vividly captured in the following Religion passage: “it is totally inconceivable… how a rational human being who knows himself to deserve punishment could seriously believe that he only has to believe the news of a satisfaction having been rendered for him, and (as the jurists say) accept it utiliter in order to regard his guilt as done away with, indeed, to such an extent (to its very roots) that a good life conduct too, would be for the future the unavoidable consequence of his faith and his acceptance of the proffered kindness. No thoughtful person can bring himself to this faith, however much self-love often transforms into a hope the mere wish for a good, for which one does nothing or can do nothing, as though the object were to come on its own, lured by the mere yearning for it. One cannot think any such thing possible unless a human being considers this faith itself as heavenly instilled in him, as something, therefore, for which he has no need to give his reason a further accounting” (RBR, 6:116–17). | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
42 | This is why Stephen Palmquist (2016, p. 183) makes the following comment: “Kant reminds us that our very existence (Dasein) as embodied beings (beings ‘in time,’ in der Zeit) make moral failures inevitable—a fact that would be rationally intolerable if we were not able to conceive of how God can overlook that failure”. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
43 | The relevant New Testament verses are Matt. 3:17, 17:5; Mark 1:11; Luke 3:22. | ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
44 | This suggestion does not address the question of how positive moral contributions that merit divine assistance can emerge from fundamentally evil roots of humanity, which was briefly noted in Section 3. Here, I think the move should be to conceptualize humans as starting with a capacity to produce something at least morally passable, rather than being utterly incapable of producing anything of value. This move would take the position I am proposing further away from Luther and, more fundamentally, Augustine. |
References
- Adams, Robert Merrihew. 1987. Moral Arguments for Theistic Belief. In “The Virtue of Faith” and Other Essays in Philosophical Theology. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 144–63. [Google Scholar]
- Adams, Robert Merrihew. 2018. Introduction to Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason: And Other Writings, by Immanuel Kant. Edited and Translated by Allen W. Wood and George di Giovanni, Revised by Robert Merrihew Adams. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. vii–xxx. [Google Scholar]
- Ameriks, Karl. 2019. Kantian Subjects: Critical Philosophy and Late Modernity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Barth, Karl. 1959. Protestant Thought: From Rousseau to Ritschl. Translated by Brian Cozens. New York: Harper & Brothers. [Google Scholar]
- Batka, Ľubomír. 2014. Luther’s Teaching on Sin and Evil. In The Oxford Handbook of Martin Luther’s Theology. Edited by Robert Kolb, Irene Dingel and Ľubomír Batka. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 233–51. [Google Scholar]
- Beiser, Frederick C. 2006. Moral Faith and the Highest Good. In The Cambridge Companion to Kant and Modern Philosophy. Edited by Paul Guyer. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 588–629. [Google Scholar]
- Chignell, Andrew. 2014. Rational Hope, Possibility, and Divine Action. In Kant’s “Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason”: A Critical Guide. Edited by Gordon E. Michalson. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 98–117. [Google Scholar]
- Despland, Michel. 1973. Kant on History and Religion: With a Translation of Kant’s “On the Failure of All Attempted Philosophical Theodicies”. Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Gawthrop, Richard L. 1993. Pietism and the Making of Eighteenth-Century Prussia. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hare, John E. 1996. The Moral Gap: Kantian Ethics, Human Limits, and God’s Assistance. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hare, John E. 2000. Kant on recognizing our duties as God’s commands. Faith and Philosophy 17: 459–78. [Google Scholar]
- Kant. 1993. Opus postumum. Edited by Eckart Förster. Translated by Michael Rosen. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kant. 1996a. On the Common Saying: That May Be Correct in Theory, but It Is of No Use in Practice. In Practical Philosophy. Translated and Edited by Mary J. Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 273–309. [Google Scholar]
- Kant. 1996b. Religion and Rational Theology. Translated and Edited by Allen W. Wood, and George di Giovanni. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kant. 1997. Moral Philosophy: Collins’s Lecture Notes. In Lectures on Ethics. Edited by Peter Heath and J. B. Schneewind. Translated by Peter Heath. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 37–222. [Google Scholar]
- Kant. 1998. Critique of Pure Reason. Translated and Edited by Paul Guyer, and Allen W. Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kant. 2000. Critique of the Power of Judgment. Edited by Paul Guyer. Translated by Paul Guyer, and Eric Matthews. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kant. 2012. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, rev. ed. Translated and Edited by Mary Gregor, and Jens Timmermann. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kant. 2015. Critique of Practical Reason, rev. ed. Translated and Edited by Mary Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kant. 2017. The Metaphysics of Morals, rev. ed. Edited by Lara Denis. Translated by Mary Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Kant. 2018. Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason: And Other Writings, rev. ed. Translated and Edited by Allen Wood, and George di Giovanni. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Luther, Martin. 1957. The Bondage of the Will. Translated by James Innell Packer, and Olaf Raymond Johnston. Grand Rapids: Fleming H. Revell. [Google Scholar]
- Luther, Martin. 1963. Luther’s Works. Edited by Jaroslav Pelikan and Walter A. Hansen. St. Louis: Concordia, vol. 26, Lectures on Galatians 1535: Chapters 1–4. [Google Scholar]
- Luther, Martin. 2008. The Freedom of a Christian, Luther Study ed. Translated by Mark D. Tranvik. Minneapolis: Fortress Press. [Google Scholar]
- Luther, Martin. 2012. Two Kinds of Righteousness. In Martin Luther’s Basic Theological Writings, 3rd ed. Edited by William R. Russell. Minneapolis: Fortress Press, pp. 119–25. [Google Scholar]
- Mariña, Jacqueline. 1997. Kant on Grace: A Reply to His Critics. Religious Studies 33: 379–400. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mariña, Jacqueline. 2017. Kant’s Robust Theory of Grace. Con-Textos Kantianos 6: 302–20. [Google Scholar]
- McGrath, Alister E. 2020. Iustitia Dei: A History of the Christian Doctrine of Justification, 4th ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Michalson, Gordon E., Jr. 1990. Fallen Freedom: Kant on Radical Evil and Moral Regeneration. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Palmquist, Stephen. 2010. Kant’s Ethics of Grace: Perspectival Solutions to the Moral Difficulties with Divine Assistance. The Journal of Religion 90: 530–53. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Palmquist, Stephen. 2016. Comprehensive Commentary on Kant’s “Religion within the Bounds of Bare Reason". Malden: Wiley Blackwell. [Google Scholar]
- Palmquist, Stephen. 2019. Kant’s Critical Religion: Volume Two of Kant’s System of Perspectives. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Pasternack, Lawrence. 2014. Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Kant on “Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason”: An Interpretation and Defense. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Pasternack, Lawrence. 2017. Restoring Kant’s Conception of the Highest Good. Journal of the History of Philosophy 55: 435–68. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Pasternack, Lawrence. 2020. On the Alleged Augustinianism in Kant’s Religion. Kantian Review 25: 103–24. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Perovich, Anthony N., Jr. 1991. “For Reason… Also Has Its Mysteries”: Immortality, Religion, and “The End of All Things”. In Kant’s Philosophy of Religion Reconsidered. Edited by Philip J. Rossi and Michael Wreen. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, pp. 165–80. [Google Scholar]
- Reardon, Bernard M. G. 1988. Kant as Philosophical Theologian. London: Macmillan Press. [Google Scholar]
- Reath, Andrews. 1988. Two Conceptions of the Highest Good in Kant. Journal of the History of Philosophy 26: 593–619. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Silber, John R. 1960. The Ethical Significance of Kant’s Religion. In Religion within the Limits of Reason Alone. Written by Immanuel Kant. Translated by Theodore M. Greene, and Hoyt H. Hudson. New York: Harper & Row, pp. lxxix–cxxxiv. [Google Scholar]
- Stevenson, Leslie. 2014. Kant on Grace. In Kant’s “Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason”: A Critical Guide. Edited by Gordon E. Michalson. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 118–36. [Google Scholar]
- Sussman, David. 2005. Kantian Forgiveness. Kant-Studien 96: 85–107. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tönissen, Bas. 2024. Do Good People Love Themselves? On Rational Self-Love in Kant. Kant-Studien 115: 433–53. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Von der Ruhr, Mario. 2000. Kant and Kierkegaard on Eternal Life—A Reply. In Kant and Kierkegaard on Religion. Edited by D. Z. Phillips and Timothy Tessin. New York: St. Martin’s Press, pp. 207–35. [Google Scholar]
- Wood, Allen W. 1970. Kant’s Moral Religion. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Wood, Allen W. 2020. Kant and Religion. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content. |
© 2025 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Woo, J. Why Kant’s Moral–Religious Project Was Bound to Unravel. Religions 2025, 16, 235. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16020235
Woo J. Why Kant’s Moral–Religious Project Was Bound to Unravel. Religions. 2025; 16(2):235. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16020235
Chicago/Turabian StyleWoo, Jaeha. 2025. "Why Kant’s Moral–Religious Project Was Bound to Unravel" Religions 16, no. 2: 235. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16020235
APA StyleWoo, J. (2025). Why Kant’s Moral–Religious Project Was Bound to Unravel. Religions, 16(2), 235. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel16020235